Some doubts concerning the mathematical bases of GR

In summary: I still don't know what you are trying to say. Are you trying to say that the definition of Hausdorff space in wikipedia is incorrect?In summary, the conversation discusses various assumptions made in general relativity, such as the assumption that the spacetime manifold is a Hausdorff space, which does not seem to be supported by the fact that pseudometric spaces are not Hausdorff. It is also mentioned that curvature is not a property of the manifold alone, and that the assumption of smoothness is contradicted by the existence of singularities. The claims made in the conversation are then discussed and justified. Finally, it is noted that all topological manifolds are Hausdorff, regardless of the
  • #71
Ben Niehoff said:
"Distance" is not part of the subject of topology, period.

Points along a null geodesic are separate because they have different values of affine parameter. This is the whole point of saying the manifold can be covered by open sets that map continuously to open sets of R^n.

A pseudo-Riemannian metric tensor does not induce a topology that agrees with the underlying manifold structure. We do not use, nor care, what topology the pseudo-Riemannian metric tensor does induce, precisely because it disagrees with the underlying manifold structure.

Just because a structure can be defined does not mean that it is useful or physically reasonable. GR uses differential geometry, which is done on manifolds, and hence it is the manifold structure we require. Physically, it is reasonable that null geodesics be a series of distinct points, rather than a single point, because it is our physical observation that light rays travel.

Note also, that on any manifold, we can define a Riemannian metric tensor. But in GR we choose not to, because a Riemannian metric tensor is incompatible with the physical requirement of local Lorentz symmetry. So this is another example of a structure that is possible to define, but is left unused in the context of GR.



Ok, I was not trying to link topology and distance, I happen to have questions about both but independently.

My question about topology that has not yet been addressed was if Riemannian and Pseudo-Riemannian manifolds have the same topology?

My question about distance was how do we separate points on null geodesic in Lorentzian manifolds?
If as you say we do it relying on the geodesic affine parametrization, how is this different from a timelike geodesic? IOW, it looks like a Lorentzian manifold has the same notion of distance that the Riemannian ones have, even if infinitesimally one has ds=0, ds>0 or ds<0.

Also, why exactly is local lorentz symmetry incompatible with a Riemannian metric?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #72
TrickyDicky said:
My question about topology that has not yet been addressed was if Riemannian and Pseudo-Riemannian manifolds have the same topology?

That question doesn't make sense as written.

A 2-sphere and a 2-torus have different topologies, although both will accept Riemannian metrics.

On a 2-torus you can put either a Riemannian metric or a pseudo-Riemannian one. In both cases, the underlying topology is the same: a 2-torus.

If what you mean is "local topology", then the answer is yes. A manifold (be it Riemannian or pseudo-Riemannian) looks locally like a piece of [itex]R^n[/itex] (not [itex]R^{n-1,1}[/itex]).

In fact, [itex]R^{n-1,1}[/itex] is topologically the same as [itex]R^n[/itex]; it just has a pseudo-Riemannian metric defined on it.

My question about distance was how do we separate points on null geodesic in Lorentzian manifolds?
If as you say we do it relying on the geodesic affine parametrization, how is this different from a timelike geodesic? IOW, it looks like a Lorentzian manifold has the same notion of distance that the Riemannian ones have, even if infinitesimally one has ds=0, ds>0 or ds<0.

You need to be very careful what you mean when you say "distance".

Let's just take standard, 2-dimensional Minkowski space. The points (0,0) and (1,1) are distinct points because they have different coordinates.

Also, why exactly is local lorentz symmetry incompatible with a Riemannian metric?

Because Riemannian manifolds have local Euclidean symmetry.
 
  • #73
Ben Niehoff said:
That question doesn't make sense as written.

A 2-sphere and a 2-torus have different topologies, although both will accept Riemannian metrics.

On a 2-torus you can put either a Riemannian metric or a pseudo-Riemannian one. In both cases, the underlying topology is the same: a 2-torus.

If what you mean is "local topology", then the answer is yes. A manifold (be it Riemannian or pseudo-Riemannian) looks locally like a piece of [itex]R^n[/itex] (not [itex]R^{n-1,1}[/itex]).

In fact, [itex]R^{n-1,1}[/itex] is topologically the same as [itex]R^n[/itex]; it just has a pseudo-Riemannian metric defined on it.
I guess I should have been more formal when formulating the question but I thought the context was clear enough.

Let's see I am aware that any smooth manifold admits infinite Riemannian metrics, this is not related to what I meant with my question.

