The Refutation of Bohmian Mechanics

In summary: Unfortunately, I did not have much time to study your paper in detail, but the claim is rather strong, so let me ask you something about your paper.1. Have you replied to the critique by Marchildon? (http://arxiv.org/PS_cache/quant-ph/pdf/0007/0007068v1.pdf )2. What is your opinion about the unitary evolution and the theory of measurement of quantum mechanics, strictly speaking, contradicting each other?1. My paper has not been published in a peer-reviewed journal.2. My opinion about the unitary evolution and the theory of measurement of quantum mechanics, strictly speaking, contradicting
  • #36
A. Neumaier said:
Only if the initial distribution matches exactly the required statistics, the outcomes are correct.
It was thought so in the past, but today it is known that this is not so. Even if the system starts with a different distribution, after a while it settles down towards the equilibrium distribution which coincides with the required quantum distribution. This is not a postulate, but a derived consequence of the Bohmian equations of motion.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
A. Neumaier said:
And if none is in the laboratory?

Wouldn't you have to treat all the possible devices anywhere in the world as pointer variables parameterizing the spin wave function?
I said "(or elsewhere in the real world)".
 
  • #38
Demystifier said:
I said "(or elsewhere in the real world)".

I understood that. Now there are lots of devices capable of measuring spins. Why are we allowed to treat the spin wave function to be psi(y) with just one pointer variable y rather than with one for each possible device?
 
  • #39
A. Neumaier said:
Thus Bohmian mechanics is no deterministic theory in the usual sense, since for its interpretation it needs to make assumptions of a stochastic nature that cannot be derived from the dynamics.

Arnold - everything you say here seems to be based on the one afternoon you spent studying deBB sometime in the mid 1990s - this just does not justify your supercilious tone. Things do move on.

Today it is well known that the assumptions you refer to are not assumptions (even though they were presented as such by Bohm and by the early textbooks) but arise as a natural consequence of the dynamics. If the particles are not distributed as the square of the wave function, then they will become so under de Broglie-Bohm dynamical evolution (they will approach 'quantum equilibrium').

http://arxiv.org/abs/1103.1589" [Broken] is a recent paper which demonstrates this particularly nicely.

Demystifier - I'm glad to see that you now contributing here. Looking back at the misinformation in this shocking thread it is good to see some posts from someone who knows what he is talking about. I'm only an amateur in deBB, and I thought you and zenith had given up (I know it must be very boring constantly having to refute ignorant arguments).
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #40
camboy said:
Today it is well known that the assumptions you refer to are not assumptions (even though they were presented as such by Bohm and by the early textbooks) but arise as a natural consequence of the dynamics. If the particles are not distributed as the square of the wave function, then they will become so under de Broglie-Bohm dynamical evolution (they will approach 'quantum equilibrium').
It doesn't for the ground state of the harmonic oscillator.
camboy said:
http://arxiv.org/abs/1103.1589" [Broken] is a recent paper which demonstrates this particularly nicely.
A numerical simulation of a particular, simple case (as given in that paper) is no proof of your claim that ''If the particles are not distributed as the square of the wave function, then they will become so under de Broglie-Bohm dynamical evolution (they will approach 'quantum equilibrium').''

So now we have one example of analytically demonstrated non-approach to quantum equilibrium and one numerical simulation of approach to quantum equilibrium.

The paper starts off saying:
According to a recently-published (2008) encyclopedia of quantum mechanics [2] ''the conclusion seems to be that no generally accepted derivation of the Born rule has been given to date, but this does not imply that such a derivation is impossible in principle".
The counterexample of the ground state of the harmonic oscillator shows that such a derivation is impossible in principle.

Remark (1) on p.5 is also illuminating in that it shows that there are many inequivalent ontologies producing the same quantum equilibrium. At most one of them can be the real ontology. But all variants are (according to the Bohmian dogma) observationally fully equivalent to standard quantum mechanics. Thus it would be impossible to distingush between them experimentally. In stark contrast to what the remark (1) says.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #41
A. Neumaier said:
It doesn't for the ground state of the harmonic oscillator.

