Why is superdeterminism not the universally accepted explanation of nonlocality?

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of nonlocality and entanglement in a deterministic universe, where the information about instantaneous transfer is known to the universe. The conversation also touches upon the idea of superdeterminism, which some people reject due to its conspiratorial nature and lack of a concrete scientific theory. The possibility of interpreting nonlocality as an answer rather than a problem is also mentioned, as well as the importance of keeping beliefs aligned with measured reality. The conversation concludes with the suggestion that it may be better to believe in the existence of random and non-local phenomena rather than inventing longer explanations.
  • #351
lugita15 said:
Yes, P(θ) is the local hidden variable that determines the individual detection results.
It can't be since θ is not local-realistic.

Consider a setup where settings a and b are determined immediately before the measurement A and B by sampling polarization of photons coming from distant stars and detectors A and B are some distance apart and in relative motion. Thanks to relativity of simultaneity, it can be arranged so that in reference frame of A, measurement of A happens before the photon determining b hits the target, and vice versa, in reference frame of B, measurement B is done before a is determined. So from the point of view of either detector θ does not yet exist when the measurement is done. Therefore the results of the measurement cannot be determined by θ or any function of θ, not in local-realistic sort of way.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #352
Delta Kilo said:
It can't be since θ is not local-realistic.

Consider a setup where settings a and b are determined immediately before the measurement A and B by sampling polarization of photons coming from distant stars and detectors A and B are some distance apart and in relative motion. Thanks to relativity of simultaneity, it can be arranged so that in reference frame of A, measurement of A happens before the photon determining b hits the target, and vice versa, in reference frame of B, measurement B is done before a is determined. So from the point of view of either detector θ does not yet exist when the measurement is done. Therefore the results of the measurement cannot be determined by θ or any function of θ, not in local-realistic sort of way.
Sorry about the confusion. When I say P(θ), I don't really mean θ the relative angle between the polarizers, just the angle of a single polarizer. So P(θ1) determines the behavior of particle 1, and P(θ2) determines the behavior of particle 2, so everything is local. I could say P(x) or something instead.
 
  • #353
lugita15 said:
When I say P(θ), I don't really mean θ the relative angle between the polarizers, just the angle of a single polarizer.
Oh, I see. I though you were referring to the same θ as introduced in #338. I suspect you and ThomasT may be talking about different P(θ) then ...
 
  • #354
Delta Kilo said:
Oh, I see. I though you were referring to the same θ as introduced in #338. I suspect you and ThomasT may be talking about different P(θ) then ...
No, I think, at least I hope, that that's not the point of confusion between us.
 
  • #355
DrChinese said:
Alice and Bob are created in Venice at 10am precisely. Chris and Dale are created in New York precisely (it's just an analogy of an experiment that has actually already been performed and which I referenced earlier)). The polarization of Alice and Dale are immediately checked and they both cease to exist. They never existed in a common region of space time because they were both too far apart.

Bob and Chris are sent to our space station on Mars, where they arrive about 10:03. There, an experimenter decides to entangle them or not. After deciding to entangle, we now have the situation where Alice and Dale were entangled after they were detected, and they never existed in a common area of space time.

Now of course all of the remaining apparati/observers involved were in causal contact with each other previously, no argument about that. What I want to know is by what specific mechanism is it possible for the laser that created Alice and the laser that created Dale supposed to know how to impart a different future result for each, all the while knowing which photons will later be entangled and which ones will not.

If you understand how a laser works you will understand that there is no known distinguishing factor for one photon as compared to another. They are all 100% identical, even as to polarization.

Or maybe it isn't the laser, maybe it is the BBo crystal. But the same question then applies, how does a crystal make it do one thing versus another? By definition, the inputs are identical and the crystal has no active component which is dynamic (changes). So why one result versus another?

So the question is about the mechanism. Where is it? How does it interact with known particles? Maybe we could probe it if you told us what to look for! I think once you go through this exercise a few times, you will realize the stretch you are making. Or you can simply skip my critique and continue to hold onto your (near religious) beliefs, and prove me right as I have said.
How do you propose to entangle Bob and Chris on Mars (without using new photons)?
 
