Detecting Macroscopic Entanglement With the Bell Inequality

In summary, the author is proposing to test whether or not a macroscopic object can be entangled with a quantum object. They are proposing to do this by shooting a photon and a tennis ball and measuring which inequality is predicted by QM. However, the author admits that they do not understand why they would bring this up unless they are misunderstanding the comment.
  • #1
michael879
698
7
So first off, Ill admit I've forgotten most of the finer details of the bell inequality so I apologize if I've gotten something wrong.

From how I remember it, the bell inequality is a test of any local hidden variable theory vs. QM. It uses the fact that the inequality measured if a classical, local hidden variable theory were true is necessarily different than the inequality given by QM.

As far as I know, the nature of decoherence is somewhat of a mystery. Personally, I like Everett's interpretation that decoherence is just an illusion caused by the entanglement of a macroscopic object (the observer) with the measured quantum object. I was thinking of this and the other theories (Penrose's specifically which I really dislike) and it seems to me like these are more than just interpretations. Although MWI is clearly an interpretation, Everett's view of decoherence should be testable.

So here's the experiment I thought of that should test it:

Put a photon into an equal superposition between up and down spin (or polarization w/e). Have a detector in a vacuum (space) measure this photon. Then have the detector shoot a new photon with identical spin to the measured photon, alone with a tennis ball with some property determined by the measured spin (e.g. angular momentum, speed).

Now do the Bell inequality test on the photon and the tennis ball (repeated many times of course). The detectors must be isolated enough from the first detector that no information about the projectiles can reach them (or else the systems wave function would collapse).

If a macroscopic object is capable of entangling with a quantum object, the measured inequality should be that predicted by QM. However if some theory like penrose's is right, the tennis ball would not be capable of entangling with the photon and the measured inequality would be that of a hidden variably theory.

Did I miss something or is this actually testable?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
michael879 said:
Did I miss something or is this actually testable?

Are you proposing to test something from Penrose or from Everett? The consensus has always been that there is no test possible of MWI (although this is a subject that gets attention).

As far as I know, progressively larger objects are capable of being entangled. I am speaking of atoms, and I do not think there is any particular cutoff. A tennis ball might be a little tough as its entropy is so high it would be hard to nail down the state sufficiently to perform any kind of test. In fact, a high-efficiency detector would itself be about the macroscopic limit (pretty much by definition).
 
  • #3
michael879 said:
So here's the experiment I thought of that should test it:

Put a photon into an equal superposition between up and down spin (or polarization w/e). Have a detector in a vacuum (space) measure this photon. Then have the detector shoot a new photon with identical spin to the measured photon, alone with a tennis ball with some property determined by the measured spin (e.g. angular momentum, speed).

Now do the Bell inequality test on the photon and the tennis ball …
The rules of physics give us conservation laws that demand two electrons in on a atom with a specific combined spin that in a pronominal that cause them to jump off simultaneously will do so conserving spin in a predictable way.
Likewise, when a single photon converters into two photons via SPDC.

Exactly what physics rule of conservation do you hope to use that would apply to a photon and a tennis ball wrt their spins??
 
  • #4
RandallB said:
The rules of physics give us conservation laws that demand two electrons in on a atom with a specific combined spin that in a pronominal that cause them to jump off simultaneously will do so conserving spin in a predictable way.
Likewise, when a single photon converters into two photons via SPDC.

Exactly what physics rule of conservation do you hope to use that would apply to a photon and a tennis ball wrt their spins??

seriously? that's your only comment? First of all, isn't spin conservation just conservation of angular momentum? Anyway, its not really important. quick solution:
have some other objects in an isolated vacuum that are used to conserve all conserved quantities. e.g. a photon with opposite spin and some object with opposite angular momentum.

I really don't understand why you would bring this up unless I am misunderstanding your comment.. Theres just so many possible ways to fix it, and my proposed theory was far from specific...
 
  • #5
DrChinese said:
Are you proposing to test something from Penrose or from Everett? The consensus has always been that there is no test possible of MWI (although this is a subject that gets attention).

As far as I know, progressively larger objects are capable of being entangled. I am speaking of atoms, and I do not think there is any particular cutoff. A tennis ball might be a little tough as its entropy is so high it would be hard to nail down the state sufficiently to perform any kind of test. In fact, a high-efficiency detector would itself be about the macroscopic limit (pretty much by definition).

yea I know there are no tests possible, but then I thought of this and don't see any immediate problems with it. In theory at least it seems like a testable difference between the two theories, as hard as it may be to do in practice.

If the two states of the tennis ball used for the entanglement are significantly different (direction of momentum/angular momentum?), shouldn't it be easy to test?
 
