Exploring the Homeomorphism between H^n and R^n

  • Thread starter Palindrom
  • Start date
In summary, the conversation discusses the difference between the topological spaces H^n and R^n, and whether or not they are homeomorphic. It is noted that H^n has a boundary while R^n does not. The concept of boundary in topological spaces is explored and it is concluded that the boundary of any topological space is always empty. The conversation also touches on the idea of removing points from spaces and how it can affect their topological properties. It is suggested that removing a point from R^n changes some of its qualitative topological properties, but this is not necessarily the case for H^n. However, it is also noted that removing points from H^n can also change its topological properties. The conversation ends with a request for a
  • #1
Palindrom
263
0
I'm trying to see why H^n is not homeo. to R^n.

I'm now having doubts on whether this is at all true.

Is it? If not, why not?

*By H^n I mean the closed "upper" space, i.e. x_n>=0.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
For one obvious point, Hn has a boundary and Rn doesn't. That is, neighborhoods of points (x, y, 0) are different from neighborhoods of (x, y, z) for z> 0. There is no way to homeomorphically map Rn to Hn that will respect that difference.
 
  • #3
But H^n has no boundary as a topological space. For any topological space X, the boundary of X is empty.

And why are the nhbds you mentioned different? A nhbd of a point with z>0 is homeo. to R^n, whereas a nhbd of a point with z=0 is homeo. to H^n. So that comes down to the same question: Why is H^n not homeo. to R^n?

You see my problem?
 
  • #4
Oh, come on, don't give up, help me out here...
 
  • #5
Palindrom said:
For any topological space X, the boundary of X is empty.

Consider the space [tex] X = (1,2) \cup (3,4) [/tex] in the standard order topology. BdX={1,2,3,4} is not empty.

-Dan
 
  • #6
topsquark, regarding (1,2) U (3,4) as a subset of R, it does have that boundary. But regarding X as a space itself, what Palindrom said is correct: For any topological space X, the boundary of X is empty.

The boundary of a set S in a topological space X is defined as:

[tex]Bd(S) = \overline{S} \cap \overline{X - S}[/tex]

So

[tex]Bd(X) = \overline{X} \cap \overline{X - X} = X \cap \overline{\emptyset} = X \cap \emptyset = \emptyset[/tex]
 
  • #7
The one-point compactification of R is homeomorphic to S1, and you can remove any point from S1 and still have a path-connected space (you will have something homeomorphic to (0,1), which is in fact homeomorphic to R). The one-point compactification of H is homeomorphic to, I believe, the interval I (i.e. the compact space [0, 1]). However, you can't just remove any point from I and be left with a path-connected space; in fact, if you remove any point except the extreme points, you won't even be left with a connected space.

Now you know that Rn = R x ... x R (n times), and you know that Hn = R x ... x R x H (where there are n-1 copies of R). So Rn and Hn differ by their nth factor, and we know that the nth factors are not homeomorphic, so can we use this to say that the product spaces are not homeomorphic? That is, can you argue that if A and B are not homeomorphic, then for any non-empty space X (for us, X = Rn-1), X x A and X x B are not homeomorphic?
 
  • #8
I don't think we need to go quite that far: removing any point from Rn changes some of its qualitative topological properties -- but you can remove points from Hn without said change.

I wanted to suggest something about removing a whole hyperplane, when is intuitively obvious, but it wasn't clear to me how the details would pan out. :frown:


By the way, XxA and XxB can be homeomorphic without A and B being homeomorphic.

As an example, let X be the product of infinitely many copies of R. Then, simply let A=R and B=R².

Or, as a simpler example, let X, A, and B all be discrete, A and B be nonempty with different cardinality, and X have infinite cardinality at least as much as both A and B.
 
Last edited:
  • #9
In general you cannot use Krull-Schmidt (cancellation) properties like that unless you prove they work. If we assumed they worked even in finite dimensional cases then there would be smooth vector fields on the sphere.
 