  • #356
lugita15 said:
But P(θ) just tells the particle whether to go through the polarizer or not. So the only instruction it gives the particle is a yes or a no, or equivalently a 1 or a 0.
That's one way of thinking about it. But the usual way, afaik, is (wrt optical Bell tests) to think of λ, the hidden variable determining individual detection, as the underlying polarization of polarizer-incident optical disturbances. So, one might denote the disturbance incident on polarizer setting a as λa, and the same way for the B side ... with the possible values of λab) being continuous between 0° and 180° (or between 0° and 360°, depending on how you want to frame it). And the same for the values of the polarizer settings, a and b. So that, in line with standard classical and quantum optics, the photon flux at A would be denoted by the function,

cos2(a - λa),

and in the same way for the B side.

This LR way of modelling individual detections is compatible with QM. But when it's extended to model the joint (entanglement) context it isn't compatible with QM.

Anyway, the point I'm making here is that confining the values of the hidden variable (that presumably determines individual detection) to the discrete values, 0 and 1, might be the point at which the conclusion that the correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is linear becomes logically necessary. I'm not sure.
 
  • #357
OK, so let's say a particular entangled photon pair is sent to the two polarizers. When the one of them encounters a particular polarizer setting, it calculates the corresponding value of λ, which is an angle. Now how does it use this angle to decide whether to go through or not? Remember, there must be a deterministic way it does this. Talking about average photon flux doesn't help here, because we're talking about a single photon meeting a single polarizer.
 
  • #358
lugita15 said:
Just to add to this, the function P(θ), since it is the hidden variable, can be determined by any number of things, including a polarization vector or anything else. But the input of the function must be the polarizer setting, and the output must be a yes-or-no instruction telling the particle to go through or not.
Yes. But wrt a local realistic view, the independent variables, the input, are not just the polarizer orientation, but also the polarization of the incident optical disturbance ... which are continuous within proscribed limits. The output is either the registration of a detection (usually denoted as 1), or a nondetection (usually denoted as 0), wrt any particular coincidence interval (ie., wrt paired detection attributes).

As I mentioned, maybe it's wrt this step that your particular LR line of reasoning necessitates the conclusion that the correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is linear.

Though I thought it was Step 5. But I could be mistaken.

I don't see how the inference of a linear correlation follows from Step 4. ...

lugita15 said:
4. Another experimental prediction of quantum mechanics is that if the polarizers are set at different angles, the mismatch (i.e. the lack of correlation) between the two photons is a function R(θ) of the relative angle between the polarizers.

... because all Step 4. says is that the correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is a function of θ. Which leaves open the question of whether or not this is a linear or a nonlinear correlation.
 
  • #359
ThomasT said:
Yes. But wrt a local realistic view, the independent variables, the input, are not just the polarizer orientation, but also the polarization of the incident optical disturbance ... which are continuous within proscribed limits.
I'm including things like polarization vectors in the description of the particular function P for a particular entangled pair, rather than including them as an input of the function. This is just an arbitrary choice in how I'm defining things, so it shouldn't affect anything.
 
  • #360
lugita15 said:
OK, so let's say a particular entangled photon pair is sent to the two polarizers. When the one of them encounters a particular polarizer setting, it calculates the corresponding value of λ, which is an angle. Now how does it use this angle to decide whether to go through or not?
λ is meant to denote the polarization (angle) of the incident optical disturbance. a (or b) denotes the polarizer setting.

So, from standard optics, individual detection is the function, cos2(a - λa), or in the same way for the B side.

-------------------------------

You've asked, quite rightly I think, which of your steps would a more comprehensive local deterministic view disagree with.

It's the step (in your steps) from which a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is necessitated.

So, which step, in your opinion, is that?
 
  • #361
lugita15 said:
I'm including things like polarization vectors in the description of the particular function P for a particular entangled pair, rather than including them as an input of the function. This is just an arbitrary choice in how I'm defining things, so it shouldn't affect anything.
You've discretized the possible values of λ, a presumably continuous underlying parameter, in terms of dichotomized detector outputs. Is this the point where LR models of entanglement become incompatible with QM ... and the design of Bell tests?
 
  • #362
ThomasT said:
λ is meant to denote the polarization (angle) of the incident optical disturbance. a (or b) denotes the polarizer setting.

So, from standard optics, individual detection is the function, cos2(a - λa), or in the same way for the B side.
You still haven't told me how any of this determines whether a particular photon goes through the polarizer or not.
ThomasT said:
You've asked, quite rightly I think, which of your steps would a more comprehensive local deterministic view disagree with.

It's the step (in your steps) from which a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is necessitated.

