Is it possible for all truths to be known?

  • Thread starter lugita15
  • Start date
In summary, the conversation discusses different paradoxes that challenge our notions of truth and falsity, as well as other philosophical concepts such as knowledge, possibility, and morality. One of the most famous paradoxes, Fitch's Paradox of Knowability, is presented and raises the question of whether all true statements are knowable. The argument suggests that if one believes in the knowability of all truths, it leads to the absurd conclusion that all truths are already known. However, this hypothesis itself is questioned as it is based on the existence of unknown truths. The conversation ends with a desire for more paradoxes to be discussed and a question about how unknown truths can be considered true.
  • #36
lugita15 said:
No, contrary to popular belief Godel's theorem does NOT say there is a single statement that is undecidable in all sufficiently strong axiomatic systems.
Of course; the proof of this is trivial: given any undecidable statement P in a theory claimed to be absolutely undecidable, simply construct a new theory by adding P as an axiom. Contradiction!

Rather, it says that for each sufficiently strong axiomatic system, there exists a statement in that system, but easily decidable in other systems.
And, in particular, Godel's theorem applies to any (computable) scheme for constructing a sequence of progressively more inclusive axiomatic systems.

But don't forget we're talking about the informal notion of "known"; even if we assume there is a notion of objective truth, given our knowledge of incompleteness theorems, what sort of scheme could possibly produce any objective through and still be plausibly called "known"?

(the only loopholes I can imagine require some sort of temporal logic; e.g. depend on us having a non-deterministic oracle we have absolute faith into give us new "known" statements, which have a chance of producing any truth sometime in the future. But then, is that really plausible?)
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
lugita15 said:
Sure, I can go on to other ones. (And it's a he by the way.) But let me first explain my preferred resolution to Fitch's paradox. I came up with it on my own soon after reading about the paradox a while back, but then I later found out that Joseph Melia thought of more or less the same solution in 1991; see the attached paper. The key idea is this: Fitch's "argument presupposes that we can discover a statement's truth value without affecting that statement's truth value. But this is not so: there exist statements which are true, yet which would have been false had we performed the procedures necessary to discover that statement's truth value."

To illustrate this point, suppose for sake of argument that it were possible for someone to be omniscient (i.e. knowing literally everything) but that no one was actually omniscient. Now consider the statement "No one is omniscient." That would be a true statement. But could it be known? Well, since we're assuming that omniscience is possible, by definition it would be possible for someone to know literally all true statements. But in that case "no one is omniscient" would not be a true statement, so it obviously wouldn't be known. So the thesis "all truths are knowable" doesn't make much sense, only because if the truth value of some true statements were found out they would no longer be true, and thus no longer be in the set of statements people can know (because you can't know a false statement).

So how do we remedy that? Surely "all truths are knowable" does try to capture some sensible and debatable sentiment, namely the belief that there are no limits to human knowledge. A better way of expressing that sentiment, one that does not fall victim to Fitch's paradox, is to say, "all truths are verifiable" or to put it another way "the truth value of any statement is knowable". To put it in more formal language, "For all statements P, either P is knowable or not P is knowable." You might think that that's equivalent to "For true statements P, P is knowable and for all false statement P, not P is knowable." But that's not true. Because your knowledge of the truth value of P may change the truth value of P (e.g. "the statement "there is no light in the room" becomes false if you turn on the light to test whether there's any light in the room!). But the important point is that Fitch's paradox allows for the possibility that you can find out the truth value of any statement, and if that's the case then surely it does not put any limitations on human knowledge.

Does that make sense to everyone? If not, look at the attached paper, and if you still have questions I'm happy to try and clarify matters.

I do see where you're coming from. Allow me to tell you how it runs with me.

Your statement .. suppose for sake of argument that it were possible for someone to be omniscient (i.e. knowing literally everything) .. seems contradictory. I cannot believe that a person, with a limited brain, intelligence, life span, etc (i.e., finite), can ever literally know everything (i.e., infinite). Can you even imagine someone having infinite knowledge ? He would need an infinite space to put it all in, and probably, an infinite span of time to assimilate it - particularly given that new and further knowledge of infinitely more things and events would be coming up all the time.

Thus, the juxtaposition of 'person' and 'omniscient' in the real world, is to me nonsensical, and if I supposed it, would simultaneously suppose that anything flowing from it would be also.

We cannot take a term such as 'someone', i.e., a human being, and suppose upon him omniscience, because for a start, that is not the ordinary definition of a person. And BTW, I was interested to read on another thread, where a contributor was railing against too narrow a definition of words on these forums, another contributor pointed out that these forums rules require for words to be used only in accordance with their dictionary meaning. And in no dictionary will you find omniscience as a description of a normal person.

Now, I'm NOT trying to pull rules here - I'm sure I sail against the wind myself on the odd occasion. And I do like the odd flight of fancy myself. But it IS a flight of fancy to say 'suppose someone is omniscient'. No logical discourse can follow from that.

I personally believe that these paradoxes (certainly the one in question) arise from different folk attributing different meanings to words - a nuance here, an inflection there, a not so subtle leap of faith elsewhere .. before you know it - confusion and chaos.

But anyway, I do enjoy the interaction and thinking about these things, and by no means am I trying to assert a superiority of view here - I'm just sayin' how I see it.

PS - will read the one on #35 soon.
 
