Dedekind's Axiom: Exploring its Fundamentals & Contradiction

  • Thread starter Canute
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Axiom
In summary, the conversation discusses Dedekind's axiom, which is a fundamental axiom in mathematics and states that if all points on a straight line can be divided into two classes, then there exists one unique point that produces this division. This axiom is used in Euclidean geometry and is also a part of the definition of real numbers. The conversation also addresses a potential self-contradiction in the axiom, but it is clarified that the dividing point can belong in either class and it is a formal convention in the construction of the real number line.
  • #1
Canute
1,568
0
Not sure if this is the place to ask this. It concerns Dedekind's axiom. Quoting from Dantzig this says:

"If all points of a straight line fall into two classes, such that every point of the first class lies to the left of any point of the second class, then there exists one and only one point which produces this division of all points into two classes, this severing of the straight line into two portions"

Two questions -

1. Is this still a fundamental axiom in some or all forms of mathematics?
2. How is the inherent self-contradiction resolved?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
What inherent self-contradiction? Suppose you have the real line, and you divide it into one class (-infinity, 0) and [0, infinity) then 0 is the one and only one point which produces the division.
 
  • #3
This axiom is one of Hilbert's axioms for Euclidean geometry.

The algebraic version of Dedekind's axiom is part of the definition of the real numbers: it's the complete part of "The real numbers form a complete ordered field".

And I'll echo AKG: I have no idea what you mean by "inherent self-contradiction".
 
  • #4
There are various completeness axioms for the real numbers. Dedekind's was AFAIK the first. They all imply each other, so you could say correctly that yes, Dedekind's axiom is still a part of mathematics, either as an axiom itself or a true theorem from other axioms. And Canute, what again is that "inherent contradiction"?
 
  • #5
Thanks, that's very clear. The contradiction I referred to is that in the first part of the axiom, as given, it is stated that all points on the line fall into two classes, while the second part states that there is another point that does not belong in either class. I don't see how both these statements can be true.
 
  • #6
it doesn't state that the dividing point does not lie in either subset.
 
  • #7
Doesn't it? To me it does. The axiom clearly states that there are two categories of points and that all points belong in one of these two categories. But then it immediately contradicts this rule and clearly states that there is a third category of point. I can't see how there can be both two and three categories of points. What am I misunderstanding here?

Does it say - there are two mutually exclusive categories of points, but these categories overlap, and where they overlap there is a point that belongs in both categories? This also seems self-contradictory to me. Surely there are three categories of points according to the axiom, however one reads it? :confused:
 
Last edited:
  • #8
Because you're misreading it. there is nothing there that states the point of division is in the left or right hand set, or that it cannot be in either. which is not surprising. it states that any divisoin of the real line is of the form

(-inf,x) [x,inf)

or

(-inf,x] (x,inf)

and that the x is unique.
 
  • #9
So does the dividing point belong in the first class or the second class?
 
  • #10
That would depend upon the division as i indicated above.
 
  • #11
I'm trying understand this, but genuinely can't grasp how it is possible for the axiom to state that point x is unique having just stated that no point is unique. This problem shows up in your symbolic representation, since this shows point x as being either divided down the middle, in which case it is not a point; in both classes at the same time, in which case the classes are not mutually exclusive after all; or shows two different x's, in which case x is not unique. How can a unique individual be in two classes that are defined as mutually exclusive at the same time? I'm afraid I can't make sense of that yet.
 
  • #12
what? do you understand the notation?

(-inf,x) means the x is not included [x,inf) means the x is included. this is one way to divide into two classes

(-inf,x] and (x,inf) means the x is in the first class and not the second. These are the two options (and the only two).
 
  • #13
Ah yes, I misunderstood that. You probably have no idea how little mathematics some people do! So x can be thought of as being in either class as long as it's in one or the other? But in this case how can it be said that x divides the classes? Say I represent the line of points as 1,2,3,4,5. Say that 1 & 2 are in the first class and 3,4 & 5 are in the second class. Does x = 2 or x =3, or is it an arbitrary choice?

