The Validity of Force and Point Particles in Special Relativity

In summary, the discussion is about getting rid of the concept of relativistic mass. The author suggests that relativistic mass is a moral link between the new theories which deal primarily in fields, and the old theories in which point particles and forces were ok. They argue that without relativistic mass, force and point particles are not useful in the same way. However, the author thinks that the future of gravitation theory will go back to the force point of view.
  • #36
atyy said:
Yes, I think I need at least two vectors to slot into the Faraday tensor to make a scalar.

BTW, now that we established that the E field is as real or as fake as the inertial mass, why is the latter considered so much more pedagogically harmful than the former?

We get ever more philosophical. I have never considered relativistic mass to be inertial mass (who ever heard or transverse versus longitudinal inertial mass). To me, the temptation to treat relativistic mass as inertial mass comes from using the 'wrong' formula.

However, I get your main point. E could be obsoleted (and I note that Penrose, in all his discussions of EM in "Road to Reality" uses only F, not E or B). Yet most people (myself included) still find E and B useful.

In sum, I'll grant you:

touche.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
atyy said:
Yes, I think I need at least two vectors to slot into the Faraday tensor to make a scalar.

Yes. One would be your 4-velocity, the other would be the 4-velocity of the "measuring instrument"; a better term would probably be "test particle", since in general we measure EM fields by watching the acceleration (i.e., the instantaneous change in 4-velocity) of test particles.
 
  • #38
PeterDonis said:
But the theory of gravity as a "real force" is a field theory; it's the theory of a massless spin-2 field, or the fancier versions given in string theory (is string theory one of the "modern and satisfactory theories of gravity"?), which are also field theories, just not field theories based on point particles. If the original massless spin-2 field theory is only an "effective" theory, are the string theory versions "effective" too?

Other "modern" theories of gravity (I don't know whether you consider them "satisfactory"), such as loop quantum gravity, don't look to me like theories of gravity as a "real force"; they look more like theories of geometry.

Correct, the field theory of gravity treats gravity as a real force associated to a gravitational field. The popular stringy claim that GR is a spin-2 field is a myth (already Wald warns his readers a bit about this myth).

But we can go beyond the limits of field theory toward a fundamental action-at-a-distance theory of gravity.

Two main alternatives are available on the literature: (i) the adaptation to gravity by Schieve and coworkers of the Stuckelberg-Horwitz-Piron theory and (ii) the adaptation to gravity of the action-at-a-distance electrodynamics of Wheeler & Feynman.

Note: I do not discuss superstring-M theory, LQG, and similar nonsenses in quantum gravity literature.
 
Last edited:
  • #39
juanrga said:
Correct, the field theory of gravity treats gravity as a real force associated to a gravitational field. The popular stringy claim that GR is a spin-2 field is a myth (already Wald warns his readers a bit about this myth).

I'm not sure what "myth" you're referring to; can you give a specific reference in Wald? It's known that the theory of a massless spin-2 field on a flat spacetime background yields the exact Einstein-Hilbert Lagrangian; that's what I was referring to as the theory of gravity as a massless spin-2 field. String theory basically claims that the ground state of a closed string loop looks like a massless spin-2 field on distance scales that are large compared to the string size, but you made it clear that you don't consider string theory to be a "modern and satisfactory" theory of gravity, so we can leave that out of the discussion.

juanrga said:
Two main alternatives are available on the literature: (i) the adaptation to gravity by Schieve and coworkers of the Stuckelberg-Horwitz-Piron theory and (ii) the adaptation to gravity of the action-at-a-distance electrodynamics of Wheeler & Feynman.

Can you give any references? I'm not familiar with these theoretical efforts, but they sound interesting.
 
  • #40
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure what "myth" you're referring to; can you give a specific reference in Wald? It's known that the theory of a massless spin-2 field on a flat spacetime background yields the exact Einstein-Hilbert Lagrangian; that's what I was referring to as the theory of gravity as a massless spin-2 field. String theory basically claims that the ground state of a closed string loop looks like a massless spin-2 field on distance scales that are large compared to the string size, but you made it clear that you don't consider string theory to be a "modern and satisfactory" theory of gravity, so we can leave that out of the discussion.