Your second example is closer to where I was getting at, given a certain topology given by the smooth manifold structure, topologically makes no difference if the metric we add on top that structure is Riemannian or Pseudo-Riemannian, agree?

The thing is that unlike geometry topology has only global structure, that is why topology is usually considered something global, and therefore the local topology distinction you are making is confusing to me, if a differentiable manifold has "local" topology R^4 then that is also its (global) topology, no?


You need to be very careful what you mean when you say "distance".

Let's just take standard, 2-dimensional Minkowski space. The points (0,0) and (1,1) are distinct points because they have different coordinates.
Yes, I guess I should have been more precise here too, when I say Pseudo-Riemannian manifold and since what we are finally always dealing here with is GR, I always mean a connected, curved, Lorentzian manifold.
Minkowski spacetime is flat and therefore it can be covered by a single coordinate system, a curved manifold will need more than one chart and there will be overlap between charts, so using coordinates to separate distinct points is not always possible.


Because Riemannian manifolds have local Euclidean symmetry.
Infinitesimally, how is Euclidean symmetry different from Lorentzian symmetry?
I thought the whole point of manifolds was that they were locally isomorphic to a Euclidean space.
 
  • #74
To make more precise what I mean by distance, if (connected) Pseudo-Riemannian manifolds have no pseudosemimetric space structure, must I suppose they have metric space structure like (connected) Riemannian manifolds do?
 
  • #75
TrickyDicky said:
To make more precise what I mean by distance, if (connected) Pseudo-Riemannian manifolds have no pseudosemimetric space structure, must I suppose they have metric space structure like (connected) Riemannian manifolds do?

If you haven't defined a metric (i.e. global, positive distance function), then there is no metric space structure.

I really suggest you pick up a more mathematical text, rather than learning from the traditional GR sources, if you are concerned about the precise mathematical underpinnings of differential geometry. I think Nakahara is good, Micromass might have some other suggestions.
 
  • #76
It seems to me you are making some exploration of "What kind of mathematical structures can I define, and how are they related?", which is good and interesting from a pure mathematical point of view. I suggest you keep exploring that, you'll gain some better understanding of what's really going on.

In the context of GR (or any physical theory, really), you need to ask an additional question: "Does this structure model the physics I want to model?" This question is answered both by intuition about what you think the physical theory should be like, and also by contact with experiment.
 
  • #77
Ben Niehoff said:
It seems to me you are making some exploration of "What kind of mathematical structures can I define, and how are they related?", which is good and interesting from a pure mathematical point of view. I suggest you keep exploring that, you'll gain some better understanding of what's really going on.

In the context of GR (or any physical theory, really), you need to ask an additional question: "Does this structure model the physics I want to model?" This question is answered both by intuition about what you think the physical theory should be like, and also by contact with experiment.

Ben, thanks for your wise advice which I'll follow.
Meanwhile, could you comment on my last questions?
 
  • #78
TrickyDicky said:
Your second example is closer to where I was getting at, given a certain topology given by the smooth manifold structure, topologically makes no difference if the metric we add on top that structure is Riemannian or Pseudo-Riemannian, agree?

Yes, with one caveat: some manifolds do not allow us to define a pseudo-Riemannian metric tensor. For example, the 2-sphere cannot have a p-R structure; whereas the 2-torus can. As explained in Pallen's earlier link, it is possible to define a p-R structure if and only if there is a non-vanishing vector field; i.e. if the Euler characteristic is zero.

The thing is that unlike geometry topology has only global structure, that is why topology is usually considered something global, and therefore the local topology distinction you are making is confusing to me, if a differentiable manifold has "local" topology R^4 then that is also its (global) topology, no?

Topology concerns homeomorphisms; that is, continuous one-to-one maps. Local topology concerns local homeomorphisms; i.e., homeomorphisms between open patches. The local topology of an n-fold is the same as the local topology of R^n.

There is more to topology than counting invariants like handles, holes, etc. Topology is the study of how points are connected, which is another way of expressing what it means for something to be "continuous" (since topology concerns continuous maps). A homeomorphism is any map that leaves all the "connectedness" information intact.

Consider graph theory. The connectedness of all the vertices in a graph can be represented by a matrix. Two graphs are isomorphic if and only if their adjacency matrices are related by a permutation; i.e., the graphs are topologically the same if they have the same connectedness information.