It seems to me that if x is in the first class then the division between the classes occurs to the right of x, and if x is in the second class then the division is to the left of x. In neither case does x represent the point of division between the classes. Would it be right to say that the axiom is a formal convention and that this ambiguity is therefore not important? Or am I still seeing an ambiguity where there isn't one?
 
  • #14
You have chosen an entirely different number line to what Dedekind's Axiom is defined on. Dedekind's Axiom is defined on the real number line and it is a way of helping construct the Real number line which isn't as easy as it sounds.

Now here we can compare integers to the real number line, say you have the division in the integers: (-inf, 0] and [1, inf) or we could write this as (-inf, 1) and [1, inf) or we could even write this (-inf, 0] and (0, inf). As you can see, there is no single point that is the division.

However if we look a real number division: (-inf, 1) and [1, inf), as we see here the point 1 is the unique point where there is a division, it's quite important to note here that unlike in the integers there is no other way of writing this.
 
Last edited:
  • #15
Does it make a difference what sort of line it is? I assumed it is a line of points, seeing as this is what the axiom says it is. Is it not this? If it is a line of points then how we name them is entirely arbitrary. They can be represented a 1,2,3,4,5... or a,b,c,d,e, ... or anything at all. Surely they're just the names we use to distinguish the different points so we can talk about them?

I'm not worried about formalisms here. Of course within mathematics the axiom is not problematic. My question is meta-mathematical, which I forgot to say earlier, and asks whether the axiom can be applied to, say, a line of apples.
 
  • #16
Think geometrically. Which of the following is a line:

. . . . . . . . . . .

or

______________

The first is just a bunch of dots and we'd say that they're in line or they're in a line, but the dots themselves don't form a line. The second thing is a line.
 
  • #17
Canute said:
Does it make a difference what sort of line it is? I assumed it is a line of points, seeing as this is what the axiom says it is. Is it not this? If it is a line of points then how we name them is entirely arbitrary. They can be represented a 1,2,3,4,5... or a,b,c,d,e, ... or anything at all. Surely they're just the names we use to distinguish the different points so we can talk about them?

I'm not worried about formalisms here. Of course within mathematics the axiom is not problematic. My question is meta-mathematical, which I forgot to say earlier, and asks whether the axiom can be applied to, say, a line of apples.

Dedekind's axiom exactly distinguishes the real line from, say, the rational numbers, it shows that all convergent sequences have a limit, that is its whole raison d'etre! It doesn't apply to the rationals, or the integers, it is a completeness axiom! For example, the classes: S whcih is the set of positive raitonal numbers whose square is greater than two, and its complement in the rationals are a divisoin of the rationals into two distinct classes alll the elements of one lying to the left of all the elements of the other yet there is no rational number that splits the rationals into those two classes.
 
  • #18
AKG said:
Think geometrically. Which of the following is a line:

. . . . . . . . . . .

or

______________

The first is just a bunch of dots and we'd say that they're in line or they're in a line, but the dots themselves don't form a line. The second thing is a line.
Well, this is just my problem. The axiom states of itself that it applies to a line made of points, or a line of points. Yet a line of points does not seem able to behave in the way the axiom states. If the axiom defines a continuous line by stating that it's a series of points then I will be confused, but assume that the contradiction involved is down to the difficulty of representing the continuous mathematically. Is that it?

For example, the classes: S whcih is the set of positive raitonal numbers whose square is greater than two, and its complement in the rationals are a divisoin of the rationals into two distinct classes alll the elements of one lying to the left of all the elements of the other yet there is no rational number that splits the rationals into those two classes.
That seems ok to me, since you do not state anywhere that there is a unique rational dividing the two classes. What I can't handle is the word 'all' at the start of the axiom. If all means all then where does the unique dividing point come from?

In oversimplified terms is the axiom saying that between any two points there is another point? That's my naive reading of it. Or is it not a stand alone axiom, and so perhaps my problem stems from not knowing the others that go with it?

But maybe I need to understand what an axiom of completeness is. I know this is painfully elementary but could you briefly explain? Sorry to be a bore but I want to understand this. After what's been said I'm not even sure now whether the axiom defines a series of points or a continuum, even though I started out taking it at face value, as the former.
 
