Could ‘Wheeler's delayed choice experiment’ be delayed?

In summary, Wheeler's classic delayed choice experiment has two possible outcomes: either the screen is left in place and we don't know which slit the photon went through, or the screen is removed and we reveal two telescopes and get an interference pattern which tells us the photon went through one of the two slits.
  • #1
leftriver
5
0
http://www.bottomlayer.com/bottom/basic_delayed_choice.htmThis link is from wiki's .

And my question is whether we can delay the choice?If we watched the photon which has passed the slit,did we have enough time to take measure to remove the screen?

We watch! And the speed of the photon is as soon as our watching. When we wanted to choice, the photon from the slit is on the screen.

If there is some way which make the speed of message overtakes a photon, and it would turn back the clock.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Is there anyone can open the link. I found I can not do it.
 
  • #3
The following content is from the link which I have referenced before.


Wheeler's Classic Delayed Choice Experiment
by Ross Rhodes

N.B. Familiarity with The Reality Program Chapter 2 is assumed.

John Archibald Wheeler is one of those thinkers who takes the ideas of quantum mechanics seriously. After studying the Copenhagen explanation of the double slit experiment – with its emphasis on what the observer knows and when it is known – Wheeler realized that the observer's choice might control those variables in a test.

"If what you say is true," he said (in effect), "then I may choose to know a property after the event should already have taken place." [1] Wheeler realized that in such a situation, the observer's choice would determine the outcome of the experiment – regardless of whether the outcome should logically have been determined long ago.

"Nonsense," said the reductionists. "Rubbish," said the materialists. "Completely absurd," said the naïve realists. "Yup," said the mathematicians.

And so Wheeler's thought experiment and the predictions of quantum mechanics were brought to the laboratory for testing. [2] This is what happens.

basic_delayed_choice.jpg



Basic delayed choice
1. Photon (or other quantum unit) is sent toward double slit.

2. Photon passes through double slit unobserved, logically either through one, through the other, or through both. To obtain an interference pattern, we surmise that something must pass through both slits; to obtain a particle distribution, we surmise that the photon must pass through one or the other. Whatever the photon does, it presumably does it now when it passes through the slits.

3. After passing through the slits, the photon is in transit towards the back wall.

At the "back wall," we have available two separate methods of detecting the photon.

4. First, we have a screen (or other detection system that can measure the horizontal placement of a photon hit, but is not able to distinguish where the photon came from).

The screen can be removed, as indicated by the dotted line. It can be removed quickly, very quickly, after the photon has passed the double slits but before the photon reaches the plane of the screen. That is, the screen can be removed while the photon is in transit in region 3.

Or the screen can be left in place. This is the experimenter's choice, which is delayed until after the photon has passed the slits (2) in whatever manner it happens to do so.

5. If the screen is removed, we reveal two telescopes. The telescopes are tightly focused on, watching, observing, just the narrow space of one slit only. The left telescope watches the left slit; the right telescope watches the right slit. (The mechanism/metaphor of the telescope assures that if you are looking through the telescope, you will see a flash of light if the photon went either wholly or in part through the slit on which it is focused; otherwise not. Therefore, you will obtain "which-path" information about the photon hit.)



Now suppose we have a photon in transit in region 3. The photon has already passed the slits.

We can yet choose to leave the screen in place, in which case we do not know which slit the photon went through.

Or we can choose to remove the screen. If we remove the screen, we will expect to see a flash at one telescope or the other (or both, except that never happens) for every photon sent through. Why? Because the photon has to go through either one slit, the other slit, or both slits. Those are all the possibilities. By watching both slits, we must see one of the following:

a flash at the left telescope and no flash at the right telescope, indicating that the photon went through the left slit; or
a flash at the right telescope and no flash at the left telescope, indicating that the photon went through the right slit; or
a weak half-flash at both telescopes indicating that the photon went through both slits.
Those are all the possibilities.

Upon observation at the screen QM tells us what we will get: Pattern 4r, which is exactly reminiscent of wave interference caused by two symmetrical waves, one emanating from each of the slits.