Yes, I guess I should have been more precise here too, when I say Pseudo-Riemannian manifold and since what we are finally always dealing here with is GR, I always mean a connected, curved, Lorentzian manifold.
Minkowski spacetime is flat and therefore it can be covered by a single coordinate system, a curved manifold will need more than one chart and there will be overlap between charts, so using coordinates to separate distinct points is not always possible.

If two charts do not overlap, then they contain distinct points. If they do overlap, you can use the transition functions to compare coordinates in one chart with coordinates in the other. Hence you can always decide whether two points are distinct.

Infinitesimally, how is Euclidean symmetry different from Lorentzian symmetry?
I thought the whole point of manifolds was that they were locally isomorphic to a Euclidean space.

Manifolds are locally homeomorphic to R^n, but you must forget any notion of "distance" on R^n. Topology does not care about distance. It only care about how points are connected to each other.

Riemannian manifolds have an extra structure defined on them: the metric tensor. Riemannian manifolds have local Euclidean symmetry because each tangent space is isomorphic to Euclidean space, with the usual notion of Euclidean distance. Euclidean distance is preserved by Euclidean symmetry.

Pseudo-Riemannian manifolds also have extra structure defined on them: a pseudo-Riemannian metric tensor. P-R manifolds have local Lorentz (actually Poincare) symmetry, because each tangent space is isomorphic to Minkowski space, with the Minkowski product. The spacetime interval is preserved by Poincare symmetry.
 
  • #79
Thanx, time to give it some more thought and read.
 
  • #80
A couple of related interesting links:

https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=495816
http://mathpages.com/rr/s9-01/9-01.htm

A certain clash between GR Lorentzian metric and rigorous definitions of smooth manifolds seems to be hinted at in those links. That is, extra conditions like strong causality have to be added to the causal structure of the Lorentzian metric in order to make conform its Alexandrov topology to the smooth manifolds topology, and that only in the flat Minkowski case.
When curvature is present only in certain cases are p-r metrics admitted like those mentioned by Ben Niehoff and PAllen by virtue of using the S¹, CP space decomposition that allows closed timelike curves. On the other hand CTC's are not usually considered physical.
Do, say, non-compact curved 4-manifolds admit pseudoriemannian metrics? Knowing that would surely help constrain GR's possible topologies.

The problem I see is that many of the physical features associated to GR, like those related to singularities(BH's, horizons, BB, KS space...) fail to fulfill the extra conditions needed to qualify as a smooth manifold like the strong causality condition. Has that ever been seen as a problem by physicists?
 
Last edited:
  • #81
TrickyDicky said:
When curvature is present only in certain cases are p-r metrics admitted like those mentioned by Ben Niehoff and PAllen by virtue of using the S¹, CP space decomposition that allows closed timelike curves...

The problem I see is that many of the physical features associated to GR, like those related to singularities(BH's, horizons, BB, KS space...) fail to fulfill the extra conditions needed to qualify as a smooth manifold like the strong causality condition. Has that ever be seen as a problem by physicists?

I haven't read the relevant papers, but I would think that the difficulty would be: given a manifold, it may not always be possible to come up with a metric with signature (+---) on that manifold. However, in cases such as the Schwarzschild black hole, that's not what is done. Instead, one starts with a hypothetical metric (or rather, equivalently, a quadratic form for ds2 that has the right signature) and then uses that to define the manifold. There is no question about whether it is possible to give it the right type of metric, since you started with the right type of metric in the first place.

The approach that I'm talking about has its own problems, of course. One of them is the fact that a metric that is defined in terms of a particular set of coordinates only describes a "patch" of the manifold, and it may not be clear if and how it can be extended to a complete manifold. The other problem is that if you start with the metric, then you may not have a realistic stress-energy tensor. But the problem that you seem to be worried about doesn't really come up---we never start with an arbitrary manifold, and then ask what metric can we put on top of it.
 
