Splitting an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets.

In summary: A|=|B U C|=|B'|+|C'|=|B|+|C|=|A|+|A|=|A|.In summary, for any infinite set A, it is possible to partition A into two disjoint subsets B and C, each with cardinality |A|. This can be proven by showing that |A| = |A| + |A| and then constructing B and C such that |B| = |C| = |A| and |A| = |B U C|. This does not require any form of choice and follows directly from the definitions.
  • #1
mathboy
182
0
So if A is an infinite set, we know that |A|+|A|=|A|. But are we allowed to go backwards, i.e. divide A into two disjoint subsets B and C such that A = B U C, and |B|=|C|=|A|. For the integers and for the reals, this is clear, e.g. R = (-infinity,0) U [0, infinity), each with cardinality c. But are we allowed to do this for any infinite set of larger cardinality? I'm sure the answer is yes, but how do we go about proving this? Do we have to use the Axiom of Choice and transfinite induction? How complicated will the proof be?
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
an equality goes both ways
 
  • #3
I think you're misunderstanding the question: he's asking if, for an infinite set A, the the system of equations

A = B U C
|A| = |B|
|A| = |C|

has a solution for B and C.
 
  • #4
and B and C must be disjoint.

e.g.
A=Integers: B= even integers, C=odd integers. Done.
A=Reals: B=(-infinity,0), C=[0, infinity). Done.
A=P(R): B=? C=? The problem begins with cardinality greater than c.

How about this: Well-order A. Put the first element in the left bin, the second in the right bin,...alternatingly put the elements of A
in the left bin and right bin. By transfinite induction, this can be done for all elements of A. Then each bin has |A| elements.
 
Last edited:
  • #5
You need choice. By choice there exists a bijection between any set and an ordinal. Every ordinal can be written as A + n where n is a natural number. You can then split them into "even" and "odd".
 
  • #6
So ordinals must be used to prove this?
 
  • #7
What's important is the bijection. Of course there might be other ways.
 
  • #8
Here's my proof attempt without using ordinals.

Let A={a_i| i in I}. Well-order I. Suppose all elements a_i can be placed alternatingly in bin B and bin C for i < j. Then a_j can be placed in B if the previous was placed in C (and vice versa). So by transfinite induction, this can be done for all i in I, so A=BUC. We have B and C disjoint, and |B|=|C|. Then
|A|=|BUC|=|B|+|C|=2|B|=|B|=|C|. Sounds good?
 
  • #9
I observe that your conjecture is a consequence of |A|=|AxA|. That can be proven without choice, right?
 
  • #10
Wait, wait, do you want A = B U C, or |A| = |B U C|? Because if it's the latter, all you have to do is notice that |A| = | {0}xA U {1}xA |
 
  • #11
mathboy said:
Well-order I.

This uses choice.
 
  • #12
Dragonfall said:
Wait, wait, do you want A = B U C, or |A| = |B U C|? Because if it's the latter, all you have to do is notice that |A| = | {0}xA U {1}xA |

Partition A into B U C, such that |B|=|C|=|A|. Actually, we should be able to generalize this to k partitions of A such that each partition has cardinatility |A|, and k is any (infinite) number less than |A|, right?
 
  • #13
Hurkyl said:
I think you're misunderstanding the question: he's asking if, for an infinite set A, the the system of equations

A = B U C
|A| = |B|
|A| = |C|

has a solution for B and C.

i knew what he meant and what i said stands. c + c = c, and [itex]\aleph_0 + \aleph_0 =\aleph_0[/itex] if the sets are disjoint and if they're not they can be made so by using dragonfall's method. hence c = c + c and [itex]\aleph_0 = \aleph_0 + \aleph_0 [/itex].

now that i reread his first post i don't understand the difficulty?

mathboy said:
So if A is an infinite set, we know that |A|+|A|=|A|. But are we allowed to go backwards, i.e. divide A into two disjoint subsets B and C such that A = B U C, and |B|=|C|=|A|. For the integers and for the reals, this is clear, e.g. R = (-infinity,0) U [0, infinity), each with cardinality c. But are we allowed to do this for any infinite set of larger cardinality? I'm sure the answer is yes, but how do we go about proving this? Do we have to use the Axiom of Choice and transfinite induction? How complicated will the proof be?

if the question is this :

|A| + |A| = |A| :1
|B|=|C|=|A| :2

|B|+|C| [tex]\stackrel{?}{=}[/tex] |A|

how is it not immediate that by 2
(|A|=|B|) + (|A|=|C|) = |B|+|C| = |A| ?

this is of course taking for granted cardinal addition and equality.
 