  • #19
an axiom is just an axiom, for instance the axiom

G contains a unique element e such that e*x=x*e=x for all x

is an axiom from group theory.

it itself has no truth value and is only true of false when applied to some G and *.

here dedekind's axiom is not true in and of itself or true for all "lines". it only makes sense to say it is true or false when applied to something. and it is true for the real line and false fro the rationals. the reals are complete (all cauchy sequences have a limit) and the rationals aren't, ie it is possible to find a sequence of rationals increasing and bounded above that do not converge to a rational.


the axiom states that if we define two classes of elements of the reals, one allto the left of the other that this is the same as picking a unique point of division.

thus the example i gave abuot the positive rationals whose square is bigger than 2 and its complement divide the line into two parts, but there is no rational that is the point of divisoin.

another way is this: if we define two classes dividing the line up then we an take the sup of the left hand one and the inf of the right hand one and these agree, and that this element is in either the left or right hand sets.
 
Last edited:
  • #20
all is all, and if is if.
 
  • #21
another way is this: if we define two classes dividing the line up then we an take the sup of the left hand one and the inf of the right hand one and these agree, and that this element is in either the left or right hand sets
So is the dividing point both the sup of the LH class and the inf of the RH class, or is it just one of them? If so which one? But there's no need to answer that, the axiom still makes no sense to me but I've probably pushed your patience far enough. At the moment I rather agree with bao ho, but I'll go away and do some reading around it. Sorry to be so dense but thanks for your help.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
It's both the sup of the LH class and the inf of the RH class. I can't understand how this axiom is troubling you. For one, did you even see what matt wrote about axioms? They're axioms. It's not a statement of a law of nature. If I define a word "spen" as a pen that has a mismatched cap, will you say, "that definition makes no sense to me?" Dedekind's axiom helps to define the reals, so the reals are by definition, some set of numbers that is, put briefly, complete. So I hope you don't disagree that the Reals are complete, since that wouldn't make sense. Do you just not understand what it means to be complete? What is it that's so confusing?

Suppose you have the integers. If you cut the integer line at the point 2.5, then you'll split the integers into two classes, the class A = {..., -3, -2, -1, 0, 1, 2} and the class B = {3, 4, 5, ...}. Here, every point of class A is to the left of class B. However, if you divided the line at 2.75, you'd have the same two classes, but with a different dividing point. So the integers are not complete. In the case of the reals, is it evident to you that any splitting of the Reals into two classes such that all of one class is less than all of the other must split in one of the following two ways:

(-infinity, x) and [x, infinity)

or

(-infinity, x] and (x, infinity)

Is it also not obvious to you that in these cases, there is one and only one dividing point, and that point is x?
 
  • #23
Canute said:
So is the dividing point both the sup of the LH class and the inf of the RH class, or is it just one of them? If so which one? But there's no need to answer that, the axiom still makes no sense to me but I've probably pushed your patience far enough. At the moment I rather agree with bao ho, but I'll go away and do some reading around it. Sorry to be so dense but thanks for your help.
They're both the same uniquie dividing point!

bao_ho's post makes no sense other than referring to the definition of the words!
 
  • #24
one thing about AKG's post is that to "split the integers to the left and right of 2.75" assumes thart such as thing as 2.75 exists, but it may not, well it does, but we dont' know that, or more accurately the completeness axiom doesn't say what does or deosn't exist. It may be that *nothing* satisfies the completeness axiom. As we can show there is something that does satisfy the axiom.


ok to be honest i *wanted* to use this kind of example but thought of the several ontological issues. actually the integers are a bad example to use since in any reasonable sense they are complete since a cauchy sequence is eventually constant and hence converges. but the integers aren't a field.

let's assume that we konw the reals exist and the rationals are inside them


define a splitting of Q via L as the rationals less than pi and R as the rationals greater than pi.

sup(L) and inf(L) are not in Q, there is no rational that is the cut point. the rationals are not complete.

what is hard about this?
 