Can you give any references? I'm not familiar with these theoretical efforts, but they sound interesting.

Wald explains, in his well-known textbook on general relativity, that the popular claim that GR is equivalent to the theory of a massless spin-2 field on a flat spacetime background makes no sense beyond linearized GR.

I would say more than him, linearized GR is only pseudo-equivalent to the theory of a massless spin-2 field on a flat spacetime background.

An introduction to the classical version of the SHP theory that includes the gravitational counterpart of the original electromagnetic interaction is given in

Classical Relativistic Many-Body Dynamics 1999: Springer. Trump, Matthew A.; Schieve, William C.

A presentation of the extension of wheeler and Feynman action-at-a-distance electrodynamics to gravitation is given in

Gravitational interaction in the relational approach 2008: Grav. and Cosm. 14(1), 41—52. Vladimirov, Yu. S.
 
  • #41
atyy said:
Point particles can't exist in GR (unless they are black holes). So point particles only appear as an approximation, before which there are no forces (again, there isn't a fundamental concept of inertial mass).

Would it be ok to think of them as wormholes connecting two times, the present and big bang?
 
  • #42
juanrga said:
Wald explains, in his well-known textbook on general relativity, that the popular claim that GR is equivalent to the theory of a massless spin-2 field on a flat spacetime background makes no sense beyond linearized GR.

I'll have to dig out my copy to see what he says; I don't remember reading this (but it's been quite some time since I looked at Wald's textbook). I know that in the Feynman Lectures on Gravitation, which is where I first read about the massless spin-2 field theory, Feynman proves that the Lagrangian of that theory correct to *all* orders (not just linearized order) is the Einstein-Hilbert Lagrangian. (At that point, of course, the flat background is "unobservable"; that actual physical metric is the curved metric. Maybe that's what Wald was referring to.)

Thanks for the other references, I'll look them up.
 
  • #45
PeterDonis said:
I'll have to dig out my copy to see what he says; I don't remember reading this (but it's been quite some time since I looked at Wald's textbook). I know that in the Feynman Lectures on Gravitation, which is where I first read about the massless spin-2 field theory, Feynman proves that the Lagrangian of that theory correct to *all* orders (not just linearized order) is the Einstein-Hilbert Lagrangian. (At that point, of course, the flat background is "unobservable"; that actual physical metric is the curved metric. Maybe that's what Wald was referring to.)

Thanks for the other references, I'll look them up.

If my memory does not fail, Wald main argument was that the concept «spin 2 field» requires a background metric to be defined precisely and beyond linearized GR, the concept has not meaning (it is a vacuous word as «pertribvb 9-tredx»).

Feynman lectures are completely wrong. He does not proves such stuff. His claim that GR has both a geometrical and a field description are without any support.

A correct treatment shows that GR is different from the field theory, which is not strange the first is a geometric theory the second is physical one. Feynman confounds the curved spacetime metric with the effective metric derived from the field among other basic stuff.

See also http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0409089 for other myths
 
  • #47
Plenty to digest, thanks PAllen and juanrga for the links. It looks to me like we might as well let Deser and his critics fight it out; I doubt we're going to settle anything here.
 
  • #48
Padmanabhan does not dispute gravity=spin 2. His reservations are on the point of uniqueness. I think uniqueness for the geometric point of view was proved only in the 1970s by Lovelock.
 
  • #49
PAllen said:
Adding to the mix, Deser strongly disputes these critiques, and reasserts his claims in:

http://arxiv.org/abs/0910.2975

He avoids the criticism about (GR ≠ spin-2 field) cited here and only offers a partial dispute with Padmanabhan work also cited here
 
  • #50
Pitts and Schieve seem to have no disagreement that gravity=spin 2. All the questions are about exactly what assumptions are needed to obtain uniqueness.
 
  • #51
PeterDonis said:
You may be implicitly switching between two views of "inertial forces" here. Strictly speaking, there is a key physical difference between "inertial forces" and "real forces": real forces are actually felt as acceleration; inertial forces are not. This is modeled in differential geometry as the covariant derivative of a worldline: it's zero for a body moving solely due to "inertial forces", but nonzero for a body subject to "real forces".