  • #82
stevendaryl said:
I haven't read the relevant papers, but I would think that the difficulty would be: given a manifold, it may not always be possible to come up with a metric with signature (+---) on that manifold. However, in cases such as the Schwarzschild black hole, that's not what is done. Instead, one starts with a hypothetical metric (or rather, equivalently, a quadratic form for ds2 that has the right signature) and then uses that to define the manifold. There is no question about whether it is possible to give it the right type of metric, since you started with the right type of metric in the first place.
I guess by "the right metric in the first place" you must mean that it is after all one of GR's EFE solutions, and since most of us think GR is the right theory, we are confident that there must be some smooth manifold that admits that metric. The problem is that mathematically (and even physically as many GR solutions don't make much sense physically), that heuristic is not very rigorous, it basically reverses the hierarchy usually employed in mathematics since the manifold cannot be defined from the metric in many cases, like those where their topologies don't agree, the manifold always comes first, or at least that is what I've been told throughout this thread.
stevendaryl said:
The approach that I'm talking about has its own problems, of course. One of them is the fact that a metric that is defined in terms of a particular set of coordinates only describes a "patch" of the manifold, and it may not be clear if and how it can be extended to a complete manifold.
Exactly, that is what I mean. But not only that, it is not even assured that a manifold exists that admits that metric.
stevendaryl said:
The other problem is that if you start with the metric, then you may not have a realistic stress-energy tensor.
That's part of the unphysical solutions issue I mentioned above.

stevendaryl said:
But the problem that you seem to be worried about doesn't really come up---we never start with an arbitrary manifold, and then ask what metric can we put on top of it.
Right, I can see how that wouldn't even come up with the approach you are describing, that I presume is the usual one among physicists, but as we agreed that can lead to some serious problems and IMO to certain physical claims that might contradict the math.
 
  • #83
TrickyDicky said:
A couple of related interesting links:

https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=495816
http://mathpages.com/rr/s9-01/9-01.htm

A certain clash between GR Lorentzian metric and rigorous definitions of smooth manifolds seems to be hinted at in those links. That is, extra conditions like strong causality have to be added to the causal structure of the Lorentzian metric in order to make conform its Alexandrov topology to the smooth manifolds topology, and that only in the flat Minkowski case.
When curvature is present only in certain cases are p-r metrics admitted like those mentioned by Ben Niehoff and PAllen by virtue of using the S¹, CP space decomposition that allows closed timelike curves. On the other hand CTC's are not usually considered physical.
Do, say, non-compact curved 4-manifolds admit pseudoriemannian metrics? Knowing that would surely help constrain GR's possible topologies.

The problem I see is that many of the physical features associated to GR, like those related to singularities(BH's, horizons, BB, KS space...) fail to fulfill the extra conditions needed to qualify as a smooth manifold like the strong causality condition. Has that ever been seen as a problem by physicists?

While I highly respect and usually like Keven Brown's expositions (author of mathpages), I have the opposite bias as to what is the physically reasonable topology of spacetime. Specifically, no observer would have any tendency to consider the source and emission events for a light pulse to be topologically indistinguishable (as would follow from using a pseudo-semimetric toplology). In fact, the most uniform explanation of redshift in GR involves parallel transporting vectors along null paths, something which clearly distinguishes all the points along the null path. To my mind, the role of the Lorentzian metric is purely about chronometry, i.e. geometry, not topology. Topology is determined by boundary conditions or assumption (i.e. 'what would be the physical consequences per GR if we assume some overall manifold topology').

A more interesting question is the physical utility of distinguishing semi-riemannian manifolds for which the Alexandrov topology [a specific way of inducing a topology from the Lorentzian metric that is, IMO, much more satisfactory than integrating to a pseudosemimetrc] matches the manifold topology. Exploring the consequences of such a requirement is in the same spirit as energy conditions.

I think the clearest exposition of how none of this is relevant to the mathematical soundness of GR is the following from the thread you linked:

https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3295723&postcount=13

Separate from mathematical foundations, are physical validity of the GR as mathematical model. Here, we have mostly open questions, without conclusive answers:

- Energy conditions that are both too strong and too weak (so far)
- Which causality conditions are enforced in a 'physically plausible' GR solution?
- In what ways does GR fail to match our actual universe at event horizons and singularities?
 
  • #84
PAllen said:
While I highly respect and usually like Keven Brown's expositions (author of mathpages), I have the opposite bias as to what is the physically reasonable topology of spacetime. Specifically, no observer would have any tendency to consider the source and emission events for a light pulse to be topologically indistinguishable (as would follow from using a pseudo-semimetric toplology). In fact, the most uniform explanation of redshift in GR involves parallel transporting vectors along null paths, something which clearly distinguishes all the points along the null path.
I tend to agree with you, but note that this observer-biased approach to null geodesics amounts to treating them as timelike geodesics, which is what we normally do when thinking about light as paths as rays traversing a certain distance in a certain time.
PAllen said:
A more interesting question is the physical utility of distinguishing semi-riemannian manifolds for which the Alexandrov topology [a specific way of inducing a topology from the Lorentzian metric that is, IMO, much more satisfactory than integrating to a pseudosemimetrc] matches the manifold topology. Exploring the consequences of such a requirement is in the same spirit as energy conditions.