It doesn't for any stationary ground-state of any system, but that's precisely the point - the 'simple example' given in the paper is of a non-stationary state.

In the extremely unlikely event of your harmonic oscillator having existed since the beginning of the universe as a stationary ground state without ever being perturbed by anything ever, then of course it is possible that it will still be out of quantum equilibrium. It's always possible to do that for a fake model system that exists all by itself in your imaginary universe.

However, the real universe has had a long and violent astrophysical history, which is why essentially every real subsystem we see today is in quantum equilibrium.
A numerical simulation of a particular, simple case (as given in that paper) is no proof of your claim that ''If the particles are not distributed as the square of the wave function, then they will become so under de Broglie-Bohm dynamical evolution (they will approach 'quantum equilibrium').''

It doesn't claim to be. The numerical simulation is an illustrative example which they use to compute timescales for relaxation to quantum equilibrium. More complicated systems would be expected to relax more quickly.

Without bothering to repeat them in their entirety, the article refers to well-known arguments that justify the expectation that all systems will relax to quantum equilibrium, subjet to certain assumptions about the initial conditions of the universe having no-fine grained microstructure (see references 1, 16, 20, 21). In this way, it is entirely analagous to the normal Boltzmann argument regarding relaxation to thermal equilibrium in classical statistical mechanics, and is as well established. It is merely a consequence of the fact that the particle distribution being equal to psi-squared has the maximum entropy.
So now we have one example of analytically demonstrated non-approach to quantum equilibrium and one numerical simulation of approach to quantum equilibrium.

No we don't, you're tossing off authorative-sounding arguments about something you've spent about 30 seconds reading, in an attempt to sound like you know what you're talking about.
The counterexample of the ground state of the harmonic oscillator shows that such a derivation is impossible in principle.

No it doesn't. You've merely artificially eliminated the mechanism responsible for relaxation to the Born rule, and pretended that this is the general case.
Remark (1) on p.5 is also illuminating in that it shows that there are many inequivalent ontologies producing the same quantum equilibrium. At most one of them can be the real ontology. But all variants are (according to the Bohmian dogma) observationally fully equivalent to standard quantum mechanics. Thus it would be impossible to distingush between them experimentally. In stark contrast to what the remark (1) says.

No it isn't impossible. Remark (1) itself points out that it is possible away from quantum equilibrium.

So, all your points are wrong. Want to try again?
 
  • #42
camboy said:
No it isn't impossible. Remark (1) itself points out that it is possible away from quantum equilibrium.
If quantum nonequilibrium is possible then Bohmian mechanics deviates from standard QM.

But Bohmian mechnics claims to be equivalent to standard QM. You cannot have the cake and eat it.
 
  • #43
A. Neumaier said:
If quantum nonequilibrium is possible then Bohmian mechanics deviates from standard QM.

But Bohmian mechnics claims to be equivalent to standard QM. You cannot have the cake and eat it.
The precise statement is:
Measurable statistical predictions of Bohmian mechanics IN QUANTUM EQUILIBRIUM are equivalent to those of standard QM.

BM also allows a possibility of being OUT of quantum equilibrium, but it does not predict that an out-of-equilibrium situation must occur. In fact, an out-of-equilibrium situation is a situation which, according to BM, is very difficult to achieve in practice.
 
Last edited:
  • #44
A. Neumaier said:
Why are we allowed to treat the spin wave function to be psi(y) with just one pointer variable y rather than with one for each possible device?
Because a device modeled by a single pointer variable y is a good approximation, in the sense that nothing substantially changes if more pointer variables are added. No matter how many variables you add, you always get that the statistical distribution of the relevant variables (i.e., those variables the wave functions of which interact strongly with the measured system) is equal to the statistical distribution predicted by standard QM.
 
  • #45
Demystifier said:
The precise statement is:
Measurable statistical predictions of Bohmian mechanics IN QUANTUM EQUILIBRIUM are equivalent to those of standard QM.

