Bohm Interpretation and Bell Theorem

In summary: In addition, the activities of all of the other particles in the universe which exert a non-local influence on Bob must exactly have an identical influence on Alice, and yet Bob is around longer and therefore should be influenced in ways that wouldn't affect Alice. So it seems this would provide an influence that would tend to remove the correlation between Alice and Bob.Yes, that's a valid point.
  • #1
NJV
39
0
I recently read about the pilot wave theory and the Bohm interpretation, and I must say I really like the idea. The only of my confusions it leaves unchanged are those concerning the EPR paradox. The Bohm interpretation does not seem to answer the question of the dreaded spokhafte Fernwirkung. Yet, I read that

"The Bohm interpretation describes [the experiment described in the Bell Theorem] as follows: to understand the evolution of these particles, we need to set up a wave equation for both particles; the orientation of the apparatus affects the wave function. The particles in the experiment follow the guidance of the wave function; we don't know the initial conditions of these particles, but we can predict the statistical outcome of the experiment from the wave function. It is the wave function that carries the faster-than-light effect of changing the orientation of the apparatus."
(source: Wikipedia; http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bohm_interpretation#The_Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen_paradox )

How does the orientation of the apparatus affect the wave function? Can someone explain just how, according to the Bohm Interpretation, the wave function of these particles could have such superluminal effect? Is there any theory about this at all? From the way Wikipedia put it, I got the impression there was more to be said about it.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
NJV said:
How does the orientation of the apparatus affect the wave function?
The apparatus also also has its wave function. Different orientations mean different wave functions. However, the apparatus interacts with the system you want to measure, which means that the wave functions of the apparatus and the system influence each other. More precisely, these two wave functions become entangled, so that at the end you do not have separate wave functions of the apparatus and the system, but a single wave function that describes both.

NJV said:
Can someone explain just how, according to the Bohm Interpretation, the wave function of these particles could have such superluminal effect?
Just take a look at the equation that describes the motion of particles for a wave function of two or more particles. For example, take a look at Eq. (15) in
http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/quant-ph/0512065 [AIP Conf.Proc.844:272-280,2006]
This equation clearly shows that a force on a particle depends on the instantaneous positions of all other particles.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #3
Thanks for the quick reply.

Demystifier said:
The apparatus also also has its wave function. Different orientations mean different wave functions. However, the apparatus interacts with the system you want to measure, which means that the wave functions of the apparatus and the system influence each other. More precisely, these two wave functions become entangled, so that at the end you do not have separate wave functions of the apparatus and the system, but a single wave function that describes both.

That's clarified, thanks. I'm not sure if I've understood the rest, though:

Demystifier said:
Just take a look at the equation that describes the motion of particles for a wave function of two or more particles. For example, take a look at Eq. (15) in
http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/quant-ph/0512065 [AIP Conf.Proc.844:272-280,2006]
This equation clearly shows that a force on a particle depends on the instantaneous positions of all other particles.

In other words, the force that affects either of the entangled particles also affects the other because both depend on the instantaneous positions of the same particles?
 
  • #4
NJV said:
In other words, the force that affects either of the entangled particles also affects the other because both depend on the instantaneous positions of the same particles?
Yes.
 
  • #5
Thank you. I stand demystified. :)
 
  • #6
I have a few questions. An entangled pair is created at T0. You measure Alice at time T1 and Bob at time T2 (where T0<T1<T2), and the measurement apparati settings are changing at all points in time between T0 and T2.

1. How is Bob able to be sensitive to the observation of Alice at T1? It seems Bob would need to ignore the settings at Alice at all points in time other than exactly at T1.

2. In addition, the activities of all of the other particles in the universe which exert a non-local influence on Bob must exactly have an identical influence on Alice, and yet Bob is around longer and therefore should be influenced in ways that wouldn't affect Alice. So it seems this would provide an influence that would tend to remove the correlation between Alice and Bob.

Thanks,
 
  • #7
DrChinese said:
1. How is Bob able to be sensitive to the observation of Alice at T1? It seems Bob would need to ignore the settings at Alice at all points in time other than exactly at T1.
No. The Bob's observations at T2 are determined by the Alice's state at T2. But why then it is also correlated with the Alice's state at T1? Because the evolution of Alice's state is deterministic, so the Alice's state at T2 is correlated with Alice's state at T1. Typically, the Alice's observable measured at T1 does not change at all during the further evolution from T1 to T2.