But often when we talk about "inertial forces", we forget that the actual "force" we feel is not due to the inertial force itself; it's due to the real force that is pushing us out of the geodesic path that the inertial force would have us follow. I feel a force sitting here on the surface of the Earth, and speaking loosely I might say this is the "force of gravity": but actually it's not, it's the force of the Earth pushing on me. A rock falling past me is moving due to the "force of gravity", but it feels no force. The principle of equivalence does not require me to say that I and the rock are equivalent; so IMO it doesn't require me to say that inertial forces and "real" forces are equivalent either.

In the Newtonian concept, in order to get forces to transform via the Galilean transformation, gravity has to be considered to be a force - you can't omit it and keep the tensor nature of forces. Taking the example of standing on the Earth, if your feet were pushing on you that hard, and there was no gravity, you'd be flung into the air. Let me stress again that this is the Newtonian viewpont I'm discussing.

The equivalence of gravitational and inertial mass in the Newtonian theory was noticed for a long time. I believe it's accurate to say that this equality between gravitational and inertial masses gave the equivalence principle it's very name, though I don't have a reference.

Now, the equivalence principle is vague enough where you could still take the position that this equivalence is some sort of happy accident, but if you start to believe it's not just a coincidence, I think you're more or less drawn to the position I mentioned. I.e. you start to think that inertial forces are the same gravitational forces, and you already know that the inertial forces don't transform properly, i.e. like tensors. As I mentioned, you also know that gravitational forces need to be included as "real" forces in the Newtonian viewpoint.

I suppose it is also self consistent to think of gravity as being a "curvature of space time" and in no ways a force, which seems to be your suggestion. So then you do get to keep all the other forces as tensors, and you insist that gravity is "not a force".
 
Last edited:
  • #52
pervect said:
The equivalence of gravitational and inertial mass in the Newtonian theory was noticed for a long time. I believe it's accurate to say that this equality between gravitational and inertial masses gave the equivalence principle it's very name, though I don't have a reference.

Now, the equivalence principle is vague enough where you could still take the position that this equivalence is some sort of happy accident, but if you start to believe it's not just a coincidence, I think you're more or less drawn to the position I mentioned. I.e. you start to think that inertial forces are the same gravitational forces, and you already know that the inertial forces don't transform properly, i.e. like tensors. As I mentioned, you also know that gravitational forces need to be included as "real" forces. I think you get into quite a muddle, until you take the position that none of the forces were tensors under the most general sorts of coordinate transformations, and you've been making them look like tensors by considering a restricted set of transformations. Which is OK and self-consistent and even traditional, but if you want to open up the playing field to treating all sorts of transformations equivalently, you need to sacrifice the idea that forces are tensors. And you also then sacrifice the notion of inertial frames being "special", but I think this later part is or less a plus, you have one less thing to worry about defining.

I disagree with these two paragraphs.

1) The equivalence of gravitational and inertial mass was noticed long ago. The equivalence principle was Einstein's huge generalization of it: that no local physics of any kind can distinguish free fall from inertial motion in 'empty space' with no significant mass around.

2) The conclusion I draw is almost the opposite of yours. It is that gravity is not a force at all, and there are no such thing as inertial forces. Then, forces are tensors and no coordinate systems are privileged in any way. You never need to worry about inertial frames if you don't want to. In any coordinates, it is unambiguous whether a world line is experiencing force or not.
 
  • #53
pervect said:
I suppose it is also self consistent to think of gravity as being a "curvature of space time" and in no ways a force, which seems to be your suggestion. So then you do get to keep all the other forces as tensors, and you insist that gravity is "not a force".

This is more or less my position, but my terminology may be a bit different. I would say that tidal gravity is curvature of spacetime. Gravity as whatever it is that makes a rock fall to Earth is not tidal gravity, though it is related to it. But I would agree that the latter type of gravity is still not a force, because the rock falling to Earth feels no force (its 4-acceleration is zero, neglecting air resistance). A force is something that causes a nonzero 4-acceleration; by this definition, yes, all forces are tensors.
 
