Virtual Particles: Are Coulomb Forces Mediated by Photons?

In summary, virtual particles are intermediate photons in interactions that cannot be directly observed. They consist of u and t channel photons in low order perturbation theory and are involved in electron-electron scattering processes. The electrostatic coulomb force is mediated by virtual photons, which can have any frequency and are off-shell, meaning they do not obey the usual dispersion relation of real photons. This distinction between real and virtual photons is not necessary for physical particles and is primarily used as a visualization tool in perturbation theory.
  • #1
freeman
10
0
According to what I have read, virtual particles are those which are intermediate photons in interactions, which cannot be directly observed. If my understanding is correct that would mean that they consist of (in low order perturbation theory), (among other things) u and t channel photons. But electron electron scattering processes are described by such diagrams. That leads me to believe that all electrostatic coulomb force is mediated by virtual photons. Am i therefore to conclude that coulomb force over observable distance is mediated by photons of sufficiently low frequency so as to be unobservabe?

Help would be super.

Regards,
Gordon.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
A virtual photon is an internal photon line, i.e. a propogator.

One measures the presence of a Coloumb potential by the results of the interaction between the source and some charged body. The Coloumb force is the result of a virtual interaction. Two positively charged particles repel by exchanging a virtual photon. I can't trick the system and jump between the two of them and exclaim "hoozah there's a real photon there, look I just detected it", because you'd have just detected it by interacting with the source, assuming you were charged and if you weren't you wouldn't interact with it (the coupling between you and the EM force would be zero, you'd just be a free field).

Non-virtual photons are external photon lines in Feynman diagrams, and are just radiated or absorbed photons.

I'm probably not reading your post right, but are you saying that virtual photons only occur at low orders in perturbation theory? If so, contributions from virtual interactions are less prevalent in the low orders of perturbation theory than in the higher orders.
 
Last edited:
  • #3
Hi freeman,

I just wanted to add to Perturbation's good answer and toss in some other interesting tidbits. It is important to realize that while one often draws a distinction between real and virtual photons, even so called real photons are detected by being absorbed by an atom or a crystal or whatever. That means even real photons are internal lines in some larger system that includes the atoms or whatever is doing the detection. So you can think of real photons as photons that are close to being on the mass shell, but you know that even real photons can't actually have definite energy. If they did have definite energy then they would be an energy eigenstate and hence could never disappear.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
Hello,

Thanks for the help.

Just to clarify, what you have said is that all photons, are intermediate states between charged particles and therefore the distinction between real and virtual particles is based on their proximity to the mass shell. All photons real and virtual can be detected by charged objects.

On the basis of this it seems like a very ad hoc distinction to me. Is it really necessary, or is it just there to explain away the temporary violation of conservation of energy that is often given as a justification in more hand wavy explanations?

Many thanks,
Gordon.
 
  • #5
Perturbation said:
I'm probably not reading your post right, but are you saying that virtual photons only occur at low orders in perturbation theory? If so, contributions from virtual interactions are less prevalent in the low orders of perturbation theory than in the higher orders.

I didn't mean to say that, it's just that I'm only thinking in terms of lowest order diagrams, which I would hope are the leading order in behaviour anyway.

Regards,
Gordon.
 
  • #6
freeman said:
According to what I have read, virtual particles are those which are intermediate photons in interactions, which cannot be directly observed. If my understanding is correct that would mean that they consist of (in low order perturbation theory), (among other things) u and t channel photons. But electron electron scattering processes are described by such diagrams. That leads me to believe that all electrostatic coulomb force is mediated by virtual photons. Am i therefore to conclude that coulomb force over observable distance is mediated by photons of sufficiently low frequency so as to be unobservabe?

Help would be super.

Regards,
Gordon.

Yes, roughly speaking you may think of the photons exchanged in th eu and t channels, at lowest order of perturbation theory (I say roughly because virtual photons are just a gimmick to visualize things...one should reallythink of excitations of the field and a nonperturbative treatment would not involve an expansion in exchanges of virtual photons. So I see them more as a trick related to PT than something physical).