DrChinese said:
2. In addition, the activities of all of the other particles in the universe which exert a non-local influence on Bob must exactly have an identical influence on Alice, and yet Bob is around longer and therefore should be influenced in ways that wouldn't affect Alice. So it seems this would provide an influence that would tend to remove the correlation between Alice and Bob.
If other particles have a significant influence on Bob, then these other particles cause the environment-induced decoherence. Yes, it will affect Alice too and the correlation between Alice and Bob will be effectively destroyed. There is no big difference between standard QM and Bohmian QM in that regard.
 
Last edited:
  • #8
Demystifier said:
No. The Bob's observations at T2 are determined by the Alice's state at T2. But why then it is also correlated with the Alice's state at T1? Because the evolution of Alice's state is deterministic, so the Alice's state at T2 is correlated with Alice's state at T1. Typically, the Alice's observable measured at T1 does not change at all during the further evolution from T1 to T2.


If other particles have a significant influence on Bob, then these other particles cause the environment-induced decoherence. Yes, it will affect Alice too and the correlation between Alice and Bob will be effectively destroyed. There is no big difference between standard QM and Bohmian QM in that regard.

Thanks as always for helping me to understand this.

So even changing Alice's measurement apparatus setting from X at T1 to Y at T2 would not affect the result of Bob's measurement at T2? I was thinking that the measurement apparatus itself was inducing an effect on Alice. And I would think that it would be significant, in order to comply with Bell.

For example: Bob is being measured at 0 degrees at T2; and Alice at one or the other of two settings, either +120 degrees or -120 degrees relative to Bob, at earlier time T1. Let's say the apparatus at Alice switches from the one setting at T1 to the other at T2. We know the coincidence rate will be 25%. But the results at Bob must reflect whether the setting at Alice is the +120 or -120 setting, which nearly reverses the outcome at Alice. Obviously, to comply with Bell, the observer settings of Alice and Bob must somehow be factored into make the numbers work. But what you are saying about the time evolution is hard for me to grasp. It seems like you could do experiments in which you vary the settings at Alice at T1 and T2 to either be the same or 120 degrees apart, and the results would reveal the non-local effect either way. (And yet I know there wouldn't really be any difference in the outcome no matter what happens after T1 at Alice.) Does where I'm going with this example make sense? In this case, we know decoherence has not set in.
 
  • #9
DrChinese said:
So even changing Alice's measurement apparatus setting from X at T1 to Y at T2 would not affect the result of Bob's measurement at T2? I was thinking that the measurement apparatus itself was inducing an effect on Alice. And I would think that it would be significant, in order to comply with Bell.
If I understood you correctly, this changing of the Alice measurement apparatus is something that an experimentalist makes buy her "free will", right? If it would affect Bob, it would mean that she could send a GENUINE information to Bob faster than light, whereas we know that it is not possible. From this, it follows that SUCH changing of the apparatus (by "free will") cannot influence Bob. It is equally true in both the standard and the Bohmian interpretation.

But perhaps you meant some automatic deterministic change of the apparatus? Something determined by a predefined time-dependent Hamiltonian or by the unitary evolution of the wave function? In this case, it can be said that this change will influence Bob. (But in a sense, it can also be said that such a change is not a change at all because everything was actually predetermined already at T0, so there is no GENUINE transfer of information.) In the Bohmian interpretation, Bob's observations at T2 are determined by the Alice and apparatus state at T2. Again, if you know how is Alice and apparatus state at T2 deterministically related to that at t<T2, then you can also interpret Bob's observations at T2 as being (indirectly) determined by the Alice and apparatus state at t<T2.

Or perhaps you meant some genuinely random change of the apparatus? Well, there are no genuinely random events in Bohmian mechanics.
 
Last edited:
  • #10
DrChinese said:
It seems like you could do experiments in which you vary the settings at Alice at T1 and T2 to either be the same or 120 degrees apart, and the results would reveal the non-local effect either way. (And yet I know there wouldn't really be any difference in the outcome no matter what happens after T1 at Alice.)
In THIS SPECIFIC situation that you describe, you are right that there wouldn't really be any difference in the outcome no matter what happens after T1 at Alice. On the other hand, Bohmian mechanics claims that it should be determined by the state at T2, which is AFTER T1. Is this a contradiction? No, because in THIS SPECIFIC situation, all the relevant properties of Alice do not change after T1.