I think the clearest exposition of how none of this is relevant to the mathematical soundness of GR is the following from the thread you linked:

https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3295723&postcount=13
I used precisely this exposition in my post. I also specify that certain results of GR follow this conditions and certainly for those the mathematical soundness of GR is perfectly preserved, but that for a number of other GR results those conditions are apparently ignored.
PAllen said:
Separate from mathematical foundations, are physical validity of the GR as mathematical model. Here, we have mostly open questions, without conclusive answers:

- Energy conditions that are both too strong and too weak (so far)
- Which causality conditions are enforced in a 'physically plausible' GR solution?
- In what ways does GR fail to match our actual universe at event horizons and singularities?
These are sensible questions, but I find the last one a bit confused when you attribute the "actual universe" precisely some of the predictions of GR, and then question how those two fail to match. IMO what needs to be compared is observation and GR predictions , not the "actual universe" as predicted by GR and GR itself.
 
  • #85
PAllen said:
Separate from mathematical foundations, are physical validity of the GR as mathematical model. Here, we have mostly open questions, without conclusive answers:

- Energy conditions that are both too strong and too weak (so far)
- Which causality conditions are enforced in a 'physically plausible' GR solution?
- In what ways does GR fail to match our actual universe at event horizons and singularities?

TrickyDicky said:
These are sensible questions, but I find the last one a bit confused when you attribute the "actual universe" precisely some of the predictions of GR, and then question how those two fail to match. IMO what needs to be compared is observation and GR predictions , not the "actual universe" as predicted by GR and GR itself.

In all of these questions, I was implying comparison to observation.

I guess the difference is:

- With energy conditions or causality conditions, the goal to make improve the match between GR and observation by excluding nonsense. That is, exploring whether 'pure math' GR + <condition> better matches what is and isn't observed than 'pure math' GR. GR is thus improved or salvaged.

- With singularities and event horizons, it is believed that there is no simple way to remove these as predictions of GR. Thus, to the extent you believe observations would disagree with GR (pretty much universal for singularities; less so for horizons), you can explore where and how GR breaks down.

[edit: to clarify nonstandard usage: By pure math GR I mean GR where any manifold admitting a Lorentzian metric, along with such metric, is considered to be a possible prediction of GR. The EFE are then satisfied simply by using them to prescribe the stress energy tensor]
 
Last edited:
  • #86
PAllen said:
In all of these questions, I was implying comparison to observation.

I guess the difference is:

- With energy conditions or causality conditions, the goal to make improve the match between GR and observation by excluding nonsense. That is, exploring whether 'pure math' GR + <condition> better matches what is and isn't observed than 'pure math' GR. GR is thus improved or salvaged.

- With singularities and event horizons, it is believed that there is no simple way to remove these as predictions of GR. Thus, to the extent you believe observations would disagree with GR (pretty much universal for singularities; less so for horizons), you can explore where and how GR breaks down.

[edit: to clarify nonstandard usage: By pure math GR I mean GR where any manifold admitting a Lorentzian metric, along with such metric, is considered to be a possible prediction of GR. The EFE are then satisfied simply by using them to prescribe the stress energy tensor]
I find all this quite reasonable.
 
  • #87
TrickyDicky said:
I guess by "the right metric in the first place" you must mean that it is after all one of GR's EFE solutions

No, I meant a metric having the right signature: (+ - - -).

The problem is that mathematically (and even physically as many GR solutions don't make much sense physically), that heuristic is not very rigorous, it basically reverses the hierarchy usually employed in mathematics since the manifold cannot be defined from the metric in many cases, like those where their topologies don't agree,

What do you mean that the "topologies don't agree"? Coordinates are only defined for a "patch"; a small simply connected region of a manifold. There is no topology implied. Now, as I said, there is a question of whether a collection of patches can be stitched together to form a complete manifold. So in addition to defining patches, and giving metrics for the patches, you also have to define how the patches are glued together, and show that the metrics are compatible on the overlap. But that is not difficult for a simple case such as the Schwarzschild solution. (Well, it's not difficult in retrospect.)

the manifold always comes first, or at least that is what I've been told throughout this thread.

Mathematics doesn't care about what order you do things. You can start with a complete manifold, and then try to come up with a metric for it, Or you can start with a metric for a patch, and try to glue the patches into a complete manifold. The end result is the same. But I was saying that I don't think the first approach is very common in practice.