Last edited:
  • #38
alt said:
Your statement .. suppose for sake of argument that it were possible for someone to be omniscient (i.e. knowing literally everything) .. seems contradictory. I cannot believe that a person, with a limited brain, intelligence, life span, etc (i.e., finite), can ever literally know everything (i.e., infinite). Can you even imagine someone having infinite knowledge ? He would need an infinite space to put it all in, and probably, an infinite span of time to assimilate it - particularly given that new and further knowledge of infinitely more things and events would be coming up all the time.
It was just a hypothetical situation designed to illustrate my point. But if things like infinite knowledge trouble you, just imagine a simpler world in which there were, say, only 50 or a 100 truths to be known. Then surely you can imagine not all of the truths being known but it would be possible for you to learn all of them.
Thus, the juxtaposition of 'person' and 'omniscient' in the real world, is to me nonsensical, and if I supposed it, would simultaneously suppose that anything flowing from it would be also.
People use fantastical examples to illustrate logical or philosophical points all the time.
I personally believe that these paradoxes (certainly the one in question) arise from different folk attributing different meanings to words - a nuance here, an inflection there, a not so subtle leap of faith elsewhere .. before you know it - confusion and chaos.
That can't possibly be the case, at least not in the sense you're thinking of, because Fitch's paradox can be put into unambiguous symbolic language.
PS - will read the one on #35 soon.
I look forward to your thoughts on it. As I said, it's a pretty simple one, so hopefully we can settle it fairly quickly and move to yet another one.

By the way, did you read the Melia paper I attached in post #33?
 
  • #39
lugita15 said:
It was just a hypothetical situation designed to illustrate my point. But if things like infinite knowledge trouble you, just imagine a simpler world in which there were, say, only 50 or a 100 truths to be known. Then surely you can imagine not all of the truths being known but it would be possible for you to learn all of them.
It is again nonsensical, and takes us right back to the start. To know there are (say) 100 truths to be known, means that you must know they are truths, else, you couldn't call them truths - could you ? How could you call them truths up front if you didn't know they were that ?
Ergo they are not unknown truths, but known truths. Unless of course, you reply that you defer to a higher authority who knows they ARE truths even if you don't, in which case I go straight to that higher authority (but I don't think you're saying that).

People use fantastical examples to illustrate logical or philosophical points all the time.

Yes, using fantastical examples certainly does broadens the options, doesn’t it ? Did you have some examples of using fantastical examples to arrive at logical truths, other than by accident, or by the use of metaphor, parable, simile, etc ?

That can't possibly be the case, at least not in the sense you're thinking of, because Fitch's paradox can be put into unambiguous symbolic language.
I think it is very true (my earlier statement about fluid use of language). As an overt example, consider this;

Nothing is better than complete happiness in life. A strawberry ice cream cone is better than nothing. Therefore, a strawberry ice cream cone is better than complete happiness in life. But surely it isn't. So have we stumbled upon some deep metaphysical, paradoxical mystery here, or is it just fluid use of language - in this case, that word singularly least disabused of ambiguity, 'nothing' ?

Also, you mentioned symbolic language before. Do I have to learn a new language to 'grok' with you ? Modern English is a very fine and complex language - as good as any. I know it well, and you seem to be adequate in it :-)
To defer to a more obscure or symbolic language, hints of a dodge to me. Fitch's paradox must stand on it's own two feet as it were .. that being the language in which it's presented. And it still clearly to me, nothing more than word play. I repeat part of our earlier dialogue;

You said ; .. So to review, we started with the hypothesis that P is an unknown truth .."

I replied .. "But even at the start, that hypothesis seems a little shaky .."

Nothing further to this has really been added, so far as I can discern.Tell me - what do you really think Fitch's paradox is doing ? You said earlier that you heavily insisted it wasn't just a simple case of word play. So is it revealing some deep metaphysical truth ? Some new science ? Some unknown mystery or secret ? Some undiscovered incongruity in or of human existence, of knowledge... or WHAT ? I'd really like you to give me a specific answer to this question, and in the language we are presently using.

I look forward to your thoughts on it. As I said, it's a pretty simple one, so hopefully we can settle it fairly quickly and move to yet another one.

By the way, did you read the Melia paper I attached in post #33?

I will dowload it now.
 
  • #40
lugita15 said:
Now for another modal paradox. This one is pretty simple and unlike Fitch's paradox, where I heavily insisted that it wasn't just a simple case of word play, this one can more justifiably be called playing with words (although it can still be expressed in symbolic form). It goes as follows: Benjamin Franklin was the inventor of bifocals, glasses that correct for both near-sightedness and far-sightedness. And since he was the inventor of bifocals, e.g. Albert Einstein was not the inventor of bifocals. But we can readily imagine alternate histories in which all kinds of things happened, like the Confederates winning the civil war or Japan not attacking us on Pearl Harbor. Similarly, we can say that although Benjamin Franklin invented bifocals, he did not have to be; someone else could have done it instead. So we can say "It is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

So we can say "It is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

Again, some lassitude of, umm, 'crisp' word meaning here.

It WAS possible that BJ did not (or would not) invent bifocals. But he did as it turned out. So it is IMPOSSIBLE that BJ did not invent bifocals, because he DID.
 