But why? What forbids their changing? The point is that at T1 a genuine measurement has been performed. For example, the spin in z-direction has been measured to be equal to +1. The crucial point is that a genuine measurement allways contains interaction with a large number of the degrees of freedom of the measuring apparatus, which implies that decoherence takes place. The effect of decoherence is a sort of stabilization of the measured observable (in this case spin in z-direction), so the spin in z-direction does not change during the further evolution. Since it is equal to +1 at T1, it is equal to +1 at T2 as well. In fact, if there was no such a stabilization, then we would not be able to actually register the spin by a macroscopic apparatus at T1 in the first place.

I think I know what will be your next question: But what if, after T1, we perform a measurement of the spin in some other direction? My answer is ready, but I will wait for your explicit question. :)
 
Last edited:
  • #11
Demystifier said:
If I understood you correctly, this changing of the Alice measurement apparatus is something that an experimentalist makes buy her "free will", right? If it would affect Bob, it would mean that she could send a GENUINE information to Bob faster than light, whereas we know that it is not possible. From this, it follows that SUCH changing of the apparatus (by "free will") cannot influence Bob. It is equally true in both the standard and the Bohmian interpretation.

But perhaps you meant some automatic deterministic change of the apparatus? Something determined by a predefined time-dependent Hamiltonian or by the unitary evolution of the wave function? In this case, it can be said that this change will influence Bob. (But in a sense, it can also be said that such a change is not a change at all because everything was actually predetermined already at T0, so there is no GENUINE transfer of information.) In the Bohmian interpretation, Bob's observations at T2 are determined by the Alice and apparatus state at T2. Again, if you know how is Alice and apparatus state at T2 deterministically related to that at t<T2, then you can also interpret Bob's observations at T2 as being (indirectly) determined by the Alice and apparatus state at t<T2.

Or perhaps you meant some genuinely random change of the apparatus? Well, there are no genuinely random events in Bohmian mechanics.

I was imagining some system whereby Alice's measurement setting either changed - or didn't change - between times T1 and T2 according to some pseudo-random mechanism: something sufficiently macroscopic as to not be directly connected to Alice or Bob. Now I realize that everything around us is connected via a relativistic cone going to the past, but I am assuming that would not itself be capable of directly influencing the results of Alice and Bob. If it did, that would in effect be the superdeterminism argument redux. And I don't think you are advocating that.
 
  • #12
Demystifier said:
In THIS SPECIFIC situation that you describe, you are right that there wouldn't really be any difference in the outcome no matter what happens after T1 at Alice. On the other hand, Bohmian mechanics claims that it should be determined by the state at T2, which is AFTER T1. Is this a contradiction? No, because in THIS SPECIFIC situation, all the relevant properties of Alice do not change after T1.

But why? What forbids their changing? The point is that at T1 a genuine measurement has been performed. For example, the spin in z-direction has been measured to be equal to +1. The crucial point is that a genuine measurement allways contains interaction with a large number of the degrees of freedom of the measuring apparatus, which implies that decoherence takes place. The effect of decoherence is a sort of stabilization of the measured observable (in this case spin in z-direction), so the spin in z-direction does not change during the further evolution. Since it is equal to +1 at T1, it is equal to +1 at T2 as well. In fact, if there was no such a stabilization, then we would not be able to actually register the spin by a macroscopic apparatus at T1 in the first place.

I think I know what will be your next question: But what if, after T1, we perform a measurement of the spin in some other direction? My answer is ready, but I will wait for your explicit question. :)

Yes, that is exactly my next question. :smile:

So we have +1 in z direction at T1 for both Alice AND Bob. Then Bob measures at some other setting at time T2 and sees results consistent with that per standard prediction. Hmmm. I guess that actually makes good sense. And it wouldn't be inconsistent with Bell. Am I getting close? :blushing:
 
  • #13
DrChinese said:
Yes, that is exactly my next question. :smile:

So we have +1 in z direction at T1 for both Alice AND Bob. Then Bob measures at some other setting at time T2 and sees results consistent with that per standard prediction. Hmmm. I guess that actually makes good sense. And it wouldn't be inconsistent with Bell. Am I getting close? :blushing:
You certainly are. But let me clarify the notion of spin in Bohmian mechanics.