I conclude from your salomonic phrasing that, in general, Bohmian mechanics is _not_ equivalent to standard QM. Thus deviations are possible and should be looked for.

Note that Boltzmann's derivation of the approach to equilibrium need very stringent assumptions (ergodicity) that are only satisfied for few model systems. The universe (or even a flower) is far from being in equilibrium.

On the other hand, QM is universally applicable, even to flowers. Thus to establish practical equivalence of Bohmian mechanics with QM, one would need to show that quantum equilibrium holds for the whole universe and all its parts to which QM is applied. This cannot be done by a simple maximum entropy argument.
 
  • #46
A. Neumaier said:
It doesn't for the ground state of the harmonic oscillator.
But it does for the ground state of the harmonic oscillator INTERACTING WITH A SUFFICIENTLY COMPLEX MEASURING APPARATUS. But it turns out that realistic measuring apparatuses are ALWAYS sufficiently complex.
 
  • #47
Demystifier said:
Because a device modeled by a single pointer variable y is a good approximation, in the sense that nothing substantially changes if more pointer variables are added. No matter how many variables you add, you always get that the statistical distribution of the relevant variables (i.e., those variables the wave functions of which interact strongly with the measured system) is equal to the statistical distribution predicted by standard QM.

Which of the many existing pointer variables is the correct one? In particular, what is the correct model if no measurment device is close to the quantum system? Or if one removes one device in favor for another one?

Moreover, by this interpretation, spin is not a property of the particles but of the pointer!
This is very counterintuitive.

Suppose you do a long quantum calculation on a quantum computer, and decide at the very end what you are going to measure and with which device. Then according to the spin ontology, the whole quantum computer becomes an ontological property of the incidentally used measuring device...

A very strange world view, indeed.
 
  • #48
Demystifier said:
But it does for the ground state of the harmonic oscillator INTERACTING WITH A SUFFICIENTLY COMPLEX MEASURING APPARATUS.
Making claims is easy. Do you have a proof of that? (Not just a numerical simulation with a single pointer variable.)
 
  • #49
A. Neumaier said:
I conclude from your salomonic phrasing that, in general, Bohmian mechanics is _not_ equivalent to standard QM. Thus deviations are possible and should be looked for.
Yes, I agree with that.

A. Neumaier said:
Note that Boltzmann's derivation of the approach to equilibrium need very stringent assumptions (ergodicity) that are only satisfied for few model systems. The universe (or even a flower) is far from being in equilibrium.
First, one should distinguish quantum equilibrium from the (more familiar) thermodynamic equilibrium.

Second, even though we apparently do not live in the thermodynamic equilibrium, the fact is that we don't know why. It is one of the unsolved questions in statistical physics (and cosmology). Purely statistical arguments lead to the conclusion that we should expect to find nature much closer to the thermodynamic equilibrium than we actually do.

A. Neumaier said:
On the other hand, QM is universally applicable, even to flowers. Thus to establish practical equivalence of Bohmian mechanics with QM, one would need to show that quantum equilibrium holds for the whole universe and all its parts to which QM is applied. This cannot be done by a simple maximum entropy argument.
Actually, the simple maximum-entropy argument is enough. The fact that we (seem to) live in a quantum equilibrium is not surprising at all. What is surprising is that we don't live in a thermodynamic equilibrium.
 
  • #50
A. Neumaier said:
Do you have a proof of that? (Not just a numerical simulation with a single pointer variable.)
Yes, and it can be found in many textbooks and reviews of BM. In particular, Chapter. 8 of
P. R. Holland, The Quantum Theory of Motion
is especially well written. If you REALLY want to understand how the theory of quantum measurements works, I highly recommend to read this chapter.
 
  • #51
Dr. Neumaier,

I wonder - do you ever admit that you are wrong about anything ever? Essentially every statement of fact that you have made in this article has been shown to be due to a misunderstanding on your part seemingly due to your never having read any of the literature. And yet, you never say "Oh, thank you, Demystifer/camboy etc. for pointing that out to me". You just carry on to the next spurious thing "And what about this, what about that?" That's wrong too "So what about the other?".