In any case, you should not think of virtual photons as being photons of small "undetectable" frequencies...There is no such interpretation. A virtual photon may have any frequency. The point is rather that virtual photons are off-shell, i.e. they don't obey the usual dispersion relation associated with real photons (in other words, the square of their four-momentum is not zero, as one expects for a massless particle).
 
  • #7
nrqed said:
In any case, you should not think of virtual photons as being photons of small "undetectable" frequencies...There is no such interpretation. A virtual photon may have any frequency. The point is rather that virtual photons are off-shell, i.e. they don't obey the usual dispersion relation associated with real photons (in other words, the square of their four-momentum is not zero, as one expects for a massless particle).

Thanks.

I don't really understand the on/off-shell business. I understand what it means,

[tex]p^{\mu}p_{\mu}=m^2[/tex]

but where does that condition come from, and why doesn't it apply to intermediate particles.

Many thanks,
Gordon.
 
  • #8
freeman said:
Thanks.

I don't really understand the on/off-shell business. I understand what it means,

[tex]p^{\mu}p_{\mu}=m^2[/tex]

but where does that condition come from, and why doesn't it apply to intermediate particles.

Many thanks,
Gordon.

A physical particle is said to be on mass-shell when the norm of its four momentum is that of the square of its observable mass. Off or near mass-shell is when [itex]p^2[/itex] doesn't equal or is almost the square of the rest mass.

Propogators do not generally correspond to physical particles, that's usually the job of external lines, they are merely the transition amplitudes between fixed field configurations, the fixed config's being the end points in space-time, this propogation is not confined merely to those configurations with [itex]p^2=m^2[/itex]. The form of a two point function for a vector gauge boson is of the form

[tex]\int\frac{dq^4}{(2\pi )^4}\frac{i\delta^{ab}g_{\mu\nu}}{q^2}[/tex] (Feynman gauge)

(a and b label the gauge group indices and [itex]\mu,\nu[/itex] the space-time indices.)

Where q is the four-momentum of the gauge boson. Obviously if the norm of q were identically zero this amplitude would be rather poorly defined and totally useless. If you work out propogation amplitudes with just on-shell particles one gets violations of causality, which is one of the reasons physics made the progression from relativistic quantum mechanics to quantum field theory.

Similarly with fermions

[tex]\int\frac{dq^4}{(2\pi )^4}\frac{i}{\gamma^{\mu}q_{\mu}-m}[/tex]

This whole idea of being "on/near mass-shell" is important in LSZ scattering theory, where isolated poles or branch cuts in amplitudes correspond to physical particle states.

Thanks for adding that bit, Physics Monkey, I was going to put it, but I thought I'd leave it implicit, don't know why.
 
Last edited:
  • #9
Perturbation said:
If you work out propogation amplitudes with just on-shell particles one gets violations of causality, which is one of the reason physics made the progression from relativistic quantum mechanics to quantum field theory.
.

I know that this is true but it's one of those things that I keep hearing about and never see explicitly worked out. Do you have a reference (online or not) where this is explicitly worked out? I would find this instructive.
 
  • #10
Perturbation said:
Propogators do not generally correspond to physical particles, that's usually the job of external lines, they are merely the transition amplitudes between fixed field configurations, the fixed config's being the end points in space-time, this propogation is not confined merely to those configurations with [tex]p^2=m^2[/tex]

Thanks for your help all.

I suppose my problem now boils down to this. In Feynman diagrams we have internal lines and external lines. We call external lines real particles with on shell momentum, and internal lines virtual particles with no such on-shell constraint. Now if we have a one vertex diagram in QED, we have one external photon. This has definite on-shell momentum. However, if we were to detect this particle we could only do so by observing its scattering from a charged particle, in which case the whole process can be described by a two vertex diagram that is essentially electron electron scattering. Now the photon is an intermediate line. What happens now? What is going on here? I think there is something fundamental I am missing.

Regards,
Gordon.
 