  • #41
alt said:
It is again nonsensical, and takes us right back to the start. To know there are (say) 100 truths to be known, means that you must know they are truths, else, you couldn't call them truths - could you ? How could you call them truths up front if you didn't know they were that ?
It's easy. As a simple example, if I have a standard deck of cards, I know exactly one of the following statements is a truth:
  • The first card is the ace of spades
  • The second card is the ace of spades
  • The third card is the ace of spades
  • ...
And yet, I cannot identify any particular statement as being a truth.

If I didn't know the deck was standard, there is still exactly one truth among those statements, but I wouldn't even know that!
 
  • #42
alt said:
It is again nonsensical, and takes us right back to the start. To know there are (say) 100 truths to be known, means that you must know they are truths, else, you couldn't call them truths - could you ? How could you call them truths up front if you didn't know they were that ?
I'm not saying that you know that these specific 100 truths were there to be known. I'm just saying, consider a hypothetical world in which there were only a hundred truths to be known. In such a world, it might be easy for someone to know everything, but it might just happen to be the case that they don't know everything.
Yes, using fantastical examples certainly does broadens the options, doesn’t it ? Did you have some examples of using fantastical examples to arrive at logical truths, other than by accident, or by the use of metaphor, parable, simile, etc ?
I'm not using a fantastical example to PROVE a logical point. I'm using it to illustrate a logical point.
I think it is very true (my earlier statement about fluid use of language). As an overt example, consider this;

Nothing is better than complete happiness in life. A strawberry ice cream cone is better than nothing. Therefore, a strawberry ice cream cone is better than complete happiness in life. But surely it isn't. So have we stumbled upon some deep metaphysical, paradoxical mystery here, or is it just fluid use of language - in this case, that word singularly least disabused of ambiguity, 'nothing' ?
Yes, that is really just playing with words, because the word nothing is ambiguous. But Fitch's paradox is not just playing off of an ambiguity in this trivial sense.
Also, you mentioned symbolic language before. Do I have to learn a new language to 'grok' with you ? Modern English is a very fine and complex language - as good as any. I know it well, and you seem to be adequate in it :-)
To defer to a more obscure or symbolic language, hints of a dodge to me. Fitch's paradox must stand on it's own two feet as it were .. that being the language in which it's presented. And it still clearly to me, nothing more than word play.
But the thing is, English is full of ambiguities and vagaries, so you might assume that Fitch's paradox arose from one of those flaws of the English language. But in fact, Fitch's reasoning can be expressed in the language of symbolic logic, where there is no room for ambiguities or semantic tricks. I'm not asking you to learn the symbolic language (although it's not too hard to learn), just to trust me that the reasoning still works when you translate to the symbolic language, so Fitch's paradox is not as trivial as you might think.
I repeat part of our earlier dialogue;

You said ; .. So to review, we started with the hypothesis that P is an unknown truth .."

I replied .. "But even at the start, that hypothesis seems a little shaky .."

Nothing further to this has really been added, so far as I can discern.
But I've given you examples, like the number of hairs on Obama's head, which you've dismissed them as absurd. But the thing is, reductio ad absurdum doesn't mean that anything you feel is absurd should just be dismissed. The "absurd" part in the context of reductio ad absurdum means getting an actual contradiction, like a statement of the form "P and not P". Absurd in this logical context does not just mean anything you find wacky or silly.

And if you don't like my examples, what about Hurkyl's example of the playing cards in post #41?
Tell me - what do you really think Fitch's paradox is doing ? You said earlier that you heavily insisted it wasn't just a simple case of word play. So is it revealing some deep metaphysical truth ? Some new science ? Some unknown mystery or secret ? Some undiscovered incongruity in or of human existence, of knowledge... or WHAT ? I'd really like you to give me a specific answer to this question, and in the language we are presently using.
If Fitch's paradox had no resolution, then it would reduce the arguable statement "all truths are knowable", which conveys the sentiment that there are no limits to human knowledge, to the naive statement "all truths are known". Thus from the weak assumption that humans do not know all the truths they could know, Fitch's paradox would somehow be able to place fundamental barriers on the reach of human knowledge.

But at least in my opinion, the reasoning given in Melia's paper (which as I said I thought of independently) satisfactorily resolves Fitch's paradox. So in my view, all Fitch's paradox tells us is that the statement "all truths are knowable" is a bad way of representing the claim that there are no limits to human knowledge.
I will dowload it now.
OK, I look forward to hearing your thoughts on it.
 
  • #43
alt said:
So we can say "It is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

Again, some lassitude of, umm, 'crisp' word meaning here.

It WAS possible that BJ did not (or would not) invent bifocals. But he did as it turned out. So it is IMPOSSIBLE that BJ did not invent bifocals, because he DID.
OK, if that bothers you feel free to change all my instances of "it is possible" to "it was possible". That's not the important part of the reasoning.
 
  • #44
Hurkyl said:
It's easy. As a simple example, if I have a standard deck of cards, I know exactly one of the following statements is a truth:
  • The first card is the ace of spades
  • The second card is the ace of spades
  • The third card is the ace of spades
  • ...
And yet, I cannot identify any particular statement as being a truth.

If I didn't know the deck was standard, there is still exactly one truth among those statements, but I wouldn't even know that!
That's a good example!

By the way, have you had a chance to look at the paradox I outlined in post #35?
 
  • #45
lugita15 said:
That statement you quoted isn't a paradox at all. It's just an assumption used in the paradox.
We're not talking about you asserting "P is an unknown truth." Here is the logic of the paradox again.