  • #25
matt grime said:
one thing about AKG's post is that to "split the integers to the left and right of 2.75" assumes thart such as thing as 2.75 exists, but it may not, well it does, but we dont' know that, or more accurately the completeness axiom doesn't say what does or deosn't exist. It may be that *nothing* satisfies the completeness axiom. As we can show there is something that does satisfy the axiom.

ok to be honest i *wanted* to use this kind of example but thought of the several ontological issues. actually the integers are a bad example to use since in any reasonable sense they are complete since a cauchy sequence is eventually constant and hence converges. but the integers aren't a field.
I thought of this too, but I don't see how it's a bad example. As Canute is having trouble grasping this simple axiom, I figured that this example would be more instructive even if it isn't technically that good. Is he going to know what a Cauchy sequence, or even a field is?

Also, if it's bad to split the integers by 2.75, then it's bad to split the rationals by pi. I think if you wanted, you could introduce surreal numbers and split the reals into classes where the splitting point is not in the reals.
 
  • #26
The difference between the rationals and the integers is that the integers are complete. You need at least the rationals for this to make sense.

I can split the rationals by sqrt(2) without mentioning the 'ambient' space of reals. as i have done several times by example. Really we must only define our split by reference to the underlying space, so i can state things like the integers n such that 2n<5 but even then the sup exists over the integers and is an element of the left hadn set.

The rational example I gave was the positive rationals x suich that x^2>2 and its complement in the rationals. there is no rational splitting point.

if you don't know about cuachy sequences or completeness what is the point of dedekind's axiom? (this isn't rhetorical: i never learned abuot the construction of the reals until i had to teach it. if you like it was something we never mentioned as a student and by the time i realized (teaching at a different place) that it wasn't obvious it was too late...)
 
  • #27
I'm aware of what an axiom is. My query is not whether this axiom applies to reality or not, that doesn't matter. But it appears to me, even now, that it is internally inconsistent. In the example dividing the integers, 2.5 was said to be the dividing point, but 2.5 is not a member of the two classes being divided so this does not seem to be an equivalent case.

What you all seem to be saying is that the axiom does not stand alone but assumes certain other prior axioms, so is my problem that I'm reading it in isolation from these? I'm reading it naively, as a stand-alone statement about a line of points and the nature of the number line.

Zurtex - "They're both the same unique dividing point!"
This is what I thought was being said, but to me it seems an oxymoronic statement.
 
Last edited:
  • #28
Canute said:
I'm aware of what an axiom is. My query is not whether this axiom applies to reality or not, that doesn't matter. But it appears to me, even now, that it is internally inconsistent. In the example dividing the integers, 2.5 was said to be the dividing point, but 2.5 is not a member of the two classes being divided so this does not seem to be an equivalent case.

What you all seem to be saying is that the axiom does not stand alone but assumes certain other prior axioms, so is my problem that I'm reading it in isolation from these? I'm reading it naively, as a stand-alone statement about a line of points and the nature of the number line.
I still don't get what's troubling you. Where is the internal inconsistency? To me, the axiom does seem to be lacking a little, but I don't see it as inconsistent. The axioms says that if you split a line into a left half and a right half, that there exists a unique dividing point. What confuses you? That there exists a dividing point, or that this point is unique?
 
  • #29
Canute said:
I'm aware of what an axiom is. My query is not whether this axiom applies to reality or not, that doesn't matter. But it appears to me, even now, that it is internally inconsistent. In the example dividing the integers, 2.5 was said to be the dividing point, but 2.5 is not a member of the two classes being divided so this does not seem to be an equivalent case.

What you all seem to be saying is that the axiom does not stand alone but assumes certain other prior axioms, so is my problem that I'm reading it in isolation from these? I'm reading it naively, as a stand-alone statement about a line of points and the nature of the number line.

Zurtex - "They're both the same unique dividing point!"
This is what I thought was being said, but to me it seems an oxymoronic statement.

The axiom says the two sets exhaust the reals, i.e. every real number is in one set or the other. And every number in B is greater than every number in A. So the cut will be a member of B, less than every OTHER member of B, but sharing the B property of being greater than every number of A.