It is not our responsibility to read the literature for you. And yet, from the beginning of this thread, you have made pompous statements implying that everyone who studies de Broglie-Bohm theory is an idiot. If you were not a respected Professor of Quantum Physics, and a writer of FAQS which are promoted by Physics Forums, this wouldn't matter, but you are and it does. As far as I'm concerned, you seem to be abusing your position to try to destroy a subfield of QM which happens not to accord wih your personal views and research goals. Students and even ordinary physicists who happen not to have read anything about deBB will quite naturally believe every weighty pronouncement that you make. More fool them.

Your ridiculous statements that "it doesn't matter that my opinion of deBB has not been published in the peer-reviewed literature" because "my views are so obviously correct" is not only pompous, but arrogant and self-serving. You are so used to people grovelling at you, that you have forgotten the responsibility that such a position brings. Now if I was a moderator, I would ban you. But of course, they're going to now ban me for being rude to you. Well so be it - someone has to say it.
 
  • #52
A. Neumaier said:
Which of the many existing pointer variables is the correct one?
As I said, any and each one which strongly interacts with the measured system.

A. Neumaier said:
In particular, what is the correct model if no measurment device is close to the quantum system?
If no macroscopic measurement device is close to the measured quantum system, then no macroscopic measurement device can measure this quantum system (because there is no strong interaction). So in this case none of them is "correct".

A. Neumaier said:
Or if one removes one device in favor for another one?
The one (or more) which interacts strongly with the measured system, is the correct one.

A. Neumaier said:
Moreover, by this interpretation, spin is not a property of the particles but of the pointer!
That's true.

A. Neumaier said:
This is very counterintuitive.
Maybe to you, but to me other interpretations of QM are even more counterintuitive.

A. Neumaier said:
Suppose you do a long quantum calculation on a quantum computer, and decide at the very end what you are going to measure and with which device. Then according to the spin ontology, the whole quantum computer becomes an ontological property of the incidentally used measuring device...
Not exactly. Other devices and objects in the universe are also ontological, both before and after the measurement. However, only this particular device is strongly correlated with the microscopic degrees of the quantum computer. That's because, as I said many times above, only this particular device strongly interacted with the microscopic quantum-computer degrees.
 
  • #53
camboy said:
Demystifier - I'm glad to see that you now contributing here. Looking back at the misinformation in this shocking thread it is good to see some posts from someone who knows what he is talking about. I'm only an amateur in deBB, and I thought you and zenith had given up (I know it must be very boring constantly having to refute ignorant arguments).
Thanks, camboy! I see that your understanding of deBB is also very good.
 
  • #54
Demystifier said:
First, one should distinguish quantum equilibrium from the (more familiar) thermodynamic equilibrium.
Of course they are different. But the thesis about BM+quantum computing was using the statistical mechanics analogy.
Demystifier said:
Second, even though we apparently do not live in the thermodynamic equilibrium, the fact is that we don't know why. It is one of the unsolved questions in statistical physics (and cosmology). Purely statistical arguments lead to the conclusion that we should expect to find nature much closer to the thermodynamic equilibrium than we actually do.
No. There is nothing surprising in that we don't have thermal equilibrium. In statistical mechanics, The proof that equilibrium must be obtained is restricted to the very stringent assumption of ergodicity. Very few real systems are ergodic. Equilibrium is reserved for special systems that are more or less homogeneous.
Demystifier said:
Actually, the simple maximum-entropy argument is enough.
No. There must also be proof that entropy always increases, and that it increases to its maximum.
This is highly nontrivial in statistical mechanics, and wrong for most complex systems. Nature is full of systems that never reach the maximum entropy state.

It would be very surprising if the situation were different for quantum equilibrium, and that it is achieved without such stringent conditions. Can you point to an online source for the proof?
 