In Bohmian mechanics, particles do not have spins. They only have positions and velocities. Spin is a property of the wave function (not of the particle), but wave function is not something that can be measured. All that can be really measured according to Bohmian mechanics - are particle positions. But then, what does it mean to measure the spin of a particle?

Consider the Stern-Gerlach apparatus, which is supposed to measure the spin. Due to the interaction with the magnetic field, one usually says that particles of positive spin go in one direction while particles of negative spin go in the other direction. But honestly, all that we really determine by the experiment is the direction in which the particle goes. We do not really measure spin, we only interpret the measured particle position as being caused by the spin.

Now back to Bohmian mechanics. Bohmian mechanics provides a mechanism that causes particles to go in one or the other direction. The wave function splits into two channels (localized wave packets), one having one spin and localized in one direction, the other having the other spin and localized in the other direction. The particle enters one and only one of these channels. Once it enters one of the channels, it stays there because the two channels do not overlap.

Now what happens if spin is measured again, now in another direction? The wave function splits again, so now we have 4 channels, namely 2 new channels for each of the channels created by the first measurement. But particle will again enter only one of the 4 channels. More precisely, it will enter one of the 2 channels that emanate from the channel that particle entered during the first measurement. That explains why Bob is correlated not only with the result of the second measurement, but also with the result of the first measurement.

Perhaps all this is not a direct answer to your question, but I hope that it helps.
 
  • #14
I've been following http://www.tcm.phy.cam.ac.uk/~mdt26/pilot_waves.html" 's lecture course on Bohmian mechanics (though he calls it pilot-wave theory) if it's any help. All his slides are on the website with links to loads of papers.. If they're teaching it at Cambridge University now it must be getting respectable.. :grumpy:
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #15
camboy said:
I've been following http://www.tcm.phy.cam.ac.uk/~mdt26/pilot_waves.html" 's lecture course on Bohmian mechanics (though he calls it pilot-wave theory) if it's any help.
So have I, at least the gist of it. I highly recommend it to anyone interested in these matters. And Towler's got a sense of humor, too. :wink:
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #16
camboy said:
I've been following http://www.tcm.phy.cam.ac.uk/~mdt26/pilot_waves.html" 's lecture course on Bohmian mechanics (though he calls it pilot-wave theory) if it's any help. All his slides are on the website with links to loads of papers.. If they're teaching it at Cambridge University now it must be getting respectable.. :grumpy:
Beautiful! :smile:
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #17
Demystifier said:
You certainly are. But let me clarify the notion of spin in Bohmian mechanics.

In Bohmian mechanics, particles do not have spins. They only have positions and velocities. Spin is a property of the wave function (not of the particle), but wave function is not something that can be measured. All that can be really measured according to Bohmian mechanics - are particle positions. But then, what does it mean to measure the spin of a particle?

Consider the Stern-Gerlach apparatus, which is supposed to measure the spin. Due to the interaction with the magnetic field, one usually says that particles of positive spin go in one direction while particles of negative spin go in the other direction. But honestly, all that we really determine by the experiment is the direction in which the particle goes. We do not really measure spin, we only interpret the measured particle position as being caused by the spin.

Now back to Bohmian mechanics. Bohmian mechanics provides a mechanism that causes particles to go in one or the other direction. The wave function splits into two channels (localized wave packets), one having one spin and localized in one direction, the other having the other spin and localized in the other direction. The particle enters one and only one of these channels. Once it enters one of the channels, it stays there because the two channels do not overlap.

Now what happens if spin is measured again, now in another direction? The wave function splits again, so now we have 4 channels, namely 2 new channels for each of the channels created by the first measurement. But particle will again enter only one of the 4 channels. More precisely, it will enter one of the 2 channels that emanate from the channel that particle entered during the first measurement. That explains why Bob is correlated not only with the result of the second measurement, but also with the result of the first measurement.

Perhaps all this is not a direct answer to your question, but I hope that it helps.

OK, I think I get some idea about Bohmian spin, but... it follows the HUP just like position, momentum, etc. So equally as much an observable. Hmmm.

But I think I am lost on the channels. :eek: How does what happens at Alice (which clearly is related to the observational setting at Alice) get transmitted to Bob? You were saying that particles move deterministically, but yet we know the "hidden variables" cannot have been encoded at the time the particles (Alice, Bob) are created. We know there is a dependency on the measurement at T1, in this example. So I can only suppose that at the T1 time of the Alice measurement that Bob instantly adjusts to match. Or...?
 