We start with the assumption that there is some truth P which is unknown to you, but perhaps known to others. Now consider the statement Q, which says "P is a truth unknown to you." By assumption, Q is true. Now the question is, can Q be known to you? Well, suppose that Q were known to you. Then you would know the statement "P is a truth unknown to you". But if you knew that, you would know that P is true and that P is unknown to you, or in other words P would be both known to you and unknown to you, which is impossible. Thus the supposition that Q is known to you leads to a contradiction, and thus it is impossible for Q to be known to you, or in other words Q is unknowable to you. Thus we can disprove the thesis that all truths are knowable to you.

Sorry, If I missed something by not following the whole thread. But the thread looks like cycling around anyways. :)
lugita15 said:
assumption that there is some truth P which is unknown to you,but perhaps known to others.
Good, enough assumption, I accept that.
lugita15 said:
Now consider the statement Q, which says "P is a truth unknown to you." By assumption, Q is true.
Re-writing: Q = "There exist some truth P, which is unknown to you (but may be know to others". If this Re-writing is allowed, then
Q, just repeats our assumption. So, it must be true. (Because, Assumption means we take it to be true for granted)
lugita15 said:
Now the question is, can Q be known to you? Well, suppose that Q were known to you.
Well, Q = Our assumption. We got to know our assumption when working on a problem, don't we? :)
lugita15 said:
Then you would know the statement "P is a truth unknown to you"
Well, it was assumed, so we have been knowing it all way along.
lugita15 said:
But if you knew that, you would know that P is true and that P is unknown to you, or in other words P would be both known to you and unknown to you, which is impossible.
If I knew my assumption (which is what you are referring by the word 'that'), I would know that there exist some truth P, which is unknown to me. I would know nothing whatsoever about what the truth exactly is.
I can't understand how you jumped to the conclusion that P is known to me? The only thing known to me is my assumption, which states that there exist some truth P, which is unknown to me.
To my knowledge, P is just an unknown variable (like the x in algebra). I am yet to solve the puzzle and find out what particular truth P contains.

I am not a philosophy student, but just sometimes get interested in such things.
 
  • #46
lugita15 said:
I'm not saying that you know that these specific 100 truths were there to be known. I'm just saying, consider a hypothetical world in which there were only a hundred truths to be known. In such a world, it might be easy for someone to know everything, but it might just happen to be the case that they don't know everything. I'm not using a fantastical example to PROVE a logical point. I'm using it to illustrate a logical point. Yes, that is really just playing with words, because the word nothing is ambiguous. But Fitch's paradox is not just playing off of an ambiguity in this trivial sense. But the thing is, English is full of ambiguities and vagaries, so you might assume that Fitch's paradox arose from one of those flaws of the English language. But in fact, Fitch's reasoning can be expressed in the language of symbolic logic, where there is no room for ambiguities or semantic tricks. I'm not asking you to learn the symbolic language (although it's not too hard to learn), just to trust me that the reasoning still works when you translate to the symbolic language, so Fitch's paradox is not as trivial as you might think.But I've given you examples, like the number of hairs on Obama's head, which you've dismissed them as absurd. But the thing is, reductio ad absurdum doesn't mean that anything you feel is absurd should just be dismissed. The "absurd" part in the context of reductio ad absurdum means getting an actual contradiction, like a statement of the form "P and not P". Absurd in this logical context does not just mean anything you find wacky or silly.

And if you don't like my examples, what about Hurkyl's example of the playing cards in post #41? If Fitch's paradox had no resolution, then it would reduce the arguable statement "all truths are knowable", which conveys the sentiment that there are no limits to human knowledge, to the naive statement "all truths are known". Thus from the weak assumption that humans do not know all the truths they could know, Fitch's paradox would somehow be able to place fundamental barriers on the reach of human knowledge.

But at least in my opinion, the reasoning given in Melia's paper (which as I said I thought of independently) satisfactorily resolves Fitch's paradox. So in my view, all Fitch's paradox tells us is that the statement "all truths are knowable" is a bad way of representing the claim that there are no limits to human knowledge.

OK - I don't disagree with your view (underlined). Other than this, to comment any further on the above would only be repeating what we've discussed earlier.

I still maintain that I do not believe there is such a thing as an unkown truth - at least if not reduced to the absurd. I'm not deliberatley being obstinate about this - I really haven't seen any proof of any unknown truth here. Will try to address Hurkyl's post soon.
 
  • #47
lugita15 said:
OK, if that bothers you feel free to change all my instances of "it is possible" to "it was possible". That's not the important part of the reasoning.

The conclusion to this 'paradox' is that "it is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

My response was that it may have been possible at one time, but now it isn't, because manifestly, he did. So the conclusion is wrong.

It is IMPOSSIBLE that BF did not invent bifocals.
 
  • #48
alt said:
The conclusion to this 'paradox' is that "it is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

My response was that it may have been possible at one time, but now it isn't, because manifestly, he did. So the conclusion is wrong.

It is IMPOSSIBLE that BF did not invent bifocals.
And I told you, feel free to substitute "it was possible" for "it is possible".
 
  • #49
Wrt to Fitch's paradox we can just assume that all truths aren't necessarily knowable ... which seems to be a most reasonable assumption.
 
  • #50
ThomasT said:
Wrt to Fitch's paradox we can just assume that all truths aren't necessarily knowable ... which seems to be a most reasonable assumption.
But the thing is, even if there are unknowable truths, one would not expect so trivial a disproof of an arguable viewpoint like the belief that all truths are knowable. For my preferred resolution to this, see post #33 and the paper attached with that post.
 