So, which step, in your opinion, is that?
I'll summarize the argument up to the point where I think logical necessity enters the picture: the two photons in a pair exhibit identical behavior at identical angle settings, therefore the particles have coordinated in advance which polarizer angles they will go through and which ones they won't. From just this much, I think linear correlation is necessitated. The rest is just spelling out the chain of logical deduction.
 
  • #363
ThomasT said:
You've discretized the possible values of λ, a presumably continuous underlying parameter, in terms of dichotomized detector outputs. Is this the point where LR models of entanglement become incompatible with QM ... and the design of Bell tests?
In step 3, all I'm saying is that the two photons, right when they are created, agree in advance what polarizer angles to go through and what angles not to go through. (I'm talking about individual polarizer settings, not angle difference.) How they choose which angles they want to go through and which ones not to is irrelevant. They could do it using some polarization vector or anything else. But the point is that they've made a definite decision about what angles are "good" and what angles are "bad". And it is just this information that I am calling P(θ).

I think if you do not believe that the particles have chosen the good and bad angles in advance, but you believe in identical behavior at identical polarizer settings, you cannot sensibly call yourself a local determinist.
 
Last edited:
  • #364
lugita15 said:
You still haven't told me how any of this determines whether a particular photon goes through the polarizer or not.
Afaik, there's no way to determine that.

But, in one way of modelling it, the rate of individual detection (ie., the photon flux), per unit time, is,

cos2(a - λa)


lugita15 said:
I'll summarize the argument up to the point where I think logical necessity enters the picture: the two photons in a pair exhibit identical behavior at identical angle settings ...
Wrt your points this would be:

lugita15 said:
2. One of these [QM] experimental predictions is that entangled photons are perfectly correlated when sent through polarizers oriented at the same angle ...
From this I might infer that entangled photons are created via some common causal mechanism, and that their underlying properties are therefore related (which is in line with the QM treatment).

lugita15 said:
... therefore the particles have coordinated in advance which polarizer angles they will go through and which ones they won't.
Wrt, say, Aspect 1982, the QM treatment is that the polarizer-incident optical disturbances are related wrt the conservation of angular momentum. The net effect of this assumption is that wrt θ = 0° coincidental detection attributes will be (1,1) or (0,0).

This isn't in conflict with LR predictions, and doesn't necessitate a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection.

lugita15 said:
From just this much, I think linear correlation is necessitated.
Well, that can't be it. Because identical detection attributes at EPR settings don't necessitate a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection. So, it has to be some other step.
 
  • #365
lugita15 said:
In step 3, all I'm saying is that the two photons, right when they are created, agree in advance what polarizer angles to go through and what angles not to go through. (I'm talking about individual polarizer settings, not angle difference.) How they choose which angles they want to go through and which ones not to is irrelevant. They could do it using some polarization vector or anything else. But the point is that they've made a definite decision about what angles are "good" and what angles are "bad". And it is just this information that I am calling P(θ).
Ok, and what I'm saying is that this "information" which determines the rate of individual detection is irrelevant wrt determining the rate of coincidental detection. Wrt the Aspect experiments the creation of an entangled pair imparts a relationship between them. They have a particular common or identical polarization which determines the rate of individual detection, and they have a relationship which, obviously, does not determine the rate of individual detection.

As I mentioned, the usual way of thinking about this is that, wrt say the Aspect experiments, λ refers to an underlying common polarization orientation ... which is, as far as I can tell, an acceptable inference given the experimental results.

From that inference one can construct a model of individual detection that's compatible with QM.

But if one tries to model coincidental detection in terms of that underlying parameter (the parameter that determines individual detection), then such a model will not be able to reproduce all the predictions of QM.

Now, go back to the visualization I suggested. You'll see that the parameter that determines individual detection, λ, the polarization of polarizer-incident photons, has nothing to do with, ie., is irrelevant wrt, coincidental detection.

What might we conclude from this? The assumption of identical underlying (and locally produced via emission process) polarization seems supported by experimental results. But, as we've seen, the polarization orientation has nothing to do with the rate of coincidental detection, and, additionally, the underlying parameter determining the rate of coincidental detection cannot be varying from pair to pair. Hence, the only logical conclusion is that the underlying parameters determining individual detection and coincidental detection are different underlying parameters.

lugita15 said:
I think if you do not believe that the particles have chosen the good and bad angles in advance, but you believe in identical behavior at identical polarizer settings, you cannot sensibly call yourself a local determinist.
I do believe that there is an underlying parameter that determines rate of individual detection. And it's an experimental fact that when θ = 0° then coincidental detection attributes will be either (0,0) or (1,1).