Last edited:
  • #14
I'm not trying to prove that |B|+|C| = |A|. That follows immediately from |A| + |A| = |A|. I'm trying to prove that B and C exist such that B and C partition A and each have cardinality |A|. But I think I've already proven it now, and am wondering about the infinite partitioning case.
 
  • #15
again huh? what do you mean by partition? here are three theorems from my set theory book that might be what you're looking for :

countable union of countable sets is countable
any infinite set can written as the union of disjoint countably infinite sets.
any infinite set A can be written as a disjoint union A = B U C where A,B, and C have the same cardinality.
 
  • #16
ice109 said:
any infinite set A can be written as a disjoint union A = B U C where A,B, and C have the same cardinality.

This is what mathboy was asking about, I think. Does this require some form of choice?
 
  • #17
mathboy said:
So if A is an infinite set, we know that |A|+|A|=|A|.

ice109 said:
an equality goes both ways

That answers the question.
Starting with the knowledge that |A|=|A|+|A|, no choice is required, it is just a matter of applying the definitions.

More precisely, |A|=|A|+|A| just means that there are two disjoint sets B,C such that |B|=|C|=|A| and |A|=|B U C|. By definition B U C can be put into 1-1 correspondence with A. Let B' be the image of B and C' be the image of C. Then A = B' U C' and |B'|=|C'|=|A|.
 
  • #18
ice109 said:
any infinite set A can be written as a disjoint union A = B U C where A,B, and C have the same cardinality.
Yes, that was my original question (but I've generalized it now). How long is the proof in your textbook for this? What's the sketch of the proof? Does it depend on axiom of choice?


ice109 said:
any infinite set can written as the union of disjoint countably infinite sets.
any infinite set A can be written as a disjoint union A = B U C where A,B, and C have the same cardinality.

Almost gives me what I seek. My generalized conjecture is:

If A is infinite, then A can be written as the union of pairwise disjoint sets {B_i| i in I}, with |B_i| = |A| for each i in I, and |I| can be any finite number or any infinite number less than |A|.

For example, the reals can be partitioned into
..., [-1,0), [0,1), [1,2), [2,3), ... .
Each set is disjoint, each with cardinality |R|, and there are |Z|<|R| many of them.
 
Last edited:
  • #19
mathboy said:
If A is infinite, then A can be written as the union of pairwise disjoint sets {B_i| i in I}, with |B_i| = |A| for each i in I, and |I| can be any finite number or any infinite number less than |A|.

That is equivalent to |A| = |A| x |I| using a similar argument to my previous post.
 
  • #20
gel said:
That is equivalent to |A| = |A| x |I| using a similar argument to my previous post.

I already know that for any two cardinal numbers a,b, that ab=max{a,b}.

I am wondering if the partition is always possible for any infinite set A.
 
Last edited:
  • #21
mathboy said:
I am wondering if the partition is always possible for any infinite set A.

Well, if |A| = |A| x |I| then there is a 1-1 mapping between A and A x I. Let this be f : AxI -> A. Then, for every i in I, let Ai be the image of {(a,i): a in A} under f. This gives the required partition.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
gel said:
Well, if |A| = |A| x |I| then there is a 1-1 mapping between A and A x I. Let this be f : AxI -> A. Then, for every i in I, let Ai be the image of {(a,i): a in A} under f. This gives the required partition.

Ah, yes. That does it!

Now since |R| = |R|x|R|, then that means that R (reals) can be partitioned into |R| many disjoint subsets each with cardinality |R|. What is an explicit such partition of R? R can be partitioned into
..., [-1,0), [0,1), [1,2), [2,3), ... ,
each subset with cardinality |R|, but there are only |Z| many of them.