  • #51
Hurkyl said:
It's easy. As a simple example, if I have a standard deck of cards, I know exactly one of the following statements is a truth:
  • The first card is the ace of spades
  • The second card is the ace of spades
  • The third card is the ace of spades
  • ...
And yet, I cannot identify any particular statement as being a truth.

Having set up the initial finite alternatives (standard deck) of course one of them is the ace of spades. There is nothing, no unknown truth here. You'll know it in up to 52 guesses. Similarly, I could make, say, 50,000 guesses about the number of hairs on Obamas head, and I'm sure I'd get it right.

If I didn't know the deck was standard, there is still exactly one truth among those statements, but I wouldn't even know that!

If you didn't know the deck was standard, how would you know if it contained an ace of spades ?
 
  • #52
lugita15 said:
And I told you, feel free to substitute "it was possible" for "it is possible".

I did - again, you said;

The conclusion to this 'paradox' is that "it is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

Wrong conclusion. It WAS possible that BF did not or would not invent bifocals (before he did so) but when he did invent bi focals, he invented them.

Therefore, it is now IMPOSSIBLE that BF did not invent bifocals.

Glad we got that sorted.

Next !
 
  • #53
I_am_learning said:
Sorry, If I missed something by not following the whole thread. But the thread looks like cycling around anyways. :)

Good, enough assumption, I accept that.

Re-writing: Q = "There exist some truth P, which is unknown to you (but may be know to others". If this Re-writing is allowed, then
Q, just repeats our assumption. So, it must be true. (Because, Assumption means we take it to be true for granted)

Well, Q = Our assumption. We got to know our assumption when working on a problem, don't we? :)

Well, it was assumed, so we have been knowing it all way along.

If I knew my assumption (which is what you are referring by the word 'that'), I would know that there exist some truth P, which is unknown to me. I would know nothing whatsoever about what the truth exactly is.
I can't understand how you jumped to the conclusion that P is known to me? The only thing known to me is my assumption, which states that there exist some truth P, which is unknown to me.
To my knowledge, P is just an unknown variable (like the x in algebra). I am yet to solve the puzzle and find out what particular truth P contains.

I am not a philosophy student, but just sometimes get interested in such things.

Underlined .. yep - that's part of what I've been trying to say all along. I think it arises from a degree of word play.
 
  • #54
alt said:
Having set up the initial finite alternatives (standard deck) of course one of them is the ace of spades. There is nothing, no unknown truth here. You'll know it in up to 52 guesses. Similarly, I could make, say, 50,000 guesses about the number of hairs on Obamas head, and I'm sure I'd get it right.

You're interchanging "asserting P to be true" with "knowing P to be true" here
 
  • #55
I_am_learning said:
Sorry, If I missed something by not following the whole thread. But the thread looks like cycling around anyways. :)

Good, enough assumption, I accept that.

Re-writing: Q = "There exist some truth P, which is unknown to you (but may be know to others". If this Re-writing is allowed, then
Q, just repeats our assumption. So, it must be true. (Because, Assumption means we take it to be true for granted)

Well, Q = Our assumption. We got to know our assumption when working on a problem, don't we? :)

Well, it was assumed, so we have been knowing it all way along.

If I knew my assumption (which is what you are referring by the word 'that'), I would know that there exist some truth P, which is unknown to me. I would know nothing whatsoever about what the truth exactly is.
I can't understand how you jumped to the conclusion that P is known to me? The only thing known to me is my assumption, which states that there exist some truth P, which is unknown to me.
To my knowledge, P is just an unknown variable (like the x in algebra). I am yet to solve the puzzle and find out what particular truth P contains.

I am not a philosophy student, but just sometimes get interested in such things.
Sorry, a lot of your confusion is because I didn't word things well enough. The "you" that I'm discussing the argument with is different from the "you" whose knowledge we're discussing. So instead of using "you", let me call the individual John, and let me restate the argument in that way.

Assume that the truth P is unknown to John. Let Q be the statement "P is a truth unknown to John." The question is, is Q knowable by John? Well, suppose Q were known to John. Then John would know that P is a truth unknown to him. But if he knew that P is a truth, that's the same as knowing P. So he would know P and he would know that P is a truth unknown to him. But if he knew P, then it would be incorrect to say that P is a truth unknown to him, so Q would be false, and you can't know a false statement. Thus from the supposition that Q were known to John we get a contradiction, so it must be impossible for John to know Q. Hence Q is a truth unknowable by John, and therefore not all truths are knowable to John. Now do you get it?
 
  • #56
alt said:
I still maintain that I do not believe there is such a thing as an unkown truth - at least if not reduced to the absurd. I'm not deliberatley being obstinate about this - I really haven't seen any proof of any unknown truth here. Will try to address Hurkyl's post soon.
You literally don't think there are any true statements that are unknown? Don't you think the results of the 2016 US Presidential election are unknown? When you flip a coin in the air, don't you think it's unknown which side it will land on?
 