Consider A the set of numbers whose squares are less than 2. And let B be the complement of A, consisting of all other numbers. Then the axiom says there is a LEAST member of B, call it c, characterized by a < c < b, for any member a in A and other b in B. This number c then has square = 2. For it is not in A so its square is not less than 2, and if its square were greater than 2, there would be some other number whose square was equal to 2, and then that number would be in B, not A, and would be less than c. But c is the least member of B, so that's a contradiction.
 
  • #30
selfAdjoint, the cut point could be a member of A. Also, the set A of numbers whose square is less than 2 is (-sqrt(2), sqrt(2)). This divides the reals into 3.
 
  • #31
Canute said:
I'm aware of what an axiom is.

you say this but you appear not to understand it

My query is not whether this axiom applies to reality or not, that doesn't matter. But it appears to me, even now, that it is internally inconsistent. In the example dividing the integers, 2.5 was said to be the dividing point, but 2.5 is not a member of the two classes being divided so this does not seem to be an equivalent case.

and the axiom is false for the rationals. this example was supposed to show you why it applies to the real numbers and not other sets of numbers that happen to form a line.

What you all seem to be saying is that the axiom does not stand alone but assumes certain other prior axioms,

no, it may stand alone as may any axiom, but it only becomes meanignful to see if for some mathematical objesct the axiom is true for it. here is anothe example (axiom of algebraic completeness) a field k is algebraicaly closed if every polynomial p(x) with coefficients in k has a root in k. This axiom is true for the complex numbers but false for the real numbers.

so is my problem that I'm reading it in isolation from these? I'm reading it naively, as a stand-alone statement about a line of points and the nature of the number line.

read it however you will but the important point is that the reals (being complete) are such that the axiom is true for them, The rationals it is not true for. is that clear?
 
  • #32
You say that this axiom applies to this sort of number and not that sort of number and so on, but the axiom does not mention numbers at all, it mentions only points. You've told me that the axiom does not require any supporting axioms. In this case why are we talking about numbers and not points? Points cannot be distinguished from one another as if they were reals and rationals.

Let's say we wanted to represent time mathematically, as a series of moments or points in time. If we have to apply Dedekind's axiom in order to do this then we have to say that all moments fall into one of two classes, with every moment in the first class lying in the past relative to any point in the second class. But in which class does the present moment belong? It hardly matters whether we call these points in time real or rational numbers, we could represent them by the letters of the alphabet if we wanted.

This is the issue I'm delving into. This is why I said I wasn't quite sure the question belongs here, thinking it might belong in philosophy of mathematics. I'm happy to move it there if you think that's a better place for it.
 
  • #33
Canute said:
You say that this axiom applies to this sort of number and not that sort of number and so on, but the axiom does not mention numbers at all, it mentions only points. You've told me that the axiom does not require any supporting axioms. In this case why are we talking about numbers and not points? Points cannot be distinguished from one another as if they were reals and rationals.

becuase the whole raison' d'etre of dedekind's axiom, along with dedekind cuts, is to define properly the real numbers. i thought you were attempting to understand what or where it came from and "what it applies to" and as such were aware of its implications in the construction of the real numbers. we are trying to illustrate its implications by example, indeed the only example that is important. creating the dedekind cuts from the set or rationals creates a (real) totaly ordered field that satisfies the dedekind axiom.

As for the rest, time whatever it ought to be (continuous, discrete, whatever) has no point in this discussion. all you are asking is "is time better modeled by the real numbers or something else?" and is not a question that has anything to do with mathematics.
 
  • #34
Looking back, you seem to think the contradiction is that Dedekind's axiom says there are two classes, but then introduces a point which you believe is of neither class. But his axiom does not say that it is of neither class. The axiom, as you've stated it, is actually a little ambiguous. It refers to it as the point that "produces the division."