Even stranger, how can Z (the integers) be partitioned into |Z| many subsets, each subset with cardinality |Z|? So we know it is possible. But what is an example?
 
Last edited:
  • #23
mathboy said:
What is an explicit such partition of R?

For any real number x let x(n) be the digit in its n'th position (any n in Z).
Then, let Ax consist of the real numbers y satisfying y(2n)=x(n). I think that should do it.

Actually, I ignored the signs of x and y here. I should have insisted that Ax only contains non-negative numbers when x is non-negative, and negative numbers when x is negative. Also, you have to be careful to handle the possibility of repeating 9's in the expansion of x (you should allow them), and y (shouldn't allow them). That's all messy details though.
 
Last edited:
  • #24
mathboy said:
Even stranger, how can Z (the integers) be partitioned into |Z| many subsets, each subset with cardinality |Z|? So we know it is possible. But what is an example?

For every integer n, let f(n) be 22n if n >= 0 and 2-2n-1 if n <0.
Let An consist of all numbers of the form m f(n) for odd m.


...ok, to be pedantic, An is a partition of the non-zero integers. You can add 0 to A0 to make it a partition of Z.
 
  • #25
mathboy said:
Even stranger, how can Z (the integers) be partitioned into |Z| many subsets, each subset with cardinality |Z|? So we know it is possible. But what is an example?

Let B_p be the set of all integers whose lowest prime factor is the pth prime number. |B_p|=|Z| for all p and they are disjoint, and there are |Z| many such p's since there are infinitely many prime numbers. Remove 0,1,-1 from Z.
 
Last edited:
  • #26
To make my example above for the partition of R a bit more precise.

Let x(n) be the n'th digit of x, and sign(x) = 1 if x >= 0 and -1 if x < 0.
So [itex]x = {\rm sign}(x)\sum_{n=-\infty}^\infty 10^n x(n)[/itex].

For every real x, you can define [itex]f(x)= {\rm sign}(x)\sum_{n=-\infty}^\infty 10^n x(2n)[/itex], and the partition is given by Ax = f-1({x}).

This takes care of the problem of repeating 9s in the decimal expansion of x.
 
  • #27
gel said:
To make my example above for the partition of R a bit more precise.

Let x(n) be the n'th digit of x, and sign(x) = 1 if x >= 0 and -1 if x < 0.
So [itex]x = {\rm sign}(x)\sum_{n=-\infty}^\infty 10^n x(n)[/itex].

For every real x, you can define [itex]f(x)= {\rm sign}(x)\sum_{n=-\infty}^\infty 10^n x(2n)[/itex], and the partition is given by Ax = f-1({x}).

This takes care of the problem of repeating 9s in the decimal expansion of x.

i don't understand this

mathboy said:
Yes, that was my original question (but I've generalized it now). How long is the proof in your textbook for this? What's the sketch of the proof? Does it depend on axiom of choice?

yes the proof requires zorn's lemma
 
  • #28
gel said:
To make my example above for the partition of R a bit more precise.

Let x(n) be the n'th digit of x, and sign(x) = 1 if x >= 0 and -1 if x < 0.
So [itex]x = {\rm sign}(x)\sum_{n=-\infty}^\infty 10^n x(n)[/itex].

For every real x, you can define [itex]f(x)= {\rm sign}(x)\sum_{n=-\infty}^\infty 10^n x(2n)[/itex], and the partition is given by Ax = f-1({x}).

This takes care of the problem of repeating 9s in the decimal expansion of x.

gel is following the classic bijection of [0,1)x[0,1) to [0,1), moving all decimal places to double the decimal position. For example, if x = 123.456, then A_x is the set of all real numbers of the form ..._0_0_0_1_2_3_._4_5_6_0_0_0_... .
 
Last edited:
  • #29
Wow! Excellent guys! Does anyone dare give an explicit partition of the power set P(R) of the reals into |P(R)| disjoint subsets each with cardinality |P(R)| ?
 