  • #11
freeman said:
Thanks for your help all.

I suppose my problem now boils down to this. In Feynman diagrams we have internal lines and external lines. We call external lines real particles with on shell momentum, and internal lines virtual particles with no such on-shell constraint. Now if we have a one vertex diagram in QED, we have one external photon. This has definite on-shell momentum. However, if we were to detect this particle we could only do so by observing its scattering from a charged particle, in which case the whole process can be described by a two vertex diagram that is essentially electron electron scattering. Now the photon is an intermediate line. What happens now? What is going on here? I think there is something fundamental I am missing.

Regards,
Gordon.

This is exactly the issue that PhysicsMonkey was discussing in post number 3.
 
  • #12
freeman said:
Thanks for your help all.

I suppose my problem now boils down to this. In Feynman diagrams we have internal lines and external lines. We call external lines real particles with on shell momentum, and internal lines virtual particles with no such on-shell constraint. Now if we have a one vertex diagram in QED, we have one external photon. This has definite on-shell momentum. However, if we were to detect this particle we could only do so by observing its scattering from a charged particle, in which case the whole process can be described by a two vertex diagram that is essentially electron electron scattering. Now the photon is an intermediate line. What happens now? What is going on here? I think there is something fundamental I am missing.

Regards,
Gordon.

I think that the Feynman diagram in this case would have the real photon coming in as one external line and the outgoing scattered photon as another, with similar lines for the charged particle. The interaction is represented by an undirected line (frequently shown as wavy) indicating mediation by virtual states. Of course these lines, and the two vertices, are used to construct the integral for the amplitude.The essential thing for an external line in the momentum representation is that there be a real momentum, and this the photon of the example has, both before and after scattering. But I live for correction!:biggrin:
 
  • #13
nrqed said:
I know that this is true but it's one of those things that I keep hearing about and never see explicitly worked out. Do you have a reference (online or not) where this is explicitly worked out? I would find this instructive.

Work out the usual propogation amplitude from quantum mechanics for propogation from one position eigenstate to another in a time t, i.e.

[tex]\langle \vec{x}|e^{-iHt}|\vec{x}_0\rangle[/tex]

With [itex]H=E=\sqrt{|\vec{p}|^2+m^2}[/itex] and with [itex]\vec{x}-\vec{x}_0\neq 0[/itex], the above amplitude should vanish, otherwise a quantum particle could traverse a space-like distance in an arbitrary time t, but it doesn't, though it is quite small. QFT resolves this problem by making matter an operator valued distribution, and now the problem of causality becomes getting two operators at space-like separation to commute, which they do with the introduction of antiparticles.

If you want me to show you a quick run down of showing it, give me a shout.

Incidently, does anyone know if there's a latex string for the Feynman slash notation?
 
Last edited:
  • #14
Perturbation said:
.. QFT resolves this problem by making matter an operator valued distribution, and now the problem of causality becomes getting two operators at space-like separation to commute, which they do with the introduction of antiparticles...
So from above statement, assume the matter operator is the deuteron [NP], then what is the mathematics to show how this would commute with introduction of the antiparticle, anti-helium-3 [P^N^P^], where P = matter proton, P^ antimatter proton, N = matter neutron, N^ = antimatter neutron ?
 
  • #15
Perturbation said:
Work out the usual propogation amplitude from quantum mechanics for propogation from one position eigenstate to another in a time t, i.e.

[tex]\langle \vec{x}|e^{iHt}|\vec{x}_0\rangle[/tex]

With [itex]H=E=\sqrt{|\vec{p}|^2+m^2}[/itex] and with [itex]\vec{x}-\vec{x}_0\neq 0[/itex], the above amplitude should vanish, otherwise a quantum particle could traverse a space-like distance in an arbitrary time t, but it doesn't, though it is quite small. QFT resolves this problem by making matter an operator valued distribution, and now the problem of causality becomes getting two operators at space-like separation to commute, which they do with the introduction of antiparticles.

If you want me to show you a quick run down of showing it, give me a shout.