  • #54
atyy said:
Pitts and Schieve seem to have no disagreement that gravity=spin 2. All the questions are about exactly what assumptions are needed to obtain uniqueness.

(GR ≠ spin-2 field)

They avoid the criticism cited here and merely repeat Deser, Feynman, and others mistakes
 
  • #55
juanrga said:
(GR ≠ spin-2 field)

They avoid the criticism cited here and merely repeat Deser, Feynman, and others mistakes

Dang, you are persistent! I thought by citing Schieve, some of whose work you had approved of, I could make you change your mind :tongue2:
 
  • #56
juanrga said:
He avoids the criticism about (GR ≠ spin-2 field) cited here and only offers a partial dispute with Padmanabhan work also cited here

He doesn't ignore it. He rejects it completely as incorrect. I am not going to try to referee this debate among people who know enormously more than I, but there is no doubt what Deser thinks:

"In summary, I have annotated the steps involved in the non-geometric derivation [1] of
GR from special relativistic field theory as the unique consistent self-interacting system,
(13) extending the initial free massless spin 2."

In short, Deser remains convinced: GR=spin 2 field theory.

Truth is not determined by poll, but I would predict that Deser's position would handily win a poll of relevant experts. For example, I have seen a number of comments by Professor Steven Carlip endorsing this point of view.
 
Last edited:
  • #57
PAllen said:
I disagree with these two paragraphs.

1) The equivalence of gravitational and inertial mass was noticed long ago. The equivalence principle was Einstein's huge generalization of it: that no local physics of any kind can distinguish free fall from inertial motion in 'empty space' with no significant mass around.

2) The conclusion I draw is almost the opposite of yours. It is that gravity is not a force at all, and there are no such thing as inertial forces. Then, forces are tensors and no coordinate systems are privileged in any way. You never need to worry about inertial frames if you don't want to. In any coordinates, it is unambiguous whether a world line is experiencing force or not.

I was thinking about the topic as I wrote it You managed to respond to one of the earlier/earliest versions. You make some good points, I think. It's interesting that the final version I came up with (which was before I read this criticisms) almost seems as if I read your criticism (but at the time I finished my original, I didn't see the criticisms yet).

I'll agree that it is possible to view gravity as not being a force, but rather due to the curvature of the space-time. This way one gets to keep the traditional structure of "forces" mostly intact, having only to sacrifice the original Newtonian idea of gravity being a force with the replacement idea that "it's not really a force".

Then one can explain that curved space-time transforms as a tensor, but it's a rank 4 tensor, i.e. the Riemann, thus it has more degrees of freedom than any "force" concept allows.

I still don't think this approach is really in the true spirit of "general covariance", because one still has to single out inertial frames as being "special - and one has to be careful of what sort of transformations are allowed as well. But it's a reasonable way of looking at things nonetheless.
 
  • #58
atyy said:
Dang, you are persistent! I thought by citing Schieve, some of whose work you had approved of, I could make you change your mind :tongue2:

Then that is a strong difference between you and me. I do not cite authors, I cite specific works :uhh:.

And as many others I am well aware that the same author can be completely right regarding some topics and completely wrong regarding others.
 
  • #59
PAllen said:
He doesn't ignore it. He rejects it completely as incorrect. I am not going to try to referee this debate among people who know enormously more than I, but there is no doubt what Deser thinks:

"In summary, I have annotated the steps involved in the non-geometric derivation [1] of
GR from special relativistic field theory as the unique consistent self-interacting system,
(13) extending the initial free massless spin 2."

In short, Deser remains convinced: GR=spin 2 field theory.

Truth is not determined by poll, but I would predict that Deser's position would handily win a poll of relevant experts. For example, I have seen a number of comments by Professor Steven Carlip endorsing this point of view.

Deser only partially answers Padmanabhan work.

Deser completely ignores the rest of criticism to his derivation (nowhere Deser replies the criticism to his 'derivation' done in the section 3.3 of http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9912003

This reference shows conclusively that (GR ≠ spin 2 field theory).

Effectively, truth is not determined by poll, neither by appeal to authority. If you or some other want to rely on what some 'big' names say, you are welcomed. I prefer to check by myself the literature :rolleyes:
 
Last edited:
  • #60
juanrga said:
Deser only partially answers Padmanabhan work.