  • #18
DrChinese said:
So I can only suppose that at the T1 time of the Alice measurement that Bob instantly adjusts to match.
That is true. But it happens at each time t, not only at T1. Still, T1 may be more interesting because at that particular time more dramatic changes may occur.
 
  • #19
Demystifier said:
That is true. But it happens at each time t, not only at T1. Still, T1 may be more interesting because at that particular time more dramatic changes may occur.

Thanks for sticking with me. A few more questions:

1. I assume that Alice and Bob, being entangled, have a special relationship not shared by other particles. Is that correct? Or are Alice and Bob equally influenced by other nearby particles as each other?

2. From the lecture notes (#3, slide 31), Towler says that in a double slit setup: "(1) Each particle passes through one slit or the other, (2) Wave function single-valuedness implies no trajectory can cross or even intersect apparatus axis of symmetry - thus know which slit from on-screen particle position." What are your thoughts on this?

It seems as if this interpretation would be open to physical testing. I mean, you could play tricks on the path of the pilot wave, which clearly is fairly large if it goes through the slit opposite the particle. True, standard QM has this same thing. But the difference is that in QM, the particle goes through both slits and there is no preferred slit. Therefore, in Pilot Wave, the difference is that the particle is guided by the influence of the pilot wave crests/valleys but goes through a slit that is known. Seems like that would lead to a way to physically measure/observe this asymmetry by exploiting differences in the evolution of the pilot wave and the underlying particle.
 
  • #20
DrChinese said:
1. I assume that Alice and Bob, being entangled, have a special relationship not shared by other particles. Is that correct? Or are Alice and Bob equally influenced by other nearby particles as each other?
It depends. If Alice and Bob are not entangled with other particles, then their relationship is not shared by other particles. Likewise, if Alice and Bob are entangled with other particles, then their relationship is shared by other particles. These statements are interpretation independent.

DrChinese said:
2. From the lecture notes (#3, slide 31), Towler says that in a double slit setup: "(1) Each particle passes through one slit or the other, (2) Wave function single-valuedness implies no trajectory can cross or even intersect apparatus axis of symmetry - thus know which slit from on-screen particle position." What are your thoughts on this?
In the Bohmian interpretation, this is absolutely correct.

DrChinese said:
It seems as if this interpretation would be open to physical testing. I mean, you could play tricks on the path of the pilot wave, which clearly is fairly large if it goes through the slit opposite the particle. True, standard QM has this same thing. But the difference is that in QM, the particle goes through both slits and there is no preferred slit. Therefore, in Pilot Wave, the difference is that the particle is guided by the influence of the pilot wave crests/valleys but goes through a slit that is known. Seems like that would lead to a way to physically measure/observe this asymmetry by exploiting differences in the evolution of the pilot wave and the underlying particle.
It cannot be tested. If you do the experiment with only one particle, you will see the asymmetry (you will observe the particle at one side of the axis only), but standard QM also predicts this asymmetry. If you repeat the experiment many times, you will not see the asymmetry because in average you will see an equal number of particles at both sides, which is again predicted by both standard and Bohmian QM. In the Bohmian interpretation, this is because some particles (50%) will go through one slit, while others will go through the other.

By the way, there is a great difference between "knowing" the slit through which the particle passed (by calculating it using Bohmian theory) and actually measuring it. The actual measurement allways causes decoherence, which ruins a lot.
 
Last edited:
  • #21
Demystifier said:
It cannot be tested. If you do the experiment with only one particle, you will see the asymmetry (you will observe the particle at one side of the axis only), but standard QM also predicts this asymmetry. If you repeat the experiment many times, you will not see the asymmetry because in average you will see an equal number of particles at both sides, which is again predicted by both standard and Bohmian QM. In the Bohmian interpretation, this is because some particles (50%) will go through one slit, while others will go through the other.

By the way, there is a great difference between "knowing" the slit through which the particle passed (by calculating it using Bohmian theory) and actually measuring it. The actual measurement allways causes decoherence, which ruins a lot.

I see the part about the average of many trials. And the idea of having the particle go through one specific slit is great.