  • #57
alt said:
Having set up the initial finite alternatives (standard deck) of course one of them is the ace of spades. There is nothing, no unknown truth here. You'll know it in up to 52 guesses. Similarly, I could make, say, 50,000 guesses about the number of hairs on Obamas head, and I'm sure I'd get it right.
Perhaps you'll know it after you check each one of your 52 guesses, but do you agree that right when your handed the deck you don't know which place the Ace of Spades is? So if the Ace of Spades is in the 10th place, then at that moment wouldn't "The Ace of Spades is in the 10th place" be an unknown truth?
 
  • #58
alt said:
I did - again, you said;

The conclusion to this 'paradox' is that "it is possible that Benjamin Franklin did not invent bifocals."

Wrong conclusion. It WAS possible that BF did not or would not invent bifocals (before he did so) but when he did invent bi focals, he invented them.

Therefore, it is now IMPOSSIBLE that BF did not invent bifocals.
How many times do I have to say this? You can change "it is possible" to "it was possible" if you want. That's not the important part of the logic. Let me change it myself, so there's no confusion.

Benjamin Franklin invented the bifocals. But we can imagine alternative histories, so we can say "It was possible for Ben Franklin to not have been the inventor of bifocals". And for any person X, we can say "It was possible for X to not have been the inventor of bifocals." For instance, X can be "William Shakespeare" or "The inventor of special relativity" or "The eighth president of the United States", etc. Thus we can let X = "the inventor of bifocals" and thus we reach the conclusion "It was possible for the inventor of the bifocals to not have been to inventor of the bifocals." But that seems absurd, because obviously the inventor of bifocals had to be the inventor of bifocals. How can you have the inventor of bifocals not be the inventor of bifocals?

Now do you understand the paradox?
 
  • #59
My gut feeling says that the resolution of the paradox is that the bifocals don't have to be invented, so assuming there is an inventor is a fallacy. However the way that it's worded makes the whole premise absurd

If the statement "it was possible for the inventor of the bifocals to not invent the bifocals" is a paradox, then the statement "it was possible for Benjamin Franklin to not invent the bifocals" is the exact same paradox, because Benjamin Franklin IS the inventor of the bifocals (so you can freely substitute 'inventor of the bifocals' for him).
 
  • #60
"The inventor of bifocals" is a well-defined* 'variable constant'.

The informal argument that "it is not necessary that X invented bifocals" makes critical use of X being a non-'variable' constant. Roughly speaking, it boils down to observing "X does not vary with 'the inventor of bifocals'", and therefore it is possible for "X" and "the inventor of bifocals" to be different.

The argument, of course, doesn't work if X is a constant that does vary along with 'the inventor of bifocals'.*: Ignoring the technicalities of whether there is an inventor and it is unique
 
  • #61
Hurkyl said:
"The inventor of bifocals" is a well-defined* 'variable constant'.

The informal argument that "it is not necessary that X invented bifocals" makes critical use of X being a non-'variable' constant. Roughly speaking, it boils down to observing "X does not vary with 'the inventor of bifocals'", and therefore it is possible for "X" and "the inventor of bifocals" to be different.

The argument, of course, doesn't work if X is a constant that does vary along with 'the inventor of bifocals'.
Congratulations Hurkyl, you solved it! The technical way to say this is that in modal logic, you can only freely subsitute "rigid designators" into the modal operators.
 
  • #62
lugita15 said:
Sorry, a lot of your confusion is because I didn't word things well enough. The "you" that I'm discussing the argument with is different from the "you" whose knowledge we're discussing. So instead of using "you", let me call the individual John, and let me restate the argument in that way.

Assume that the truth P is unknown to John. Let Q be the statement "P is a truth unknown to John." The question is, is Q knowable by John? Well, suppose Q were known to John. Then John would know that P is a truth unknown to him. But if he knew that P is a truth, that's the same as knowing P. So he would know P and he would know that P is a truth unknown to him. But if he knew P, then it would be incorrect to say that P is a truth unknown to him, so Q would be false, and you can't know a false statement. Thus from the supposition that Q were known to John we get a contradiction, so it must be impossible for John to know Q. Hence Q is a truth unknowable by John, and therefore not all truths are knowable to John. Now do you get it?

No .. I gets me P's & Q's mixed up. Can you try it again with a real example ?

Will read the rest of your posts soon. All look very interesting and worthwile, mind.
 
  • #63
alt said:
No .. I gets me P's & Q's mixed up. Can you try it again with a real example ?
Sure. John's coat is in his closet, but he doesn't know it. So "the coat is in the closet", which we'll call P, is a truth unknown to John. So let Q="P is a truth unknown to John". Then Q is certainly a true statement, because in fact P IS a truth unknown to John. With me so far?

Now the question, is Q knowable by John? Well, that's the same asking, can John know that P is a truth unknown to John? And more concretely, that's the same as asking, can John know that the statement that the coat is in the closet is a truth unknown to him? Or equivalently, can John know that it is true that the coat is in the closet and know that the statement that the coat is in the closet is unknown to him? Or in other words, can John know that the coat is in the closet and know that he does not know that the coat is in the closet? And the answer to the last rephrasing of the question is obviously No, because if he knew the coat was in the closet, then it would be wrong to say that he does not know that the coat is in the closet, so the statement "John does not know that the coat is in the closet" is false, and it's impossible to know a false statement. Thus the answer to the initial question, is Q knowable by John, is also No. So not all truths are knowable by John.

When I write it out like that in words, I'm afraid it will sound too confusing, which is why I wrote it using lots of P's and Q's before. I hope this helps.
 