Deser completely ignores the rest of criticism to his derivation (nowhere Deser replies the criticism to his 'derivation' done in the section 3.3 of http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9912003

This reference shows conclusively that (GR ≠ spin 2 field theory).

Effectively, truth is not determined by poll, neither by appeal to authority. If you or some other want to rely on what some 'big' names say, you are welcomed. I prefer to check by myself the literature :rolleyes:

The reference only claims to show it for quantum GR in very strong gravity (eg. near spacetime singularities), for which it is agreed that GR may not be spin 2.
 
Last edited:
  • #61
atyy said:
The reference only claims to show it for quantum GR in very strong gravity (eg. near spacetime singularities), for which it is agreed that GR may not be spin 2.

You are completely confused.

One can read already from page 2 of the reference cited (bold font from mine):

There are many articles and books dealing with GR but only a few papers discuss FTG. Perhaps it is a consequence of wide-spread opinion that FTG is equivalent to GR and hence we need not spend time to study field gravity approach. [...] Indeed in papers of Thirring(1961) and Deser (1970) there were claims that field theory approach is identical with the geometrical one and there are no gravitational effects which could provide grounds to distinguish between them.
[...]
However, as it will be shown here, reality turns out to be much more complex and interesting. Actually GR and FTG are two alternative theories with different bases and different observational predictions. Of course, for the weak gravitational fields, which are available for experiments now, both theories give the same values of the classical
relativistic effects, but they profoundly different in the case of strong gravity, which will be obtainable in near future.

First, FTG and GR agree on weak gravity, are different for intermediate gravity and «profoundly different in the case of strong gravity»

Second, he writes about GR. Nowhere he writes about «quantum GR» as you pretend {*}.

Indeed, the section 3 of the paper is titled «Classical theory of tensor field». The interesting part for this thread is the subsection 3.3 «Thirring and Deser about identity of GR and FTG», where is shown why the previous claims by both about GR being equivalent or derivable from a classical field theory are incorrect.

The «Quantum theory of tensor field» is presented in section 4 {**}, but I repeat, the proof that GR (a classical theory) is not equivalent to the classical field theory of gravity is given before in section 3.

The 'derivations' presented here by Deser, Schieve, and other people are incorrect: GR is not equivalent to a field theory of gravity (FTG).

{*} Moreover, does not exist a consistent and accepted «quantum GR».

{**} There exists a classical FTG and a quantum FTG, somewhat as there exists a classical electrodynamics and a quantum electrodynamics.
 
  • #62
juanrga said:
You are completely confused.

One can read already from page 2 of the reference cited (bold font from mine):
First, FTG and GR agree on weak gravity, are different for intermediate gravity and «profoundly different in the case of strong gravity»

Second, he writes about GR. Nowhere he writes about «quantum GR» as you pretend {*}.

Indeed, the section 3 of the paper is titled «Classical theory of tensor field». The interesting part for this thread is the subsection 3.3 «Thirring and Deser about identity of GR and FTG», where is shown why the previous claims by both about GR being equivalent or derivable from a classical field theory are incorrect.

The «Quantum theory of tensor field» is presented in section 4 {**}, but I repeat, the proof that GR (a classical theory) is not equivalent to the classical field theory of gravity is given before in section 3.

The 'derivations' presented here by Deser, Schieve, and other people are incorrect: GR is not equivalent to a field theory of gravity (FTG).

{*} Moreover, does not exist a consistent and accepted «quantum GR».

{**} There exists a classical FTG and a quantum FTG, somewhat as there exists a classical electrodynamics and a quantum electrodynamics.