  • #30
mathboy said:
Wow! Excellent guys! Does anyone dare give an explicit partition of the power set P(R) of the reals into |P(R)| disjoint subsets each with cardinality |P(R)| ?
For each subset S={x_i|i in I} of R, let A_S be the collection of all subsets of R of the form {y_i|i in I}, with each y_i obtained from x_i by the doubling the digit positions again and padding between those digits with any digits. P(R) is certainly the union of all the A_S, and there are |P(R)| many such A_S.

Wait, |A_S|=|R| not |P(R)|. Arggh, this is a bit messed up!
 
Last edited:
  • #31
why does it seem to me like this is verging on trying to make onto functions from a function onto it's powerset? even before mathboy mentioned the p(r)
 
  • #32
P(A + B) and P(A) x P(B) are naturally bijective sets, right? So all you need to do is find sets A and B, and bijections

A + B ~ R
A ~ R
B ~ R

And voilà! You have a bijection P(R) ~ P(R) x P(R).
 
Last edited:
  • #33
Bijection F:P(R) x P(R) -> P(R):

Start with two subsets S and T of R. Get the characteristic functions (chi_S, chi_T). Get the characteristic function f:R -> {0,1} defined by

f(x)= (chi_S)(lnx) if x>0, (chi_T)(ln(-x)) if x<0. (problems with x=0, so someone find a better bijection from Rx{1,2} to R)

From the characteristic function f, get your unique subset of R corresponding to f. This subset of R is our F(S,T),
i.e. F(S,T)= {x|f(x)=1}.

Given S from P(R), let
A_S = F(P(R)x{S}).

The collection {A_S| S in P(R)} is the desired partition of P(R). All the A_S are pairwise disjoint, |A_S|=|P(R)|, and P(R) = U (A_S) .

Can someone find a better bijection from Rx{1,2} to R ?
 
Last edited:
  • #34
f:R->{0,1}

f(x)=
(chi_S)(ln(x+1)) if x is a non-negative integer
(chi_S)(lnx) if x>0 and not and integer,
(chi_T)(ln(-x)) if x<0.

Yuck. Can someone think of a better one?
 
  • #35
What's so yuck about it?

Anyways, observe the following: if you split the real line up into two or more intervals, at least one of them must be either a closed or a half-open interval. Such intervals cannot be homeomorphic to R.

Your method looks like one of the standard tricks for creating a point out of "thin air", so I don't see why it's so yucky.


Anyways, thinking about yours did lead me to a different, cute example: split the real line into half open intervals
... + [-2, -1) + [-1, 0) + [0, 1) + [1, 2) + [2, 3) + ...
then do your favorite rearrangement of Z into two copies of Z.
 
Last edited:

1. What is the concept of splitting an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets?

The concept of splitting an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets is a mathematical concept that involves dividing an infinite set of objects into two groups, with each group having an equal number of objects. This is different from traditional division, where the total number of objects is finite.

2. Is it possible to split an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets?

Yes, it is possible to split an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets. This is because infinity is not a number, but rather a concept of endlessness. So, even if we divide an infinite set into two parts, each part will still have an infinite number of objects.

3. How can we determine if an infinite set has been split into two equal infinite subsets?

We can determine if an infinite set has been split into two equal infinite subsets by using a one-to-one correspondence. This means that we can match each object in one subset with an object in the other subset, without leaving any objects unmatched. If this is possible, then the set has been split into two equal infinite subsets.

4. Can an infinite set be split into more than two equal infinite subsets?

Yes, an infinite set can be split into more than two equal infinite subsets. This is because infinity is not a fixed number, but rather a concept of endlessness. So, we can divide an infinite set into any number of equal infinite subsets.

5. What are some real-world applications of splitting an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets?

Splitting an infinite set into two equal infinite subsets has applications in various fields such as computer science, physics, and economics. In computer science, it is used in algorithms for sorting and searching data. In physics, it is used in the concept of fractals and infinite series. In economics, it is used in game theory to analyze decision-making processes.

Similar threads

Replies
2
Views
315
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
1
Views
495
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
4
Views
1K
Replies
8
Views
1K
Replies
66
Views
4K
Replies
1
Views
908
Replies
18
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
1K
Back
Top