Upon observation at the telescopes QM tells us what we will get: Pattern 5r, which is exactly reminiscent of particle-like behavior traveling from the source, through one slit or the other, and being detected at the telescopes.

Consider the difference in the experimental set up depending on our choice of detection. If we choose to leave the screen in place, we get a particle distribution consistent with the interference pattern that would be produced by two hypothetical symmetrical waves, each emanating from one of the slits. We might say (although we are extremely reluctant to say this) that the photon traveled as a wave from the point of origin, through both slits, and on to the screen.

On the other hand, if we choose to remove the screen, we get a particle distribution consistent with the clumping pattern that would be produced by particle motion from the point of origin through one slit or the other and to the left telescope or to the right telescope. After all, the particle "appeared" (we saw a flash) at one telescope or the other, rather than "appearing" at some other point along the length of the screen.

In summary, we have chosen whether to know which slit the particle went through, by choosing to use the telescopes or not, which are the instruments that would give us the information about which slit the particle went through. We have delayed this choice until a time after the particles "have gone through one slit or the other slit or both slits," so to speak. Yet, it seems paradoxically that our later choice of whether to obtain this information determines whether the particle passed through one slit or the other slit or both slits, so to speak. If you want to think of it this way (I don't recommend it), the particle exhibited after-the-fact wave-like behavior at the slits if you chose the screen; and it exhibited after-the-fact particle-like behavior at the slits if you chose the telescopes. Therefore, our delayed choice of how to measure the particle determines how the particle actually behaved at an earlier time.


--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

Does our choice "change the past"?
How long can we delay the choice? In Wheeler's original thought experiment, he imagined the phenomenon on a cosmic scale, as follows:

1. A distant star emits a photon many billions of years ago.

2. The photon must pass a dense galaxy (or black hole) directly in its path toward earth.

"Gravitational lensing" predicted by general relativity (and well verified) will make the light bend around the galaxy or black hole. The same photon can, therefore, take either of two paths around the galaxy and still reach Earth – it can take the left path and bend back toward earth; or it can take the right path and bend back toward earth. Bending around the left side is the experimental equivalent of going through the left slit of a barrier; bending around the right side is the equivalent of going through the right slit.

3. The photon continues for a very long time (perhaps a few more billion years) on its way toward earth.

4. On Earth (many billions of years later), an astronomer chooses to use a screen type of light projector, encompassing both sides of the intervening and the surrounding space without focusing or distinguishing among regions. The photon will land somewhere along the field of focus without our astronomer being able to tell which side of the galaxy/black hole the photon passed, left or right. So the distribution pattern of the photon (even of a single photon, but easily recognizable after a lot of photons are collected) will be an interference pattern.
5. Alternatively, based on what she had for breakfast, our astronomer might choose to use a binocular apparatus, with one side of the binoculars (one telescope) focused exclusively on the left side of the intervening galaxy, and the other side focussed exclusively on the right side of the intervening galaxy. In that case the "pattern" will be a clump of photons at one side, and a clump of photons at the other side.

Now, for many billions of years the photon is in transit in region 3. Yet we can choose (many billions of years later) which experimental set up to employ – the single wide-focus, or the two narrowly focused instruments.

We have chosen whether to know which side of the galaxy the photon passed by (by choosing whether to use the two-telescope set up or not, which are the instruments that would give us the information about which side of the galaxy the photon passed). We have delayed this choice until a time long after the particles "have passed by one side of the galaxy, or the other side of the galaxy, or both sides of the galaxy," so to speak. Yet, it seems paradoxically that our later choice of whether to obtain this information determines which side of the galaxy the light passed, so to speak, billions of years ago.

So it seems that time has nothing to do with effects of quantum mechanics. And, indeed, the original thought experiment was not based on any analysis of how particles evolve and behave over time – it was based on the mathematics. This is what the mathematics predicted for a result, and this is exactly the result obtained in the laboratory.


--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

If you are serious about the idea that the result is determined only upon observation ...
Can we delay the choice even longer? Can we delay the choice until after the photons have "hit" the telescopes or the screen? It turns out we can. We do so with a handy quantum eraser. But that's a whole 'nuther experiment. See the Delayed Choice Quantum Eraser Commentary.