And, I also believe that rate of coincidental detection is not determined by λ. It can be anything. Doesn't matter. Coincidental detection is only determined by θ.
 
  • #366
ThomasT said:
Afaik, there's no way to determine that.

But, in one way of modelling it, the rate of individual detection (ie., the photon flux), per unit time, is,

cos2(a - λa)
It's not good enough to determine the rate of individual detection. The hidden variable must determine whether a given photon goes through a given polarizer at a given angle. Otherwise you don't have a deterministic theory.
ThomasT said:
Wrt, say, Aspect 1982, the QM treatment is that the polarizer-incident optical disturbances are related wrt the conservation of angular momentum. The net effect of this assumption is that wrt θ = 0° coincidental detection attributes will be (1,1) or (0,0).

This isn't in conflict with LR predictions, and doesn't necessitate a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection.
First of all, stick to the idealized setup please, because that's what my steps are designed for. Second of all, we've hit on a crucial point here: while it's true that both the quantum mechanics guy and the local determinist agree that at identical angles you only get (1,1) or (0,0), they disagree as to the interpretation of this fact. Quantum mechanics says that you have a wave function for the two particle system which gets collapsed, nonlocally of course, as soon as one of the particles is measured, and that is how the other particle knows to do the same thing as the first particle, even though they're separated by a great distance. In contrast, the local determinist would say that it's not some nonlocal collapse that is correlating their behaviors, but rather their past interaction in which they determined *in advance* what angles they would go through and what angles they would not go through. It is because of this difference that step 3 must hold for local deterministic theories but does not hold for quantum mechanics.
 
  • #367
ThomasT said:
I do believe that there is an underlying parameter that determines rate of individual detection.
That's not good enough. You have to believe that not just the rate of individual detection is predetermined, but also each and every individual detection result. You have to believe that for each individual entangled pair, the two particles in the pair decide in advance the pair's "good" angles and "bad" angles, meaning exactly which angles the photon will go through and which it won't. Without all that, how can you call yourself a local determinist?
 
  • #368
lugita15 said:
It's not good enough to determine the rate of individual detection. The hidden variable must determine whether a given photon goes through a given polarizer at a given angle. Otherwise you don't have a deterministic theory.
The function, cos2(a - λa), does determine whether a given photon goes through a given polarizer at a given angle. At least that's the assumption. But λa can't be controlled.
 
  • #369
lugita15 said:
... we've hit on a crucial point here: while it's true that both the quantum mechanics guy and the local determinist agree that at identical angles you only get (1,1) or (0,0), they disagree as to the interpretation of this fact.
I'm not sure that's the case.

lugita15 said:
Quantum mechanics says that you have a wave function for the two particle system which gets collapsed, nonlocally of course, as soon as one of the particles is measured, and that is how the other particle knows to do the same thing as the first particle, even though they're separated by a great distance.
How, exactly, does that work? What do you think is the conceptual basis for that assumption?

lugita15 said:
In contrast, the local determinist would say that it's not some nonlocal collapse that is correlating their behaviors, but rather their past interaction in which they determined *in advance* what angles they would go through and what angles they would not go through.
I'm curious. This is based on a knowledge of the historically documented behavior of light. What makes you think that the standard QM treatment isn't based on that very same knowledge, and associated inferences/assumptions?

It's already been demonstrated that the function correlating individual detection to λ and individual polarizer setting is compatible with QM.

lugita15 said:
It is because of this difference that step 3 must hold for local deterministic theories but does not hold for quantum mechanics.

lugita15 said:
3. From this you conclude that both photons are consulting the same function P(θ). If P(θ)=1, then the photon goes through the polarizer, and if it equals zero the photon does not go through.
This seems to me to be compatible with QM. Why do you think it isn't?
 
Last edited:
  • #370
lugita15 said:
You have to believe that not just the rate of individual detection is predetermined, but also each and every individual detection result.
I believe that. And that belief is compatible with the QM formalism regarding individual results. It's just that λ can't be controlled. At least that's the assumption (based on extant experimental preparation).

lugita15 said:
You have to believe that for each individual entangled pair, the two particles in the pair decide in advance the pair's "good" angles and "bad" angles, meaning exactly which angles the photon will go through and which it won't. Without all that, how can you call yourself a local determinist?
I do believe something akin to that, just not in those terms. And so does QM. But QM recognizes that what's determining coincidental detection is the relationship between entangled photons. And that that's a parameter that individual measurements aren't measuring. Hence, the nonseparability of the parameters relevant to the coincidental measurement of entangled particles, and the nonseparability/nonlocality of the associated QM formalism.
 