  • #10
AKG said:
topsquark, regarding (1,2) U (3,4) as a subset of R, it does have that boundary. But regarding X as a space itself, what Palindrom said is correct: For any topological space X, the boundary of X is empty.

The boundary of a set S in a topological space X is defined as:

[tex]Bd(S) = \overline{S} \cap \overline{X - S}[/tex]

So

[tex]Bd(X) = \overline{X} \cap \overline{X - X} = X \cap \overline{\emptyset} = X \cap \emptyset = \emptyset[/tex]

:uhh: (Ahem!) I knew that. :cry:

-Dan
 
  • #11
For every point in Euclidean space p, and for every open ball B about p, the boundary of B does not contain p. The same is not true for points in half-spaces, in particular, any point with nth coordinate 0 in a half-space is contained in the boundary of every ball containing it.

EDIT: No wait, that's wrong.

EDIT: Okay, I don't know how to make a full proof out of this, but I think that every isometric embedding of Rn-1 into Rn separates Rn in the sense that if Z denotes the image of this embedding, then Rn - Z is disconnected. On the other hand, the same does not hold for the half-space, in particular, then the image Z is the "bottom" of the space, i.e. Z is the set of points with nth co-ordinate 0. I think this is what Hurkyl might have been trying to get at with his idea about "removing a whole hyperplane".
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Hurkyl said:
I don't think we need to go quite that far: removing any point from Rn changes some of its qualitative topological properties -- but you can remove points from Hn without said change.

I wanted to suggest something about removing a whole hyperplane, when is intuitively obvious, but it wasn't clear to me how the details would pan out. :frown:


By the way, XxA and XxB can be homeomorphic without A and B being homeomorphic.

As an example, let X be the product of infinitely many copies of R. Then, simply let A=R and B=R².

Or, as a simpler example, let X, A, and B all be discrete, A and B be nonempty with different cardinality, and X have infinite cardinality at least as much as both A and B.
Please, just give me one property that is always changed by removing a point from R^n, but that there exists a point in H^n that when removed, doesn't change that property.

I also thought about the hyperplane thing for a minute, but then i saw I couldn't formalize it.

So then are they homeomorphic or not (clearly not, but why?)?
 
  • #13
R^n is contractible. R^n - {P} is not. (This was the first one that came to mind)

(By the way, you can't talk about an isometric embedding of R^{n-1} into R^n, because we haven't picked a metric!)
 
Last edited:
  • #14
Well we must have a topology, right? And that topology is bound to be the standard topology. But the standard topology is precisely the topology induced by the standard metric.
 
  • #15
How is [itex]\mathbb{H}^n - \{p\}[/itex] contractible? Wouldn't it be noncontractible for the same reasons [itex]\mathbb{R}^n - \{p\}[/itex] would be?
 
  • #16
AKG said:
Well we must have a topology, right? And that topology is bound to be the standard topology. But the standard topology is precisely the topology induced by the standard metric.
But the standard topology doesn't force the metric. Also, we're mainly interested in homeomorphisms, and they don't respect the metric.

Incidentally, I can pick metrics on the two spaces so that I can isometrically embed R^{n-1}-->R^n without disconnecting R^n.

e.g. on R^{n-1}, I can take the metric d(P,Q) = arctan(||P-Q||), where ||.|| is the usual Euclidean norm. Any isometric embedding of this into R^n would simply map it to an open ball of codimension 1 and radius pi/2. (e.g. if n=3, to a disk)

AKG said:
How is [itex]\mathbb{H}^n - \{p\}[/itex] contractible? Wouldn't it be noncontractible for the same reasons [itex]\mathbb{R}^n - \{p\}[/itex] would be?
Remove a "boundary" point of H^n. The resulting space is contractible.
 