  • #55
camboy said:
do you ever admit that you are wrong about anything ever?
If I see that I was wrong, I correct myself immediately. Thus any state of being wrong is very short-lived. If I repeat assertions that seem wrong to you then only because your arguments did not convince me.
camboy said:
to your never having read any of the literature.
You have not the slightest idea about how much literature I have read and how much I am reading
while preparing my contributions to this forum.
camboy said:
And yet, you never say "Oh, thank you, Demystifer/camboy etc. for pointing that out to me".
Scientific dispute takes the free offering of information as a given that doesn't need special thanks.
I also do not expect being thanked for the information I provide on this forum.
camboy said:
from the beginning of this thread, you have made pompous statements implying that everyone who studies de Broglie-Bohm theory is an idiot.
Please take this back. I never said such a thing.
camboy said:
If you were not a respected Professor of Quantum Physics,
You seem to say a lot without first checking the facts. I am not a professor of quantum physics.
camboy said:
Your ridiculous statements that "it doesn't matter that my opinion of deBB has not been published in the peer-reviewed literature" because "my views are so obviously correct"
I didn't say such a thing.
 
  • #56
Demystifier said:
If no macroscopic measurement device is close to the measured quantum system, then no macroscopic measurement device can measure this quantum system (because there is no strong interaction). So in this case none of them is "correct".
.
But the system still has a dynamics. Though apparently not one easily described by BM.
 
  • #57
A. Neumaier said:
Of course they are different. But the thesis about BM+quantum computing was using the statistical mechanics analogy.

No. There is nothing surprising in that we don't have thermal equilibrium. In statistical mechanics, The proof that equilibrium must be obtained is restricted to the very stringent assumption of ergodicity. Very few real systems are ergodic. Equilibrium is reserved for special systems that are more or less homogeneous.

No. There must also be proof that entropy always increases, and that it increases to its maximum.
This is highly nontrivial in statistical mechanics, and wrong for most complex systems. Nature is full of systems that never reach the maximum entropy state.

It would be very surprising if the situation were different for quantum equilibrium, and that it is achieved without such stringent conditions. Can you point to an online source for the proof?
OK, now we are at the territory of statistical mechanics. In statistical mechanics there is a Boltzmann H-theorem that provides that entropy never decreases. Perhaps this theorem is not perfectly rigorous (it does not use ergodicity), but in Bohmian mechanics there is an analogous equally (non)rigorous theorem that entropy measuring closeness to the quantum equilibrium also never decreases. So what we have in BM are
1) A theorem, probably not perfectly rigorous, and
2) Many explicit numerical simulations which agree with the theorem
I can agree that more work is needed in order to establish a completely satisfying proof, but the above is certainly a strong evidence (if not the proof).
 
  • #58
A. Neumaier said:
But the system still has a dynamics.
Of course.

A. Neumaier said:
Though apparently not one easily described by BM.
Why do you think so?
 
  • #59
Demystifier said:
Another, more general, point is at the heart of BM: Any observation eventaually is an observation of a POSITION variable (at the macroscopic level). This is why the Bohmian trickery is applicable in any situation
When we hear something, it can count as an observation, though no position variable is observed.

When we see a star, which position variable do we observe?
 
  • #60
Demystifier said:
Why do you think so?
Because, as you said, none of the pointer variables is ''correct''. How else would you then describe the dynamics of an unobserved system of spins?
 
  • #61
A. Neumaier said:
When we hear something, it can count as an observation, though no position variable is observed.
Oh, yes it is. When your ear hears something, the nerves in your ear vibrate. And vibration is nothing but a change of a POSITIONS of parts of an elastic object.

A. Neumaier said:
When we see a star, which position variable do we observe?
The position of nerves in the eye.

Of course, it's not that you really "observe" these positions in the psychological sense, but the point is that colors and sounds are ENCODED in the positions of something.
 
  • #62
Demystifier said:
OK, now we are at the territory of statistical mechanics. In statistical mechanics there is a Boltzmann H-theorem that provides that entropy never decreases. Perhaps this theorem is not perfectly rigorous (it does not use ergodicity),
It assumes instead the Stosszahlansatz, which is taken as an unproved assumption.
(For a gas of hard spheres, the Stosszahlansatz can be justified by an ergodic theorem).