Incidently, does anyone know if there's a latex string for the Feynman slash notation?
Yes I would like to see how you would present this. I would appreciate it. This is one of those physics things that I always took for granted in order to move on and do QFT but now it is bothering me. It is also realted to what one really means by [itex] \phi(x) [/itex] applied on the vacuum. One would expect that to check causality, one would create a particle at position x, destroy a particle at position y and verify that the overlap between the two states vanishes for spacelike intervals. But it does not (this expression is simply the propagator D(x,y)).

At this point, people mumble something about ''well, this is not what we should really look at, we should really look at whether a measurement at x may affect a measurement at y and this is given by the *commutator* between the two fields, and *this* vanishes for spacelike intervals'' (that's the ''derivation'' of P&S). I have to admit that I don't follow this argument (and I wonder how an EPR situation would be treated in QFT! This is one annoying thing about QFT...It is more general than NR quantum mechanics and yet, almost none of the applications of NQRM is revisited with QFT. Normally when teaching a new technique, the logical thing to do is to show how it reproduces previous techniques in some limits...This is what everyine does in introducing SR and GR (relating the results to Newtonian and Galilean expressions) but this not done very much when introducing QM (i.e. showing the connection with classical physics) and not at all with QFT (showing how to reproduce NRQM).

I'd like to see your approach.

Bets regards

Patrick
 
  • #16
In basic QM, operators commute at space-like separation. So any particle state shouldn't be able to affect another if the two are space-like separated, i.e. they commute. The two terms in the commutator can be interpreted as the propogation of two particles simultaneously, one particle from x to y and an antiparticle from y to x.

[tex]\left[\phi (x), \phi (y)\right]=\langle 0|\left[\phi (x), \phi (y)\right]|0\rangle =\langle 0|\phi (x)\phi (y) |0\rangle-\langle 0|\phi (y)\phi (x) |0\rangle[/tex]

The two amplitudes in the above then cancel if [itex](x-y)^2<0[/itex].

Relativistic QM wise,

[tex]\langle \vec{x}|e^{iHt}|\vec{x_0}\rangle[/tex]
[tex]=\langle \vec{x}|e^{-it\sqrt{|\vec{p}|^2+m^2}}|\vec{x}_0\rangle[/tex]
[tex]=\int\frac{d^3p}{(2\pi )^3}e^{-it\sqrt{|\vec{p}|^2+m^2}}e^{i\vec{p}\cdot(\vec{x}-\vec{x}_0)}[/tex]

You can do stationary phase on this and then take [itex]x^2>>t^2[/itex], which is well outside the light-cone, and get a kind of order of magnitude guesstimate for the integrand. Or you can switch to spherical coordinates in momentum space and get

[tex]\frac{1}{2\pi^2|\vec{x}-\vec{x}_0|}\int^{\infty}_0 p\sin (p|\vec{x}-\vec{x}_0|)e^{-it\sqrt{p^2+m^2}}dp[/tex]

and use Bessel functions. However, I'm not very adept with Bessel functions. Being self taught I skipped over them as I've never found differential equations particularly interesting. I'll probably go over series solutions and what not later and have a crack at it.
 
Last edited:
  • #17
Perturbation said:
In basic QM, operators commute at space-like separation. So any particle state shouldn't be able to affect another if the two are space-like separated, i.e. they commute. ¸

you meant QM or QFT here??

I think that I am a bit confused by the term ''affect''. How would that be defined, precisely? (for example, how would EPR fit in this terminology...)

And what type of measurement are we talnking about here? Why must one introduce commutators to discuss measurements. what about the question ''if a particle is detected at this point over here at time t_0, what is the probability that it will be observed at that point over there at time t''...what would that calculation look like and why can't we focus on this?

Thanks for your feedback
 
  • #18
nrqed said:
you meant QM or QFT here??

I think that I am a bit confused by the term ''affect''. How would that be defined, precisely? (for example, how would EPR fit in this terminology...)