Yes, you are probably right about what Baryshev intends to claim, maybe not from this paper, but I looked at some of his other papers, and he says what you say he does pretty clearly. In http://arxiv.org/abs/0809.2323 Baryshev cites Straumann as providing caveats about the equivalence of GR and FTG. Straumann's caveats seem pretty standard. Is Baryshev saying anything that Straumann or eg. Ortin are not saying? As I understand, the major restriction for the equivalence of FTG and GR is that the GR spacetime needs a nice topology and can be covered by nice coordinates like harmonic coordinates
 
Last edited:
  • #63
atyy said:
Yes, you are probably right about what Baryshev intends to claim, maybe not from this paper, but I looked at some of his other papers, and he says what you say he does pretty clearly. In http://arxiv.org/abs/0809.2323 Baryshev cites Straumann as providing caveats about the equivalence of GR and FTG. Straumann's caveats seem pretty standard. Is Baryshev saying anything that Straumann or eg. Ortin are not saying? As I understand, the major restriction for the equivalence of FTG and GR is that the GR spacetime needs a nice topology and can be covered by nice coordinates like harmonic coordinates

Well it seems to me that the first paper cited before and the quotations given are pretty clear:

Baryshev said:
Actually GR and FTG are two alternative theories with different bases and different observational predictions

I cannot imagine how someone would misread that as «GR and FTG are the same theory».

Regarding the new preprint 0809 that you cite, the appeal to Straumann point is correct. Straumann point about BHs is close to the criticism done by Wald (in his famous textbook) against string theory. String theory starts from the incorrect supposition that (GR = spin-2 theory) but then defines causality (e.g. in the S-matrix) with regard to the original flat background instead of with regard to the GR real metric. Therefore it cannot be equivalent to GR.

However, the criticism done by Baryshev in the first paper cited before is more complete and applies beyond BHs.
 
<h2>1. What is the concept of force in special relativity?</h2><p>In special relativity, force is defined as the rate of change of momentum of an object with respect to time. It is a fundamental concept that explains the motion of objects in the presence of other objects or fields.</p><h2>2. How do point particles fit into the theory of special relativity?</h2><p>In special relativity, point particles are considered to be objects with no physical size or extension. They are used as a simplification to understand the behavior of particles at very small scales, such as in particle accelerators.</p><h2>3. Is the concept of force applicable to point particles in special relativity?</h2><p>Yes, the concept of force is applicable to point particles in special relativity. Even though they have no physical size, point particles still have mass and can experience forces, such as gravitational or electromagnetic forces.</p><h2>4. How does special relativity explain the validity of force and point particles?</h2><p>Special relativity explains the validity of force and point particles by incorporating them into its mathematical framework. The theory accounts for the effects of time dilation and length contraction, which are necessary to accurately describe the behavior of objects moving at high speeds.</p><h2>5. Are there any limitations to the validity of force and point particles in special relativity?</h2><p>There are some limitations to the validity of force and point particles in special relativity. For example, the theory does not account for the effects of quantum mechanics, which are necessary to describe the behavior of particles at very small scales. Additionally, some phenomena, such as black holes, require the use of general relativity to fully understand their behavior.</p>

1. What is the concept of force in special relativity?

In special relativity, force is defined as the rate of change of momentum of an object with respect to time. It is a fundamental concept that explains the motion of objects in the presence of other objects or fields.

2. How do point particles fit into the theory of special relativity?

In special relativity, point particles are considered to be objects with no physical size or extension. They are used as a simplification to understand the behavior of particles at very small scales, such as in particle accelerators.

3. Is the concept of force applicable to point particles in special relativity?

Yes, the concept of force is applicable to point particles in special relativity. Even though they have no physical size, point particles still have mass and can experience forces, such as gravitational or electromagnetic forces.

4. How does special relativity explain the validity of force and point particles?

Special relativity explains the validity of force and point particles by incorporating them into its mathematical framework. The theory accounts for the effects of time dilation and length contraction, which are necessary to accurately describe the behavior of objects moving at high speeds.

5. Are there any limitations to the validity of force and point particles in special relativity?

There are some limitations to the validity of force and point particles in special relativity. For example, the theory does not account for the effects of quantum mechanics, which are necessary to describe the behavior of particles at very small scales. Additionally, some phenomena, such as black holes, require the use of general relativity to fully understand their behavior.

Similar threads

  • Special and General Relativity
2
Replies
47
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
20
Views
939
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
5
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
2
Replies
45
Views
3K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
11
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
2
Replies
40
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
1
Views
618
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
30
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
25
Views
786
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
11
Views
2K
Back
Top