  • #6
michael879 said:
seriously? that's your only comment? First of all, isn't spin conservation just conservation of angular momentum? Anyway, its not really important. quick solution:
have some other objects in an isolated vacuum that are used to conserve all conserved quantities. e.g. a photon with opposite spin and some object with opposite angular momentum.

I really don't understand why you would bring this up unless I am misunderstanding your comment.. Theres just so many possible ways to fix it, and my proposed theory was far from specific...
Are you kidding !?
You say that your “ proposed theory was far from specific”
But complain that I expect such a minor specific detail as to how you expect to make the spin values of a photon and a tennis ball the same!

If there are “just so many possible ways to fix it”
just name one that might even come close to giving a tennis ball the same spin as anyone photon.
 
  • #7
To clarify this issue, perhaps it would be of use to note that "gedankenexperiments" have a strange limitation in quantum mechanics. Normal gedankens say, "of course we cannot actually do this, but we can conceptualize the result anyway, and we should not encounter an inconsistency". In other words, consistency must extend not only to experiments that can actually be done (technologically speaking), but also to those that cannot. However, in quantum mechanics there is yet another possibility-- that there might be more than just technological limitations, there might be fundamental limitations in our ability to extract scientific information from reality (due to certain assumptions we make before we even set out to do science).

So we must distinguish gedankens that generate observables that are difficult to actually obtain, from those that do not generate observables at all. On the observable side of the issue, the debate in this thread might be about the question: when an electron interacts with a tennis ball, is angular momentum conserved?

I think the answer must be that it is, in any QM interpretation (I don't know Penrose's). The reason is that spin is a QM notion, but it is defined by behaviors that do cross the QM/classical "boundary". In other words, it is already a QM notion that survives the classical filter we always apply, and that's why the CI includes the notion of spin as an observable operator. Also, the CI includes a "correspondence principle", which says that classical conservation laws must also be statistically conserved in QM, insofar as the conservation laws can be applied to QM notions that survive coupling to classical objects (which all QM notions do, by definition). So I do think that an electron can be said to confer its spin to a tennis ball if the electron spin flips in the interaction, even though such a tiny effect would be unmeasurable, because one could imagine aggregating vast numbers of the same effect until it was measurable. That's the correspondence principle. But what I don't see is why Penrose's picture would say anything different. I don't know that picture, but I doubt Penrose would build a picture that was not compatible with the correspondence principle.

But it sounds like you are saying that the only thing that would be different would be the concept of entanglement, not the outcome of any actual measurements. That's a bird of a different feather, for now we are in danger of leaving the realm of gedankens that actually connect with observations, and enter into the realm of gedankens that may not be doable-- not because of technological limitations, but because of fundamental limitations in the way humans can interact with and learn about reality.
 
Last edited:

1. What is macroscopic entanglement?

Macroscopic entanglement refers to the phenomenon where two or more large objects or systems become entangled, meaning their quantum states are correlated and cannot be described independently. This is in contrast to microscopic entanglement, which occurs at the atomic or subatomic level.

2. What is the Bell inequality?

The Bell inequality is a mathematical expression that sets a limit on the amount of correlation that can exist between two quantum systems if they are assumed to have local hidden variables. It is used to test for the violation of local realism, which suggests that all physical properties of a system are predetermined and independent of observation.

3. How does the Bell inequality relate to detecting macroscopic entanglement?

The Bell inequality can be used as a test to determine if two macroscopic systems are entangled. If the Bell inequality is violated, it indicates that the two systems are correlated in a way that cannot be explained by local hidden variables, thus demonstrating the presence of macroscopic entanglement.

4. What are some methods for detecting macroscopic entanglement with the Bell inequality?

One method is to use quantum optics techniques, such as measuring the polarization of photons, to create and manipulate entangled states in macroscopic systems. Another method is to use superconducting systems, such as SQUIDs, to create and detect entangled states. Additionally, researchers are exploring the use of optomechanical systems, which involve the interaction of light and mechanical motion, to generate and detect macroscopic entanglement.

5. Why is detecting macroscopic entanglement important?

Detecting macroscopic entanglement is important because it can help us better understand the fundamental nature of quantum mechanics and the boundary between classical and quantum behavior. It also has potential applications in quantum information processing, communication, and sensing. Additionally, studying macroscopic entanglement can provide insights into the behavior of complex systems and open new avenues for technological advancements.

Similar threads

Replies
4
Views
988
Replies
1
Views
804
Replies
50
Views
3K
Replies
3
Views
800
Replies
0
Views
661
Replies
0
Views
741
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
738
Replies
80
Views
3K
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
25
Views
2K
Back
Top