And what type of measurement are we talnking about here? Why must one introduce commutators to discuss measurements. what about the question ''if a particle is detected at this point over here at time t_0, what is the probability that it will be observed at that point over there at time t''...what would that calculation look like and why can't we focus on this?

Thanks for your feedback

QM has space-like operators commuting, but it would extend into QFT, since we're also bothered about operators here.

What I mean is that some measurement made at some point x cannot interfere, convolute etc. a measurement made at some point y space-like separated from x. I.e. if I find that some measurement performed at x gives an observable A, then the same procedure performed at y to give an observable B is not affected at all by that made at x if the two are space-like separated. Hence, the operator giving observable A at x commutes with that giving B at y. A simple such attempt at a "measurement" would be of [itex]\phi[/itex]. Any proper observables will be constructed from [itex]\phi[/itex] and would then have to commute at space-like separation if the field does. Since causality is really about information, what we're actually bothered about is observation, not particle propogation.

The question "if a particle is detected at this point over here at time t_0, what is the probability that it will be observed at that point over there at time t" is just particle propogation. You take states at x and y, compute their inner product and square the modulus. Observation and measurement is concerned with physical observables, i.e. operators and their eigenvalues.

Or at least that's how I understand it. Maybe someone more qualified could better me.
 
Last edited:
  • #19
Perturbation said:
QM has space-like operators commuting, but it would extend into QFT, since we're also bothered about operators here.

What I mean is that some measurement made at some point x cannot interfere, convolute etc. a measurement made at some point y space-like separated from x. I.e. if I find that some measurement performed at x gives an observable A, then the same procedure performed at y to give an observable B is not affected at all by that made at x if the two are space-like separated. Hence, the operator giving observable A at x commutes with that giving B at y. A simple such attempt at a "measurement" would be of [itex]\phi[/itex]. Any proper observables will be constructed from [itex]\phi[/itex] and would then have to commute at space-like separation if the field does. Since causality is really about information, what we're actually bothered about is observation, not particle propogation.

Or at least that's how I understand it. Maybe someone more qualified could better me.
It makes much sense and I do appreciate your point of view (I am not trying to be difficult, I am just using this thread to think aloud and get some feedback).

I see what you are saying. Measuring something at x and at y in one order or the other should not make any difference for spacelike separations. I would like to understand better the connection between applying the field operator on the vacuum and the process of measurement. What is the connection between the two?

And on ething that bothers me is why th approach is so different than in NRQM. There, we show that there is violation of SR by looking at the probability of observing a particle at (x,t_0) and then at (y,t_0). Why does one then change completely the approach in QFT...

But the key point is probably: what does one really mean by the expectation value of phi(x) phi(y) between vacuum states...In words, what does this quantity represent?

Thanks for your input!
 
  • #20
Perturbation said:
QM has space-like operators commuting, but it would extend into QFT, since we're also bothered about operators here.

What I mean is that some measurement made at some point x cannot interfere, convolute etc. a measurement made at some point y space-like separated from x. I.e. if I find that some measurement performed at x gives an observable A, then the same procedure performed at y to give an observable B is not affected at all by that made at x if the two are space-like separated. Hence, the operator giving observable A at x commutes with that giving B at y. A simple such attempt at a "measurement" would be of [itex]\phi[/itex]. Any proper observables will be constructed from [itex]\phi[/itex] and would then have to commute at space-like separation if the field does. Since causality is really about information, what we're actually bothered about is observation, not particle propogation.

But if a particle can propagate faster than light then causality is surely violated. It seems to me that proving that matter cannot propagate faster than light should be easier than proving that no information can...And yet this issue seems completely avoided. Worse yet, if one sees the expectation value of two fields at two different spacetime points to mean what it seems to mean, particles *would* have a nonzero probability of propagating faster than light. So I don't know what the expectation value of two fields mean...
 
  • #21
I'm trying to think this one through as well, I don't seem to have given the thought that it is due.

I see what you are saying. Measuring something at x and at y in one order or the other should not make any difference for spacelike separations. I would like to understand better the connection between applying the field operator on the vacuum and the process of measurement. What is the connection between the two?