This is great stuff, isn't it?

Bonus picture!



Canton, Ohio
March 23, 2003


--------------------------------------------------------------------------------

References:

[1] See Wheeler's "delayed choice", in Quantum Theory and Measurement, edited by J.A. Wheeler and W.H. Zurek, Princeton Univ. Press (1983).

[2] E.g., V. Jacques, et al., "Experimental realization of Wheeler's gedankenexperiment," Science 315 966 (2007), e-print at http://www.arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0610241 ; A.G. Zajonc et al., Nature, 353, 507 (1991); P.G. Kwiat et al., Phys. Rev. A 49, 61 (1994); T.J. Herzog et al., Phys. Rev. Lett., 75, 3034 (1995); T.B. Pittman et al., Phys. Rev. Lett., 77, 1917 (1996). The Jacques experiment is described in Physics World, "Photons denied a glimpse at their observer" (Feb. 15, 2007), http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/news/27106 .
 
  • #4
leftriver said:
http://www.bottomlayer.com/bottom/basic_delayed_choice.htm


This link is from wiki's .

And my question is whether we can delay the choice?


If we watched the photon which has passed the slit,did we have enough time to take measure to remove the screen?

We watch! And the speed of the photon is as soon as our watching. When we wanted to choice, the photon from the slit is on the screen.

If there is some way which make the speed of message overtakes a photon, and it would turn back the clock.
We don't have to watch the photon to know it passed the slit. We know it's speed so we can wait the appropriate amount of time and then remove the screen. Or did you mean something else?
 
  • #5
Dead Boss said:
We don't have to watch the photon to know it passed the slit. We know it's speed so we can wait the appropriate amount of time and then remove the screen. Or did you mean something else?



If we do not direct the situation of the two slip,the choice should have no significant.

As the purpose of ‘Wheeler's delayed choice experiment is to illustrate that our choice could
influence the past.

But I have a doubt of the possibility to the component element of choice.

Could you help me to analyze the reality of the experiment?
 
  • #6
Could you help me to analyze the reality of the experiment?
Well the experiment has been carried out in 2007 and I honestly doubt that I could find any flaw where Wheeler(!) and a bunch of professional French physicists couldn't.
 
  • #7
Dead Boss said:
Well the experiment has been carried out in 2007 and I honestly doubt that I could find any flaw where Wheeler(!) and a bunch of professional French physicists couldn't.


Thanks for your anwser, I think I shoud read that paper carefully.I got a paper for this experiment.
 

1. What is Wheeler's delayed choice experiment?

Wheeler's delayed choice experiment is a thought experiment proposed by physicist John Wheeler in the 1970s. It challenges the concept of causality by suggesting that the actions of a measuring device in the present can affect the results of an experiment that has already been completed in the past.

2. How does Wheeler's delayed choice experiment work?

In the experiment, a particle is sent through a series of two slits. Depending on which slit the particle passes through, it will create an interference pattern or a particle-like pattern on a detector screen. The twist is that the decision of whether to measure which slit the particle passes through is delayed until after the particle has already passed through the slits and reached the detector.

3. Can Wheeler's delayed choice experiment actually be delayed?

Yes, the experiment has been successfully conducted in various forms in laboratories. The results have shown that the decision to measure or not measure the particle's path can indeed be delayed without affecting the outcome of the experiment.

4. What implications does Wheeler's delayed choice experiment have?

Wheeler's delayed choice experiment has raised questions about the nature of reality and the role of the observer in quantum mechanics. It suggests that the observer's actions can have an influence on the behavior of particles in the past, leading to discussions about the concept of free will and the possibility of multiple universes.

5. How is Wheeler's delayed choice experiment relevant to modern science?

Although the experiment was initially proposed as a thought experiment, its findings have been supported by numerous experiments and have been further explored in the fields of quantum mechanics and quantum computing. It continues to spark debates and encourage further research into the nature of reality and the role of the observer in scientific experiments.

Similar threads

Replies
4
Views
761
Replies
19
Views
886
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
729
Replies
18
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
164
Replies
16
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
629
Replies
18
Views
1K
Replies
5
Views
744
Replies
1
Views
594
Back
Top