Moreover, stating that entropy doesn't decrease is very far from stating that entropy reaches its global maximum (the equilibrium state). For example, one can deduce from the Boltzmann equations in some approximation the Euler equations - there the total entropy is constant, but the dynamics is still highly nontrivial - very far from the equilibrium state. Thus the H-theorem says nothing at all about approach to equilibrium. (In simple terms: if I am climbing a hill and never go downwards, I can still end up anywhere above my current position, no matter how long I wait. No guarantee to reach the hill top.)

Finally, Boltzmann's approach only works for the classical ideal gas.
Demystifier said:
but in Bohmian mechanics there is an analogous equally (non)rigorous theorem that entropy measuring closeness to the quantum equilibrium also never decreases. So what we have in BM are
1) A theorem, probably not perfectly rigorous, and
2) Many explicit numerical simulations which agree with the theorem
I can agree that more work is needed in order to establish a completely satisfying proof, but the above is certainly a strong evidence (if not the proof).
It is as much evidence for reaching quantum equilibrium as Boltzmann's H-therorem is evidence for the universe being in global equilibrium - nil!
 
  • #63
A. Neumaier said:
Because, as you said, none of the pointer variables is ''correct''. How else would you then describe the dynamics of an unobserved system of spins?
Bohmian mechanics describes the dynamics of wave functions and particle positions, period. It does that both for observed and unobserved systems. However, Bohmian mechanics, at the fundamental level, does not describe the dynamics of spins or any other "observables". It is only in the context of specific measurements that certain configurations of particles and wave functions can be INTERPRETED as spins or other "observables".

Just as classical optics is only about electromagnetic waves and not about colors, even though some wavelengths can be interpreted as colors in specific measurement configurations.
 
  • #64
A. Neumaier said:
It is as much evidence for reaching quantum equilibrium as Boltzmann's H-therorem is evidence for the universe being in global equilibrium
With that I agree ...

A. Neumaier said:
- nil!
... but with that I don't. Anyway, I am glad that now you have a clearer picture what BM, in its current state of development, has achieved and what it has not. Just because some branch of science is not fully developed yet, it is not a reason to abandon it.
 
  • #65
Demystifier said:
Oh, yes it is. When your ear hears something, the nerves in your ear vibrate. And vibration is nothing but a change of a POSITIONS of parts of an elastic object.


The position of nerves in the eye.

Of course, it's not that you really "observe" these positions in the psychological sense, but the point is that colors and sounds are ENCODED in the positions of something.

Ah. So the only pointer variables that count are those in the head of people. For if we observe the pointer of an instrument, all we really observe is also the position of nerves in the eye?

And I never before heard that the nerves in the eye move in response to light. What moves are the electrons inside the eye. But these are not a ''POSITION variable (at the macroscopic level)''.
 
  • #66
Demystifier said:
Bohmian mechanics describes the dynamics of wave functions and particle positions, period. It does that both for observed and unobserved systems.

My question was - how, for an unobserved spin system. Your dogmatic position is of no help in answering that.
 
  • #67
Demystifier said:
With that I agree ...... but with that I don't.

If the Boltzmann's H-therorem were any evidence for the universe being in global equilibrium then
e would observe this global equilibrium - which means we wouldn't exist, contradiction.

Thus the Boltzmann's H-therorem is no evidence at all evidence for reaching global equilibrium, and because you agreed to the first part of my statement, you have also no evidence for that the state of the universe reached quantum equilibrium in BM.
 
  • #68
A. Neumaier said:
Ah. So the only pointer variables that count are those in the head of people.
Not only they, but if you want to understand how something is observed by a human, then you cannot avoid them. They are crucial.

A. Neumaier said:
For if we observe the pointer of an instrument, all we really observe is also the position of nerves in the eye?
Irrespective of one's favored interpretation of QM, that is eventually so.