Last edited:
  • #371
I asked you: which of your steps would a more comprehensive local deterministic view disagree with?

Stating that, it's the step (in your steps) from which a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is necessitated.

Then I asked: which step, in your opinion, is that?

And you answered that it's your Step 2.

Which says:

lugita15 said:
2. One of these [QM] experimental predictions is that entangled photons are perfectly correlated when sent through polarizers oriented at the same angle ...

And I pointed out that it's clearly evident (ie., obvious) that this observation, this step, doesn't imply a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection.

So, which of your steps does imply such a correlation?
 
Last edited:
  • #372
ThomasT said:
The function, cos2(a - λa), does determine whether a given photon goes through a given polarizer at a given angle. At least that's the assumption. But λa can't be controlled.
So how do you get from cos2(a - λa) to a 0 or a 1?
 
  • #373
ThomasT said:
How, exactly, does that work? What do you think is the conceptual basis for that assumption?
Wavefunction collapse has an illustrious history going back to Max Born and John von Neumann. They saw collapse as the most natural explanation for the fact the wavefunction could be calculated deterministically using the Schrodinger equation, but the results of quantum mechanical experiments could only be predicted probabilistically. And I think it was Schrodinger himself who came up with the idea that entangled particles are described a common wavefunction that stretches across space, and that any changes in the wavefunction propagate instantaneously.
It's already been demonstrated that the function correlating individual detection to λ and individual polarizer setting is compatible with QM.
Where has this been demonstrated?
This seems to me to be compatible with QM. Why do you think it isn't?
According to the conventional interpretation of quantum mechanics, you have a nonlocal wavefunction collapse that determines on the spot whether the particles should go through or not. Whereas a local determinist believes that the particles have agreed in advance what angles to go through or not go through.
 
Last edited:
  • #374
ThomasT said:
I believe that. And that belief is compatible with the QM formalism regarding individual results.
No, it's not. In the QM formalism, the question of what angles the photons goes through and what angles it doesn't go through is not predetermined in advanced, but is rather determined on the spot in a random manner when the wavefunction collapse occurs.
I do believe something akin to that, just not in those terms. And so does QM.
No, QM doesn't.
 
  • #375
ThomasT said:
I asked you: which of your steps would a more comprehensive local deterministic view disagree with?

Stating that, it's the step (in your steps) from which a linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is necessitated.

Then I asked: which step, in your opinion, is that?

And you answered that it's your Step 2.
No, I answered that it's my step 3, which says that the particles determine in advance what angles to go through and what angles not to go through. From there, it is my claim that logical deduction will get you to the conclusion that local determinism is incompatible with the notion that all the predictions of QM are correct.
 
  • #376
lugita15 said:
So how do you get from cos2(a - λa) to a 0 or a 1?
Since λa is presumably varying randomly from photon to photon, then individual detection attributes (0 or 1) can't be predicted.

We're concerned with the rate of detection at A, which can be denoted as the function R(A).
Since λa is varying randomly, then the angular difference argument of R(A) is also varying randomly. So, averaging over that, you get R(A) = .5 (the rate of detection, or photon flux per unit time, without the polarizer, a, in place).

That is, R(A) predicts a random sequence of 0's and 1's for a run ... half 0's and half 1's.

Which is the same thing that QM predicts.
 
  • #377
ThomasT said:
Since λa is presumably varying randomly from photon to photon, then individual detection attributes (0 or 1) can't be predicted.
OK, but given λa for a particular photon pair, how do you get a 0 or a 1 out of that?
 
  • #378
lugita15 said:
Wavefunction collapse has an illustrious history going back to Max Born and John von Neumann. They saw collapse as the most natural explanation for the fact the wavefunction could be calculated deterministically using the Schrodinger equation, but the results of quantum mechanical experiments could only be predicted probabilistically. And I think it was Schrodinger himself who came up with the idea that entangled particles are described by a common wavefunction that stretches across space, and that any changes in the wavefunction propagate instantaneously.
I don't think that's the most natural, or logical, way of looking at the experimental situation or interpreting the QM formalism. Instantaneous propagation seems to be a contradiction in terms. Reification of ψ carries some unnecessary baggage with it, and I doubt that most working physicists think in those terms.