... it is not even assured that a manifold exists that admits that metric.

I would not express the problem that way. It doesn't make sense to say that you have a metric, and are looking around for an appropriate manifold, because you can't really define a metric independently of having a manifold (or at least a section or patch of one). The problem, as I said, is that if I have a collection of patches, and each patch has a metric defined on it, there may be no way to glue them together into a manifold.
 
  • #88
TrickyDicky said:
I tend to agree with you, but note that this observer-biased approach to null geodesics amounts to treating them as timelike geodesics, which is what we normally do when thinking about light as paths as rays traversing a certain distance in a certain time.

The geometric object that makes sense for manifold is the parametrized path, [itex]P(s)[/itex] which is a continuous function from reals to points in the manifold. If the path is timelike, then you can choose the parameter [itex]s[/itex] to be proper time along the path, but that is not necessary to be able to talk about such things as parallel transport. [itex]s[/itex] can be any monotonically increasing real-valued parameter. So there is no difficulty at all in doing parallel transport along lightlike paths. The only thing that is slightly annoying about it is that there is no natural best choice for parametrization in the case of null paths.
 
  • #89
To model space time by differentiable manifold, the terms connected, unbounded, oriented, para-compact and Hausdorff need to be included in the term "manifold". For each of those properties ther is a well-founded physical argument. In mathematics, you can put any structure, any metric metric you please to put on the manifold, but only Lorentzian metric is meaning full in physics.

Sam
 
  • #90
stevendaryl said:
What do you mean that the "topologies don't agree"? Coordinates are only defined for a "patch"; a small simply connected region of a manifold. There is no topology implied. Now, as I said, there is a question of whether a collection of patches can be stitched together to form a complete manifold. So in addition to defining patches, and giving metrics for the patches, you also have to define how the patches are glued together, and show that the metrics are compatible on the overlap. But that is not difficult for a simple case such as the Schwarzschild solution. (Well, it's not difficult in retrospect.)
I mean precisely that, the topolog induced by a Lorentzian metric has to have several conditions added in order to agree with the smooth manifold topology, and I'm not referring only to the global topology you refer to with the "gluing of the paches". I mean the "local" topology that must be homeomorphic to R⁴ in order to agree with the smooth manifold natural topology. Why do you think coordinate patches don't have topological properties?
What you call a simple case, the KS space, doesn't actually have the required added conditions to have the smooth manifolds topology at the overlaps, for instance the strong causality condition.
 
  • #91
stevendaryl said:
The geometric object that makes sense for manifold is the parametrized path, [itex]P(s)[/itex] which is a continuous function from reals to points in the manifold. If the path is timelike, then you can choose the parameter [itex]s[/itex] to be proper time along the path, but that is not necessary to be able to talk about such things as parallel transport. [itex]s[/itex] can be any monotonically increasing real-valued parameter. So there is no difficulty at all in doing parallel transport along lightlike paths. The only thing that is slightly annoying about it is that there is no natural best choice for parametrization in the case of null paths.

Both Riemannians and Pseudoriemannian manifolds use the Levi-Civita connection so in this particular case parallel transport does require [itex]s[/itex] to be the parameter that locally extremizes the path. Even for null geodesics. As long as we want to respect the underlying manifold topology. A pseudosemimetric space for instance doesn't have this requirement, but PseudoRiemannian manifolds are not pseudosemimetric spaces.
 
  • #92
TrickyDicky said:
I mean precisely that, the topolog induced by a Lorentzian metric has to have several conditions added in order to agree with the smooth manifold topology, and I'm not referring only to the global topology you refer to with the "gluing of the paches". I mean the "local" topology that must be homeomorphic to R⁴ in order to agree with the smooth manifold natural topology. Why do you think coordinate patches don't have topological properties?

The local patches are just little sections of R4. There is really nothing much to distinguish one patch from another. In GR, locally everything looks like a little section of Minkowsky spacetime. The only issue really is how the patches are glued together. So I'm not sure what problem you're worried about.
 
  • #93
TrickyDicky said:
Both Riemannians and Pseudoriemannian manifolds use the Levi-Civita connection so in this particular case parallel transport does require [itex]s[/itex] to be the parameter that locally extremizes the path. Even for null geodesics. As long as we want to respect the underlying manifold topology. A pseudosemimetric space for instance doesn't have this requirement, but PseudoRiemannian manifolds are not pseudosemimetric spaces.