But the key point is probably: what does one really mean by the expectation value of phi(x) phi(y) between vacuum states...In words, what does this quantity represent?

Measurements correspond to eigenvalues of Hermitian operators. Since we're dealing with a theory that is the quantum analogue of lagrangian field theory, any observable can be constructed from the fields because of Noether's theorem, which will relate our observables to symmetry currents. So if we want our measurements to be commutative over space-like intervals then our fields must be.

The operation [itex]\phi (x)|0\rangle[/itex] doesn't have much to do with observation, it creates a particle state (I say "a" but there's really a sum of them as in Minkowski space-time we can expand the field as a sum over a plane wave basis).

If I write [itex]\langle 0|\phi_1\phi_2|0\rangle[/itex] as, ignoring the exponentials and what not,

[tex]\langle 0|\int d^3k\left( a^{\dagger }_{\vec{k}}+a_{\vec{k}}\right)\int d^3p\left( a^{\dagger }_{\vec{p}}+a_{\vec{p}}\right)|0\rangle[/tex]

then what we essentially have is the propogation of multiple "particles" between x and y, rather than just one of them, each described by a state [itex]a^{\dagger}_{\vec{p}}|0\rangle[/itex]. Maybe it is the interpretation that is convoluted here, whether we interpret the momentum eigenstates [itex]a^{\dagger}_{\vec{p}}|0\rangle[/itex] as particles or what may be interpreted as the position eigenstates

[tex]\phi (x)|0\rangle =\int \frac{d^3p}{(2\pi )^3}\frac{1}{2E_{\vec{p}}}e^{-i\vec{p}\cdot\vec{x}}|\vec{p}\rangle \simeq |\vec{x}\rangle [/tex]

as particles.

I think that one possible reason for this apparent violation of causality actually being acceptable is that the field does not describe a or a system of physical particles. Only some or none of them are on mass-shell, so it is perfectly acceptable for these (intermediate, as in the propogator) "particles" to not follow classical physics and have the norm of their four-momentum as, say, a negative quantity. Afterall, QFT described systems of fields not particles.

The creation of an on-shell particle state by the field at x would be written [itex]\phi (x)|\vec{p}\rangle[/itex], which are usually drawn as external lines on Feynman diagrams.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
Perturbation said:
I'm trying to think this one through as well, I don't seem to have given the thought that it is due.



Measurements correspond to eigenvalues of Hermitian operators. Since we're dealing with a theory that is the quantum analogue of lagrangian field theory, any observable can be constructed from the fields because of Noether's theorem, which will relate our observables to symmetry currents. So if we want our measurements to be commutative over space-like intervals then our fields must be.

The operation [itex]\phi (x)|0\rangle[/itex] doesn't have much to do with observation, it creates a particle state (I say "a" but there's really a sum of them as in Minkowski space-time we can expand the field as a sum over a plane wave basis).

If I write [itex]\langle 0|\phi_1\phi_2|0\rangle[/itex] as, ignoring the exponentials and what not,

[tex]\langle 0|\int d^3k\left( a^{\dagger }_{\vec{k}}+a_{\vec{k}}\right)\int d^3p\left( a^{\dagger }_{\vec{p}}+a_{\vec{p}}\right)|0\rangle[/tex]

then what we essentially have is the propogation of multiple "particles" between x and y, rather than just one of them, each described by a state [itex]a^{\dagger}_{\vec{p}}|0\rangle[/itex].

I think that one possible reason for this apparent violation of causality actually being acceptable is that the field does not describe a or a system of physical particles. Only some or none of them are on mass-shell, so it is perfectly acceptable for these (intermediate, as in the propogator) "particles" to not follow classical physics and have the norm of their four-momentum as, say, a negative quantity. Afterall, QFT described systems of fields not particles.

The creation of an on-shell particle state by the field at x would be written [itex]\phi (x)|\vec{p}\rangle[/itex], which are usually drawn as external lines on Feynman diagrams.