Anyways, if you are going to divide time then in your example, you could either divide it into one class of points that are strictly before the present, and one class that is before or during the present OR divide it into one class of points that are before and including the present, and one that is strictly after the present. Do you see how these would be complete divisions? If we took two classes, one that was strictly before and one that was strictly after, we wouldn't have completely divided time. Now, regardless of which of the above two ways you divide time, the present serves as the one and only dividing point. And depending on how you do this, the dividing point is either in the earlier class or the later class, but it is going to be in one of them, it's not in a third class. So what's the problem?
 
  • #35
Thanks to everyone for the discussion. I'll leave it there it that's ok because I think we've reached an impasse. I came across the axiom in Dantzig's book on mathematics, much praised by Einstein. He takes the view that the axiom is problematic, and I'm afraid despite what's been said here I still agree with him. But of course it's possible that I've misinterpreted him in some way. Does anyone have a copy? I borrowed it and now can't refer back to it. He specifically discusses the problem of Dedekind's cut in relation to the mathematical treatment of time, and what he says seems right to me. This is why I was suprised at the reaction to my question here. I was just checking my understanding of him and not expecting a disagreement. Probably my fault as a non-mathematician for using the wrong terminology or something.

Regards
Canute
 
<h2>1. What is Dedekind's Axiom?</h2><p>Dedekind's Axiom is a mathematical principle proposed by German mathematician Richard Dedekind in the late 19th century. It states that any non-empty set of real numbers that is bounded above has a least upper bound, also known as the supremum.</p><h2>2. How does Dedekind's Axiom relate to the real numbers?</h2><p>Dedekind's Axiom is one of the fundamental principles of the real numbers. It helps to define the completeness of the real number system, which means that there are no "gaps" or "holes" between numbers. This axiom also allows for the existence of irrational numbers, such as pi and the square root of 2.</p><h2>3. What are the fundamentals of Dedekind's Axiom?</h2><p>The fundamentals of Dedekind's Axiom include the concept of a set being bounded above, as well as the existence of a least upper bound. This axiom also relies on the idea of completeness, which means that the real number system is continuous and without any gaps.</p><h2>4. Can Dedekind's Axiom lead to any contradictions?</h2><p>There have been some attempts to prove that Dedekind's Axiom leads to contradictions, but these attempts have not been successful. In fact, Dedekind's Axiom has been widely accepted as a fundamental principle of the real number system and is used in many areas of mathematics.</p><h2>5. How is Dedekind's Axiom used in mathematics?</h2><p>Dedekind's Axiom is used in many areas of mathematics, including real analysis, topology, and measure theory. It is also a key principle in the development of the real number system and is used to prove many important theorems, such as the Intermediate Value Theorem and the Monotone Convergence Theorem.</p>

1. What is Dedekind's Axiom?

Dedekind's Axiom is a mathematical principle proposed by German mathematician Richard Dedekind in the late 19th century. It states that any non-empty set of real numbers that is bounded above has a least upper bound, also known as the supremum.

2. How does Dedekind's Axiom relate to the real numbers?

Dedekind's Axiom is one of the fundamental principles of the real numbers. It helps to define the completeness of the real number system, which means that there are no "gaps" or "holes" between numbers. This axiom also allows for the existence of irrational numbers, such as pi and the square root of 2.

3. What are the fundamentals of Dedekind's Axiom?

The fundamentals of Dedekind's Axiom include the concept of a set being bounded above, as well as the existence of a least upper bound. This axiom also relies on the idea of completeness, which means that the real number system is continuous and without any gaps.

4. Can Dedekind's Axiom lead to any contradictions?

There have been some attempts to prove that Dedekind's Axiom leads to contradictions, but these attempts have not been successful. In fact, Dedekind's Axiom has been widely accepted as a fundamental principle of the real number system and is used in many areas of mathematics.

5. How is Dedekind's Axiom used in mathematics?

Dedekind's Axiom is used in many areas of mathematics, including real analysis, topology, and measure theory. It is also a key principle in the development of the real number system and is used to prove many important theorems, such as the Intermediate Value Theorem and the Monotone Convergence Theorem.

Similar threads

  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
14
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
1
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
17
Views
440
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
6
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
961
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
976
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
7
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
5
Views
911
Replies
5
Views
1K
Back
Top