I don't think what you are saying is correct. An extremal path (not necessarily the same thing as a geodesic, but it is in the case where the connection is compatible with the metric) from point A to point B is a parametrized path [itex]P(s)[/itex] that extremizes the integral

[itex]\int \sqrt{g_{\mu \nu} \dfrac{dx^{\mu}}{ds}\dfrac{dx^{\mu}}{ds}}[/itex]

The parameter [itex]s[/itex] does not need to be proper time; it can be any monotonically increasing parameter. The above integral is invariant under reparametrization.
 
  • #94
TrickyDicky said:
What you call a simple case, the KS space, doesn't actually have the required added conditions to have the smooth manifolds topology at the overlaps, for instance the strong causality condition.

I think you might be mixing necessary and sufficient conditions. You can directly verify in the case of a Schwarzschild black hole that the metric is defined everywhere except at the singularity, and that it always has the signature (+ - - -). So you don't need a theorem telling you under what circumstances it is possible to do that. If you had a theorem giving necessary conditions, and those conditions weren't met in the Schwarzschild case, that would be an indication of an inconsistency.

So are the conditions you are talking about necessary or sufficient?
 
  • #95
stevendaryl said:
I think you might be mixing necessary and sufficient conditions. You can directly verify in the case of a Schwarzschild black hole that the metric is defined everywhere except at the singularity, and that it always has the signature (+ - - -). So you don't need a theorem telling you under what circumstances it is possible to do that. If you had a theorem giving necessary conditions, and those conditions weren't met in the Schwarzschild case, that would be an indication of an inconsistency.

So are the conditions you are talking about necessary or sufficient?

Necessary, and the putative inconsistence would be derived from the problem you've mentioned several times that starts with the metric rather than with the manifold and simply expects that a global topology exists that admits that metric.
 
  • #96
stevendaryl said:
I don't think what you are saying is correct. An extremal path (not necessarily the same thing as a geodesic, but it is in the case where the connection is compatible with the metric) from point A to point B is a parametrized path [itex]P(s)[/itex] that extremizes the integral

[itex]\int \sqrt{g_{\mu \nu} \dfrac{dx^{\mu}}{ds}\dfrac{dx^{\mu}}{ds}}[/itex]

The parameter [itex]s[/itex] does not need to be proper time; it can be any monotonically increasing parameter.
Proper time τ in GR is precisely by definition the parameter that gives the extremal path.
Any Optics text will show that light doesn't follow paths parametrized by any monotonically increasing parameter.
stevendaryl said:
The above integral is invariant under reparametrization.
Different metrics will give different paths.
We are talking about the variation of that integral: [itex]\delta[/itex]S=0
 
  • #97
TrickyDicky said:
Proper time τ in GR is precisely by definition the parameter that gives the extremal path.
Any Optics text will show that light doesn't follow paths parametrized by any monotonically increasing parameter.

Your book is lying xD
By definition a path is a continuos map [itex] \phi: \left[ 0, 1 \right] \rightarrow M\; .[/itex]

TrickyDicky said:
Different metrics will give different paths.
We are talking about the variation of that integral: [itex]\delta[/itex]S=0

The integral is invariant under reparametrization, i.e. a change of the parameter [itex]s[/itex] not of the metric.

Ilm
 
  • #98
TrickyDicky said:
Proper time τ in GR is precisely by definition the parameter that gives the extremal path.

No, that's not correct. Proper time is defined via

[itex]d\tau = \sqrt{g_{\mu \nu} \dfrac{dx^{\mu}}{ds} \dfrac{dx^{\nu}}{ds}} ds [/itex]

The definition of proper time doesn't refer to extremal paths; if the path is non-extremal (which it will be if there are non-gravitational forces such as electromagnetism) the above still gives you proper time.

The definition of proper time is independent of your choice of the parameter [itex]ds[/itex]. If you make a parameter change [itex]s' = f(s)[/itex] then [itex]d\tau[/itex] is unchanged.

Now, for time-like paths, you can actually use the freedom to change parameters to choose [itex]s = \tau[/itex], but that's really only a convenience. It doesn't have any consequences, other than making the mathematics simpler.
 
  • #99
TrickyDicky said:
Necessary, and the putative inconsistence would be derived from the problem you've mentioned several times that starts with the metric rather than with the manifold and simply expects that a global topology exists that admits that metric.