  • #64
hi lugita,
Thanks for the clarification.
Lets assume john doesn't know sun rises in the east.
Now , can john know that "he doesn't know that sun rises in the east"?
No. Because that is a paradoxical sentence. Ah! I see it now.
P = Sun rises in east.
Q = I/jhon don't know P.
Jhon don't know thousands of truth. He may know lot of them later. But for now Q is truth. Suppose Jhon searches really hard to know all truths. He may eventually know P but not Q because knowing P (or trying to know Q) makes Q false.
So Q will rather be destroyed than being known to john.
But jhon may know R = "Q was a truth."
But its not same as knowing Q.
Things are making sense. So, where is the paradox?
 
Last edited:
  • #65
I_am_learning said:
hi lugita,
Thanks for the clarification.
Lets assume john doesn't know sun rises in the east.
Now , can john know that "he doesn't know that sun rises in the east"?
No. Because that is a paradoxical sentence. Ah! I see it now.
P = Sun rises in east.
Q = I/jhon don't know P.
Jhon don't know thousands of truth. He may know lot of them later. But for now Q is truth. Suppose Jhon searches really hard to know all truths. He may eventually know P but not Q because knowing P (or trying to know Q) makes Q false.
So Q will rather be destroyed than being known to john.
Exactly, you see the solution! By knowing P, John makes Q false, so he cannot know that Q is true, because it's not. But he can know that Q is false. So the only reason Fitch's paradox says there are unknowable truths is that there are some truths that become false as soon as you find out their truth value, so you can never know them to be true, but you can know them to be false.

If you look at my post #33, you'll see that I discussed exactly this resolution to Fitch's paradox. See the attached paper by Joseph Melia in that post.
 
  • #66
lugita15 said:
You literally don't think there are any true statements that are unknown? Don't you think the results of the 2016 US Presidential election are unknown? When you flip a coin in the air, don't you think it's unknown which side it will land on?

Earlier in a post you said;
People use fantastical examples to illustrate logical or philosophical points all the time.

Very well. Let's do a bit of that.

The election might never happen as you think it would. The anarchist party might take over, or any other political upheaval might occur that would prevent them.
(In fact, this is not nearly so fantastical)

The coin might fall down a drain in the pavement - or any other similar possibility.
(Not too fantastical, either)

The ace of clubs - before you examined the deck, it might be vapourized by some explosion - imagine you were in the Twin Towers just as you were about to examine it.
(A little more fantastical, but hey, I'm no 911 denier)

All above three, therefore, cannot be called unknown truths with 100% certainty.

I still maintain that 'unknown truth' is an oxymoron - to the one observer.

Sure, my 2 year old niece doesn't know I have a 4 litre motor in my car, but if we go down that path, we are again skating on the trivial, which I can reduce to absurd infinities - as discussed earlier.
 
  • #67
lugita15 said:
Perhaps you'll know it after you check each one of your 52 guesses, but do you agree that right when your handed the deck you don't know which place the Ace of Spades is? So if the Ace of Spades is in the 10th place, then at that moment wouldn't "The Ace of Spades is in the 10th place" be an unknown truth?

See my above post.
 
  • #68
lugita15 said:
Sure. John's coat is in his closet, but he doesn't know it ..

But you do, in order to make the statement. Therefore, it is a known truth, and all John has to do is ask you.

But to use another fantastical example to illustrate a logical point - as you have allowed earlier, it might not even be there when he opens the closet. Someone might have stolen it. Or the cat might have pulled it through a crack in the floor. So YOU might even be wrong in your assumption of a KNOW truth, never mind Johns unknown truth.
 
  • #69
alt said:
Earlier in a post you said;
People use fantastical examples to illustrate logical or philosophical points all the time.
And I meant it.
Very well. Let's do a bit of that.
All right, but I don't see what logical or philosophical point you're trying to illustrate.
The election might never happen as you think it would. The anarchist party might take over, or any other political upheaval might occur that would prevent them.
Yes, all of these are possible. But isn't it still true that either "Barack Obama will win the 2016 US Presidential Election" or "Barack Obama will not win the 2016 US Presidential Election" is an unknown truth?
The coin might fall down a drain in the pavement - or any other similar possibility.
Yes, but isn't it still true that either "the coin landed heads" or "the coin did not land heads" is an unknown truth?
The ace of clubs - before you examined the deck, it might be vapourized by some explosion - imagine you were in the Twin Towers just as you were about to examine it.
OK, but either "the Ace of Clubs was the 10th card in the deck" or "the Ace of Clubs was not the 10th card in the deck" was an unknown truth, correct?
All above three, therefore, cannot be called unknown truths with 100% certainty.
I'm not saying that there is a particular statement that we know to be an unknown truth. All I'm talking about is whether we know that there EXISTS an unknown truth. Don't you think "The Earth goes around the Sun" was an unknown truth in ancient times? Don't you think the Pythagorean theorem was an unknown truth in even more ancient times? Don't you think there are similar truths unknown to us, both trivial and profound?

And by the way, we are discussing logic, where truths both trivial and profound are treated on equal footing.
I still maintain that 'unknown truth' is an oxymoron - to the one observer.
To say "No truths are unknown" is the same as saying "all truths are known". Do you really believe that all truths are known, i.e. we are omniscient?
Sure, my 2 year old niece doesn't know I have a 4 litre motor in my car, but if we go down that path, we are again skating on the trivial, which I can reduce to absurd infinities - as discussed earlier.
The example of your niece is a perfectly good one. I don't know why you dismiss things for being trivial. What's wrong with trivial examples, fantastical examples, sensible-sounding examples, or anything else. In logic we talk about all kinds of examples.