Both LR and QM have coincidental detection determined by the incident photons consulting a common function. Ie., there's a common cause which produces the relationship between entangled photons that the polarizers are jointly measuring. The difference is that QM doesn't use λ (which refers to the polarization orientation of the polarizer-incident photons), presumably recognizing that the value of λ is irrelevant wrt determining rate of coincidental detection.

lugita15 said:
Where has this been demonstrated?
In my previous post. Or you can go back to Bell 1964.
J. S. Bell said:
So in this simple case there is no difficulty in the view that the result of every measurement is determined by the value of an extra variable, and that the statistical features of quantum mechanics arise because the value of this variable is unknown in individual instances.

Wrt,
3. From this you conclude that both photons are consulting the same function P(θ). If P(θ)=1, then the photon goes through the polarizer, and if it equals zero the photon does not go through.
I said,
ThomasT said:
This seems to me to be compatible with QM. Why do you think it isn't?
To which you replied,
lugita15 said:
According to the conventional interpretation of quantum mechanics, you have a nonlocal wavefunction collapse that determines on the spot whether the particles should go through or not. Whereas a local determinist believes that the particles have agreed in advance what angles to go through or not go through.
Both QM and LR have entangled photons consulting the same function. This is because they both assume a common cause. The stuff about nonlocal wavefunction collapse is just unwarranted and unnecessary, imo. The fact is that QM is acausal and (to paraphrase Bohm) nonmechanical wrt entanglement.

Why is the QM formalism the way it is? I'm not sure about that, but I think it does have to do with the assumption of a common cause. Also, as I think I've shown, the value of λ is irrelevant wrt determining rate of coincidental detection. And, anyway, QM doesn't have to be causal, since it's just calculating measurement probabilities.

Why can one still assume local determinism given the QM formalism? Because the QM formalism is acausal wrt entanglement. So, one might interpret entanglement as being due to nonlocal transmissions between entangled photons, or not. No way to know, afaik. Ultimately, the QM treatment wrt optical Bell tests is evaluated wrt the known behavior of light. And of course so should be any LR treatment of entanglement ... which is something that your line of reasoning seems to ignore.
 
  • #379
lugita15 said:
OK, but given λa for a particular photon pair, how do you get a 0 or a 1 out of that?
The prediction, wrt LR and QM, is that the result at A, wrt any particular individual detection, will be either 0 (no detection registered) or 1 (detection registered).
 
  • #380
lugita15 said:
No, I answered that it's my step 3, which says that the particles determine in advance what angles to go through and what angles not to go through. From there, it is my claim that logical deduction will get you to the conclusion that local determinism is incompatible with the notion that all the predictions of QM are correct.
It's been shown that the underlying parameter that determines coincidental detection (lets denote rate of coincidental detection as R(A, B)) is not varying from pair to pair. So, why would you think that an underlying parameter, eg. your P(θ), that is varying randomly from pair to pair is determining R(A,B)?
 
Last edited:
  • #381
lugita15 said:
In the QM formalism, the question of what angles the photon goes through and what angles it doesn't go through is not predetermined in advance ...
But it can be interpreted that way. As noted, and demonstrated, an LR account of individual measurement is compatible with QM.

lugita15 said:
... but is rather determined on the spot in a random manner when the wavefunction collapse occurs.
Well, now you're talking about coincidental detection. Which is a different observational context. And, as I've mentioned, the QM treatment is nonmechanical wrt the projection along an axis associated with a detection. Afaik, this is based on the known behavior of light (eg., the law of Malus), and is retained because it works.
 
  • #382
ThomasT, I asked you, in what step of my argument do you believe that a local determinist can part ways? You say that it is whatever step that makes linear correlation an inevitability, and I claim that is at a very early stage in the argument that it becomes logically inevitable, but you disagree. Let me try once again to present my argument; I've refined the steps in an attempt to iron out any points of confusion or disagreement we've had so far. (And keep in mind that this is in the context of my idealized setup, not an actual practical Bell test like Aspect's.)