But in the case of the Schwarzschild solution, it's possible to explicitly calculate the metric, and see that it has signature (+ - - -) everywhere except at the singularity. This is clearest using Kruskal-Szekeres coordinates, as described here: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kruskal–Szekeres_coordinates

I'm not sure what problem you are worried about.
 
  • #100
stevendaryl said:
Now, for time-like paths, you can actually use the freedom to change parameters to choose [itex]s = \tau[/itex], but that's really only a convenience. It doesn't have any consequences, other than making the mathematics simpler.

...and if the path is lightlike, then you can't use proper time as the parameter, because the parameter has to be monotonically increasing along the path. But you can certainly use other parameters. For example, in 2-D spacetime, the light-like path [itex]x=ct[/itex] can be parametrized by [itex]t[/itex] itself, giving [itex]\dfrac{dx^0}{dt} = 1[/itex] and [itex]\dfrac{dx^1}{dt} = c[/itex]. Then the proper time [itex]\tau[/itex] is given by:

[itex]d\tau = \sqrt{g_{\mu \nu} \dfrac{dx^\mu}{dt} \dfrac{dx^\nu}{dt}} dt[/itex]
[itex]= 0[/itex]
 
  • #101
Ilmrak said:
Your book is lying xD
By definition a path is a continuos map [itex] \phi: \left[ 0, 1 \right] \rightarrow M\; .[/itex]



The integral is invariant under reparametrization, i.e. a change of the parameter [itex]s[/itex] not of the metric.

Ilm
You are ignoring the context of my answers. Light in vacuum can only follow null geodesics which are not parametrized by just any monotonically increasing parameter, but the one that extremizes the path.

The invariance of the integral is derived from the fact it is integrating dtau.
 
  • #102
stevendaryl said:
No, that's not correct. Proper time is defined via

[itex]d\tau = \sqrt{g_{\mu \nu} \dfrac{dx^{\mu}}{ds} \dfrac{dx^{\nu}}{ds}} ds [/itex]

The definition of proper time doesn't refer to extremal paths; if the path is non-extremal (which it will be if there are non-gravitational forces such as electromagnetism) the above still gives you proper time.

The definition of proper time is independent of your choice of the parameter [itex]ds[/itex]. If you make a parameter change [itex]s' = f(s)[/itex] then [itex]d\tau[/itex] is unchanged.

Now, for time-like paths, you can actually use the freedom to change parameters to choose [itex]s = \tau[/itex], but that's really only a convenience. It doesn't have any consequences, other than making the mathematics simpler.
I thougt we were talking about geodesics, not just timelike paths, proper time parametrization is equivalent to the arc length parametrization, of course if the path is not geodesic the proper time is not defined like I wrote.

You guys seem to be discussing different things from the ones I'm talking about.
 
  • #103
TrickyDicky said:
You are ignoring the context of my answers. Light in vacuum can only follow null geodesics which are not parametrized by just any monotonically increasing parameter, but the one that extremizes the path.

Whether a path is extremal or not has nothing to do with the parametrization.
 
  • #104
TrickyDicky said:
I thougt we were talking about geodesics, not just timelike paths, proper time parametrization is equivalent to the arc length parametrization, of course if the path is not geodesic the proper time is not defined like I wrote.

You guys seem to be discussing different things from the ones I'm talking about.

I'm only responding to what you have said. You said that

Proper time τ in GR is precisely by definition the parameter that gives the extremal path.

That's false. Proper time has nothing to do with extremal paths. You can define proper time for non-extremal paths, as well. Whether a parametrized path is a geodesic is completely independent of whether you use proper time as the path parameter.
 
  • #105
Really, you seem to be arguing for the sake of arguing about things that are not related to the OP and distract, in case you are not I apologize, and thanks for making my poor wording more understandable.

For your information there is a special circumstance that happens to coincide with the one at hand that relates parametrization with whether a path is extremal.
Natural parametrization, or unit speed (arc length) parametrization in the context of geodesics in a given metric and a Levi-Civita connection in a (pseudo)Riemannian manifold(see Morse theory of geodesics in pseudoRiemannian manifolds).
The extremal paths of the action functional coincide with the geodesics of the metric g in their natural (proper time in the Lorentzian case) parametrization.
 

Similar threads

  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
12
Views
3K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
5
Views
900
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
7
Views
2K
  • Beyond the Standard Models
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
7
Views
2K
  • Science and Math Textbooks
2
Replies
56
Views
5K
Replies
6
Views
3K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
34
Views
5K
  • Special and General Relativity
3
Replies
79
Views
13K
Back
Top