  • #17
Hurkyl said:
Remove a "boundary" point of H^n. The resulting space is contractible.
I just read this definition today. So it means that the identity map is homotopic to a constant function. So you'd remove a point p from the "boundary". Then pick your constant function to be any point c "above" the "bottom" and have your homotopy to just map (x, t) to the point a distance of t||x-c|| from the point c in the direction of x, right? This works because from the point of view of c, there is nothing behind p, whereas a homotopy like this in Rn would end up trying to send points behind p to p itself?
 
  • #18
Actually, I was originally trying to think of something like this, but I was thinking of using the idea that some loops are not homotopic to a point in R² - p but they are in H² - p, but I couldn't think of how to generalize it to dimensions higher than 2.
 
  • #19
Right -- that explicit example proves R^n and H^n and H^n - {P} (with P on the boundary) are all contractible.

But contractions can be much more interesting -- for example, if X is three-quarters of an annulus, then X is contractible.

So, it's actually somewhat tricky to show R^n - {P} isn't contractible! But it is the approach I would take.

Actually, I was originally trying to think of something like this, but I was thinking of using the idea that some loops are not homotopic to a point in R² - p but they are in H² - p, but I couldn't think of how to generalize it to dimensions higher than 2.
And it would be based on this idea, by looking at a copy of S^{n-1} embedded in R^n such that P is in its interior.


Surely this problem can be easily done with homology. But, alas, there's only one homology theory with which I have even a rudimentary understanding, and I don't know if it can be applied to non-compact spaces! I suppose you could simply apply the one-point compactification, though. I was trying to avoid that!
 
  • #20
Hurkyl said:
So, it's actually somewhat tricky to show R^n - {P} isn't contractible!
I would think so. Thinking of homotopies of surfaces instead of functions now (or equivalently I guess, looking at functions from Sn-1 to Rn now instead of functions from Rn) then it would be easy to show that every imbedding of Sn-1 into the half-space minus a well-chosen point is null-homotopic but the same is not true of Euclidean space minus any point.
 
  • #21
Thinking back several years now I seem to recall that De Rham (co)homology with compact support will distinguish between these two spaces.
 
  • #22
I think I've got it, using a (famous) theorem we proved in class, that S^n isn't contractible. Tell me what you think:

Assume H^n and R^n are homeo. This induces a natural homeo. between their respective one point compactifications.
However, R^n's one point compactification is homeo. to S^n (by the stereo. projection), wheras by the same homeo., it is clear that H^n's one point compactification is homeo. to the subset of S^n for which x_n>=0.
Now, that last space is clearly homeo. to B^(n-1) (the n-1- ball), simply by the projection x_n=0, which is itself contractible! And this is a contradiction to the theorem I mentioned above, that S^n isn't contractible.

Seems O.K?
 
  • #23
Hn's one-point compactification is homeomorphic to the top half of Sn, which is the subset of Sn with xn+1 > 0, not xn > 0. The projection onto the first n co-ordinates (not n-1) gives the closed n-ball (not the n-1 ball) which is contractible.
 
  • #24
AKG said:
Hn's one-point compactification is homeomorphic to the top half of Sn, which is the subset of Sn with xn+1 > 0, not xn > 0. The projection onto the first n co-ordinates (not n-1) gives the closed n-ball (not the n-1 ball) which is contractible.
The subset of Sn with xn+1 > 0 is homeo. to the subset of Sn with xn > 0... And anyway, the contradiction still holds, as we've got two homeo. spaces, one is contractible and the other isn't, right?
 
  • #25
Palindrom said:
The subset of Sn with xn+1 > 0 is homeo. to the subset of Sn with xn > 0...
Right, but that's an unnatural way to look at it. You were probably thinking that xn is the last co-ordinate, which is why you though the projection xn = 0 gives the n-1 ball. If you want to regard the one-point compactification of the half space as the subset of the n sphere (which is subset of n+1 dimensional Euclidean space) with xn > 0 instead of the last coordinate xn+1 > 0, you have to still remember that the projection xn = 0 gives the (closed) n ball, not the n-1 ball. Of course, both of these are contractible.
And anyway, the contradiction still holds, as we've got two homeo. spaces, one is contractible and the other isn't, right?
Yes, the idea of the proof still works, there's just that small technical detail.
 