So in QFT what concerns us in respect to causality is observation and measurement, as the propogation amplitude does not mean what we often would interpret it as.


You are making very interesting points...

The key point, as you mention, is, I think, that the key difference between NRQM and QFT is that in NRQM we *can* define state describing a single particle at a specific point in space (it contains an infinite spread of momenta but within NRQM that is no problem), but in QFT, defining a state at a unique position necessarily involves an infinite number of particles...which makes sense since localizing a state to a very small volume involves large energies, hence creation of more particles.

That's kinda obvious but somehow I had never fully appreciated this.

It is true that trying to think of localizing a single particle at one point and asking the probability of observing it at another point later then becomes meaningless since many particles will necessarily be created.

However, it still seems to me that one can still aks the question: if many particles are created here, what is the probability that *any* of them is observed over there, and *that* should still vanish for spacelike intervals.

GHowever, I could see that this could be violated since the vacuum is not empty and if one observes something over there, it could be a vacuum fluctuation and hence have nothing to do with faster than light propagation...and these would correspond to off-shell states, I suppose...There is still something a bit funny here...:uhh:

In any case, one should still be able to define propagation of energy from one point to another and then I guess that only on-shell states would survive and causality would be respected...

I need to keep thinking about all this...:bugeye:

Thanks for the very interesting points!
 
  • #23
I might not be right, I'm just throwing in ideas here.
 
  • #24
Before I heard about Feynman diagrams and perturbation theory I thought about virtual particles like that:

If atoms decay or electrons get accelerated real photons get transmitted, since there is energy transfer. The ripples in the electromagnetic field transport energy, and photons are the quantum description of that process.

When there is a static electromagnetic field virtual photons are exchanged between the charges. Since there are no waves in the field, no energy is transported from one body to the other.

What’s wrong with that view?
 
  • #25
Would someone like to comment on my last post?

What is the difference in the photons when we have an electromagnetic field and when we have an electromagnetic wave?

thank you
 
  • #26
I really hate to triple post but why does no one like to answer my extremely easy question?

Is it because
a, you are tired of virtual particles questions
b, question is too simplistic
c, too silly
d, others

EDIT: or e, is it one of the great unsolved mysteries in the physical sciences, there is no answer yet
 
Last edited:
  • #27
Your view seams correct to me. Real photons can be measured and are quanta of electromagnetic radiation. Virtual photons cannot be measured and are used to describe interactions between charged particles.
 
  • #28
Ratzinger said:
Before I heard about Feynman diagrams and perturbation theory I thought about virtual particles like that:

If atoms decay or electrons get accelerated real photons get transmitted, since there is energy transfer. The ripples in the electromagnetic field transport energy, and photons are the quantum description of that process.

When there is a static electromagnetic field virtual photons are exchanged between the charges. Since there are no waves in the field, no energy is transported from one body to the other.

What’s wrong with that view?
virtual photons also existent in non-static electromagnetic .
 

1. What are virtual particles?

Virtual particles are particles that do not have a physical existence but are instead mathematical constructs used to describe interactions between particles in quantum field theory.

2. How are virtual particles related to Coulomb forces?

In quantum electrodynamics, the theory that describes electromagnetic interactions, virtual photons are responsible for mediating the Coulomb force between charged particles.

3. Can virtual particles be observed?

No, virtual particles cannot be directly observed as they do not have a physical existence. However, their effects can be observed through experiments and calculations in quantum field theory.

4. Are virtual particles constantly present?

Yes, virtual particles are constantly present as they are used to describe interactions between particles in quantum field theory. However, their effects are only noticeable under certain conditions, such as in high-energy experiments.

5. How do virtual particles differ from real particles?

Virtual particles differ from real particles in that they do not have a physical existence and cannot be directly observed. They also have different properties, such as mass and charge, than their corresponding real particles.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
6
Views
396
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
29
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
3
Views
718
Replies
3
Views
773
Replies
6
Views
664
Replies
4
Views
805
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
21
Views
982
Back
Top