1. Suppose you are a local determinist who agrees with the experimental predicts of QM.
2. One of those experimental predictions is that the two photons in an entangled pair exhibit identical behavior when sent through identical polarizers at oriented at identical angles.
3. You conclude that the two photons have agreed in advance (in any way, whether by polarization vector or some other way) what polarizer angles they should go through and what polarizer angles they should not go through.
4. If they have decided to go through at particular angle θ, let us denote this by P(θ)=1, and if they have not decided to go through at the angle θ, let us denote this by P(θ)=0.
5. Let R(θ1,θ2) denote the percentage of mismatches (situations where one photon goes through and the other does not) if polarizer 1 is set to angle θ1 and polarizer 2 is set to angle θ2.
6. Using the definition of P in step 4, R(θ1,θ2) is the probability that P(θ1)≠P(θ2) for a randomly selected entangled pair.
7. It is an experimental prediction of quantum mechanics that R(θ1+C,θ2+C)=R(θ1,θ2) and R(θ1,θ2)=R(θ2,θ1), so we can just write R(θ1,θ2) as R(θ) where θ=|θ1-θ2|.
8. Using steps 6 and 7, the probability that P(θ1)≠P(θ2) for a randomly selected entangled pair is given by R(θ) where θ=|θ1-θ2|.
9. It is a mathematical fact that if you have two events A and B, then the probability that at least one of these events occurs (in other words the probability that A or B occurs) is less than or equal to the probability that A occurs plus the probability that B occurs.
10. You conclude that the probability that P(-30)≠P(30) is less than or equal to the probability that that P(-30)≠P(0) plus the probability that P(0)≠P(30), or in terms of R we can say R(60)≤R(30)+R(30)=2R(30)

So which step do you think there can be disagreeement on by a local determinist? Let me tell you that 1 is the assumption, 4 and 5 are definitions, 2 and 7 are experimental predictions of quantum mechanics, and 9 is a mathematical fact, so I think those are all beyond dispute. That leaves 3, 6, 8, and 10. But 6 follows from 4 and 5, 8 follows from 6 and 7, and 10 follows from 9.

That leaves 3, which I think is the point after which the argument becomes inevitable, but I am happy to hear if you think any of the other steps can be disagreed with.
 
  • #383
And let me also say that you're right in one respect about 3: it is not in and of itself an experimental difference between local determinism and quantum mechanics. Rather, it is a philosophical difference between local determinism and certain interpretations of QM which believe in nonlocal wavefunction collapse or nonlocal communication. Yet it is my claim that this particular philosophical, interpretational difference turns out to lead to differences in the actual empirical predictions of these two philosophical belief systems. And my purpose in this now 10-step argument is to demonstrate that there are such empirical differences: that a local deterministic universe cannot match all the experimental predictions of quantum mechanics.
 
  • #384
lugita15 said:
That leaves 3, which I think is the point after which the argument becomes inevitable, but I am happy to hear if you think any of the other steps can be disagreed with.
Step 3. has to do with individual detection, and the randomly varying underlying parameter which determines that. And, as has been shown, that underlying parameter is irrelevant wrt coincidental detection.

So, ok, if you assume that that parameter is determining coincidental detection, then that might account for the incorrect conclusion that the correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection is linear.

But it certainly doesn't inform wrt the locality or nonlocality of nature.
 
  • #385
lugita15 said:
And let me also say that you're right in one respect about 3: it is not in and of itself an experimental difference between local determinism and quantum mechanics. Rather, it is a philosophical difference between local determinism and certain interpretations of QM which believe in nonlocal wavefunction collapse or nonlocal communication. Yet it is my claim that this particular philosophical, interpretational difference turns out to lead to differences in the actual empirical predictions of these two philosophical belief systems. And my purpose in this now 10-step argument is to demonstrate that there are such empirical differences: that a local deterministic universe cannot match all the experimental predictions of quantum mechanics.
I think that the differences have nothing to do with what's actually happening in the reality underlying instrumental behavior.

And of course I have no way of proving my contention any more than you do of proving yours.

I just think that mine is ... more reasonable, given what's known about the behavior of light.
That is, there's no compelling reason, imo, to adopt the assumption that entangled particles are communicating nonlocally, while there are, imo, some compelling reasons to suppose that they aren't. So, in the absence of empirical evidence to the contrary, we retain the assumptions of locality and determinism.
 

Similar threads

Replies
75
Views
8K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
47
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
968
Replies
12
Views
2K
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
3
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
69
Views
4K
Replies
10
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
2
Views
2K
Back
Top