But consider that sub-group in which the particle is detected on the left side. According to BM, the particle went through the left slit and also the pilot wave went through the left slit. The pilot wave also went through the right slit. Could we tinker slightly with the right slit so that we might observe the right-side pilot wave in some manner?
 
  • #22
DrChinese said:
But consider that sub-group in which the particle is detected on the left side. According to BM, the particle went through the left slit and also the pilot wave went through the left slit. The pilot wave also went through the right slit. Could we tinker slightly with the right slit so that we might observe the right-side pilot wave in some manner?
Essentially, you want to detect the wave without detecting the particle? The idea is that only particles can be directly detected. Nevertheless, there are some ways to demonstrate indirectly that empty waves (i.e. waves without a particle) also exist. See, e.g., interaction free measurements and the Penrose bomb. Delayed choice quantum eraser can also be naturally interpreted as a demonstration that wave functions exist even when particles are not present in these waves. These phenomena are not proofs that the Bohmian interpretation is correct. Nevertheless, these phenomena are trivial to explain with the Bohmian interpretation, while they look very mysterious, paradoxical, or at least counter-intuitive in the conventional wave-function-collapse interpretation.
 
Last edited:
  • #23
Demystifier said:
Essentially, you want to detect the wave without detecting the particle? The idea is that only particles can be directly detected. Nevertheless, there are some ways to demonstrate indirectly that empty waves (i.e. waves without a particle) also exist. See, e.g., interaction free measurements and the Penrose bomb. Delayed choice quantum eraser can also be naturally interpreted as a demonstration that wave functions exist even when particles are not present in these waves. These phenomena are not proofs that the Bohmian interpretation is correct. Nevertheless, these phenomena are trivial to explain with the Bohmian interpretation, while they look very mysterious, paradoxical, or at least counter-intuitive in the conventional wave-function-collapse interpretation.

Well we know that the pilot wave went through the right side (particle detected on left) because if we block the right side, the pattern changes. I guess the effect of the right side pilot wave is no different than would be expected in other interpretations. Just seems like there ought to be a testable difference somewhere. :) Oh well...
 
  • #24
DrChinese said:
Well we know that the pilot wave went through the right side (particle detected on left) because if we block the right side, the pattern changes. I guess the effect of the right side pilot wave is no different than would be expected in other interpretations.
I agree.
DrChinese said:
Just seems like there ought to be a testable difference somewhere. :) Oh well...
There would be if we were able to detect waves of single particles. But we are not. Note that nobody ever detected a single electron or photon as a big object, even though the spread of its wave can be very big. For me, this is an experimental evidence that single particles are NOT their waves.
 
  • #25
Demystifier said:
For me, this is an experimental evidence that single particles are NOT their waves.

Good point.
 

1. What is the Bohm Interpretation?

The Bohm Interpretation, also known as the Pilot Wave Theory, is a quantum interpretation proposed by physicist David Bohm. It suggests that particles have definite positions and trajectories, unlike in other interpretations where particles exist as probabilities until measured.

2. How does the Bohm Interpretation differ from other interpretations?

The main difference between the Bohm Interpretation and other interpretations, such as the Copenhagen Interpretation, is that it includes hidden variables that determine the behavior of particles. In other interpretations, particles exist as probabilities until observed, while in the Bohm Interpretation, particles have definite positions and trajectories at all times.

3. What is the Bell Theorem and how does it relate to the Bohm Interpretation?

The Bell Theorem, also known as Bell's Inequality, is a mathematical proof that shows certain predictions of quantum mechanics cannot be explained by local hidden variables. This means that the Bohm Interpretation, which includes hidden variables, cannot fully account for all quantum phenomena predicted by quantum mechanics.

4. Is the Bohm Interpretation widely accepted in the scientific community?

The Bohm Interpretation is still a topic of debate and is not as widely accepted as other interpretations, such as the Copenhagen Interpretation. However, it has gained some support and continues to be studied and explored by scientists.

5. What are the implications of the Bohm Interpretation and Bell Theorem?

The Bohm Interpretation and Bell Theorem raise important questions about the nature of reality and the role of hidden variables in understanding quantum phenomena. They also have implications for the concept of determinism and the limits of our current understanding of quantum mechanics.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
15
Views
240
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
11
Replies
376
Views
10K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
4
Replies
109
Views
7K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
10
Replies
333
Views
11K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
772
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
9
Replies
309
Views
8K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
4K
Back
Top