  • #26
Now I see what you meant, sorry!
And thanks!
 
  • #27
O.K, now I've been thinking about that one for a while, this is a generalization:

Can an open subset of R^n be homeomorphic to a non-open subset of R^n?
 
  • #28
Maybe try a simpler problem: can a path-connected non-open subset of R² be homeomorphic to the open unit disk? Can you argue that if A and B are homeomorphic, then so are AC and BC? If so, the comeplement of the open disk, A, is closed, and every sequence has a limit point in AC. The complement of a non-open subset B is non-closed, so it has some sequence that doesn't have a limit point in BC. Yeah, I don't know if this is a good way to go about it, but it may be a start.
 
Last edited:
  • #29
It's not true that if A and B are homeomorphic, then so are their complements; take [0,infty) and [0,1)- they are homeomorphic, but the first complement is connected while the other isn't...

And it would satisfy me to prove the simpler problem that you presented.:smile:
 
  • #30
Ah wait, you said R^2. I really want to work with R^n, R^2 won't satisfy me.
 
  • #31
Well start with R² and work your way up. Also, let A and B be bounded.
 
  • #32
Maybe an even "simpler" problem. Can [itex]B^n[/itex] be homeomorphic to [itex]A[/itex] if [itex]B^n \subset A \subset \overline{B^n}[/itex]? We don't want to look at the case [itex]B^n = A[/itex] since we are interested in cases where A is not open. We don't need to look at the case [itex]A = \overline{B^n}[/itex] since then A would be compact, but the open ball is not compact, so it's obvious that they're not homeomorphic. So if A is strictly contained between the ball and its closure, can it be homeomorphic to the ball?
 
  • #33
For R^2, I think I can prove what I need to prove, i.e. that H^n is not homeomorphic to any open subset of R^n.

Now, as for what you said, I'm not sure whether it'll help me to prove the above proposition, although it is an interesting question by itself.

Just for the record, I'm trying to show that a homeomorphism between manifolds with boundary takes the boundary onto the boundary. I'd really like to do it in the general topological case rather than in the smooth case, hence homeomorphisms and not diffeomorphisms.

That's what I have so far: If indeed H^n is homeomorphic to an open subset of R^n, then this subset must be contractible. It would then be enough to show that any contractible open subset of R^n is homeomorphic to R^n, as we've shown that R^n and H^n aren't homeomorphic.

Do you think I should still try your way, or will it not help my cause?

Any suggestions for my cause?
 
  • #34
I don't see why you can't just say that since, (1), for any homeomorphism f:A->B, and any subset U of A, U is homeomorphic to f(U), and (2), any point x in an open subset of Rn has a neighborhood homeomorphic to Rn, that any point y in B must also have a neighborhood homeomorphic to Rn, and so B must be open in Rn. Is there something wrong with this approach?
 
  • #35
StatusX

Trying your approach, let A and B be subsets of Euclidean space, A is open and f : A -> B is a homeomorphism. Let b be any point in B, and let a be its preimage. Since A is open, there is a ball U such that a is in U, and U is contained in A. U is homeomorphic to Euclidean space. Thus f(U) is a subset of B containing b, homeomorphic to Euclidean space. You want to argue that f(U), being homeomorphic to Euclidean space, must be an open subset of Euclidean space. This will allow you to argue that B is open. However, how do you know it? After all, isn't that more or less what we're trying to prove in the first place? You've reduced our problem from:

Can an open subset be homeomorphic to a non-open subset?

to

Can Euclidean space be homeomorphic to a non-open subset?

or equivalently:

Can the open ball be homeomorphic to a non-open subset?
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
6
Views
388
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
13
Views
966
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
1
Views
574
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
1
Views
513
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
2
Views
711
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
3
Views
570
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
15
Views
2K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
4
Views
835
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
7
Views
708
Back
Top