And I still think what you're saying about "reducing to absurd infinities" makes no sense. Yes, we can find infinitely many examples of unknown truths, but so what? Just because we can find infinitely many examples of some notion does not mean that there is something wrong with the notion, does it? We can find infinitely many examples of truths, so does truth not make sense? We can find infinitely many examples of falsehoods, so does falsehood not make sense? We can find infinitely many examples of English sentence, so does English not make sense? We can find infinitely many examples of prime numbers, so do prime numbers not make sense?
 
  • #70
alt said:
But you do, in order to make the statement.
Count me out of it. I don't know that there's a coat in the closet. I'm just supposing that "the coat is in the closet" is an unknown true statement, and I am deducing the consequences of that assumption.
Therefore, it is a known truth, and all John has to do is ask you.
First of all, the "John" formulation of Fitch's paradox is a restricted version of the paradox I made up to satisfy disregardthat's objections earlier in the thread. The point of this restricted version is just to prove that "not all truths are knowable by John". So the assumption for this restricted version is just "there exists a truth unknown to John", not the more general assumption "there exists an unknown truth". So even it was known to me that the coat is in the closet, it would still be unknown to John, which is what's relevant.

But in the more general version of the paradox, the statement we're proving is "there is an unknowable truth" and the assumption is "there is an unknown truth". So in that case the truth can still be "the coat is in the closet", but this time no one knows this.
But to use another fantastical example to illustrate a logical point - as you have allowed earlier, it might not even be there when he opens the closet. Someone might have stolen it. Or the cat might have pulled it through a crack in the floor.
Sure, but when the coat was in the closet, wasn't it an unknown truth that the coat was in the closet?
So YOU might even be wrong in your assumption of a KNOW truth, never mind Johns unknown truth.
Sure I may be wrong that the coat is in the closet. But assuming it is in the closet, that is a truth is unknown to John, and assuming it's not in the closet, THAT is a truth unknown to John. Either way, isn't there a truth unknown to John?

But let me go to the very first example of an unknown truth I presented in this thread: either the Riemann hypothesis (see here) is true or it is false. Either way, isn't one of these statements an unknown truth?

By the way, have you read the paper by Joseph Melia I attached in post #33?
 
Last edited:
<h2>1. What is a modal paradox?</h2><p>A modal paradox is a logical contradiction that arises when considering the relationship between modal statements, which express possibility and necessity, and the actual state of affairs.</p><h2>2. Can you give an example of a modal paradox?</h2><p>One example of a modal paradox is the Barber Paradox, which states that in a village, there is a barber who shaves all and only those men who do not shave themselves. The paradox arises when considering whether the barber should shave himself or not.</p><h2>3. How do modal paradoxes challenge traditional logical principles?</h2><p>Modal paradoxes challenge traditional logical principles by showing that there are situations where seemingly valid logical principles, such as the principle of non-contradiction, lead to contradictory conclusions. This calls into question the reliability of these principles in all situations.</p><h2>4. What is the significance of modal paradoxes in philosophy and science?</h2><p>Modal paradoxes have significant implications in both philosophy and science. In philosophy, they challenge our understanding of logic and the nature of reality. In science, they can lead to new insights and discoveries, as they force us to question our assumptions and consider alternative possibilities.</p><h2>5. How can modal paradoxes be resolved?</h2><p>There is no one definitive way to resolve modal paradoxes, as different approaches have been proposed by philosophers and logicians. Some argue that the paradoxes arise due to a misunderstanding of the concepts of possibility and necessity, while others suggest revising traditional logical principles. Ultimately, resolving modal paradoxes requires careful analysis and consideration of different perspectives.</p>

1. What is a modal paradox?

A modal paradox is a logical contradiction that arises when considering the relationship between modal statements, which express possibility and necessity, and the actual state of affairs.

2. Can you give an example of a modal paradox?

One example of a modal paradox is the Barber Paradox, which states that in a village, there is a barber who shaves all and only those men who do not shave themselves. The paradox arises when considering whether the barber should shave himself or not.

3. How do modal paradoxes challenge traditional logical principles?

Modal paradoxes challenge traditional logical principles by showing that there are situations where seemingly valid logical principles, such as the principle of non-contradiction, lead to contradictory conclusions. This calls into question the reliability of these principles in all situations.

4. What is the significance of modal paradoxes in philosophy and science?

Modal paradoxes have significant implications in both philosophy and science. In philosophy, they challenge our understanding of logic and the nature of reality. In science, they can lead to new insights and discoveries, as they force us to question our assumptions and consider alternative possibilities.

5. How can modal paradoxes be resolved?

There is no one definitive way to resolve modal paradoxes, as different approaches have been proposed by philosophers and logicians. Some argue that the paradoxes arise due to a misunderstanding of the concepts of possibility and necessity, while others suggest revising traditional logical principles. Ultimately, resolving modal paradoxes requires careful analysis and consideration of different perspectives.

Similar threads

  • General Discussion
Replies
4
Views
485
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
9
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
17
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
10
Views
3K
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
2
Replies
39
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
9
Replies
309
Views
8K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
16
Views
2K
Replies
4
Views
3K
Replies
5
Views
842
Back
Top