A. Neumaier said:
And I never before heard that the nerves in the eye move in response to light.
They don't, but the positions of the excited nerves determine the picture you will eventually see.
 
  • #69
A. Neumaier said:
If the Boltzmann's H-therorem were any evidence for the universe being in global equilibrium then
e would observe this global equilibrium - which means we wouldn't exist, contradiction.
Irrespective of physics, this chain of reasoning is logically totally wrong.
Namely, if A is some evidence for B, it does not mean that A implies B.
For example, being in grave is an evidence for being dead, but you can still be in grave without being dead.

Anyway, perhaps we are a statistical fluctuation?
 
Last edited:
  • #70
A. Neumaier said:
My question was - how, for an unobserved spin system.
I'm not sure what kind of an answer do you expect here. Perhaps the straightest answer is: through the Schrodinger (or Schrodinger-Pauli, or Dirac, or Maxwell ...) equation and the associated equation for the particle trajectories - of the isolated system.
 
Last edited:
<h2>1. What is Bohmian Mechanics?</h2><p>Bohmian Mechanics is a theory in quantum mechanics that proposes a deterministic interpretation of quantum mechanics. It was developed by David Bohm in the 1950s as an alternative to the Copenhagen interpretation.</p><h2>2. How does Bohmian Mechanics differ from other interpretations of quantum mechanics?</h2><p>Bohmian Mechanics differs from other interpretations in that it posits the existence of hidden variables that determine the behavior of quantum particles. This is in contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, which states that quantum particles do not have definite properties until they are observed.</p><h2>3. What is the refutation of Bohmian Mechanics?</h2><p>The refutation of Bohmian Mechanics refers to the arguments and evidence that have been presented against this theory. These include the Bell's Inequality theorem, which suggests that hidden variables cannot explain all of the phenomena observed in quantum mechanics.</p><h2>4. Is Bohmian Mechanics widely accepted in the scientific community?</h2><p>No, Bohmian Mechanics is not widely accepted in the scientific community. While it has some proponents, the majority of physicists and scientists favor other interpretations of quantum mechanics, such as the Copenhagen interpretation or the Many-Worlds interpretation.</p><h2>5. What are the implications of the refutation of Bohmian Mechanics?</h2><p>The refutation of Bohmian Mechanics has significant implications for our understanding of quantum mechanics and the nature of reality. It suggests that the universe may be inherently probabilistic and that the behavior of quantum particles cannot be fully explained by deterministic theories.</p>

1. What is Bohmian Mechanics?

Bohmian Mechanics is a theory in quantum mechanics that proposes a deterministic interpretation of quantum mechanics. It was developed by David Bohm in the 1950s as an alternative to the Copenhagen interpretation.

2. How does Bohmian Mechanics differ from other interpretations of quantum mechanics?

Bohmian Mechanics differs from other interpretations in that it posits the existence of hidden variables that determine the behavior of quantum particles. This is in contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, which states that quantum particles do not have definite properties until they are observed.

3. What is the refutation of Bohmian Mechanics?

The refutation of Bohmian Mechanics refers to the arguments and evidence that have been presented against this theory. These include the Bell's Inequality theorem, which suggests that hidden variables cannot explain all of the phenomena observed in quantum mechanics.

4. Is Bohmian Mechanics widely accepted in the scientific community?

No, Bohmian Mechanics is not widely accepted in the scientific community. While it has some proponents, the majority of physicists and scientists favor other interpretations of quantum mechanics, such as the Copenhagen interpretation or the Many-Worlds interpretation.

5. What are the implications of the refutation of Bohmian Mechanics?

The refutation of Bohmian Mechanics has significant implications for our understanding of quantum mechanics and the nature of reality. It suggests that the universe may be inherently probabilistic and that the behavior of quantum particles cannot be fully explained by deterministic theories.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
11
Replies
370
Views
9K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
5
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
49
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
9
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
13
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
92
Views
7K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
4
Replies
109
Views
8K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
5
Replies
159
Views
10K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
3K
Back
Top