Exploring the Controversy Around the Axiom of Choice

In summary, the axiom of choice is an independent axiom that is not necessarily controversial, but can lead to counter-intuitive results such as the Banach-Tarski Paradox. It is often considered useful in mathematics but can also allow for the existence of non-measurable sets. The Banach-Tarski Paradox requires the existence of uncountably many atoms, although this term is used in a mathematical sense and does not refer to real-world atoms. The paradox also involves an infinite amount of choices, making it impossible to replicate in the real world.
  • #1
RandomAllTime
26
0
Hi guys. So I've been wondering, what's so controversial about the axiom of choice? I heard it allows the Banach-Tarski Paradox to work. A little insight would be much appreciated, thanks.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
RandomAllTime said:
Hi guys. So I've been wondering, what's so controversial about the axiom of choice? I heard it allows the Banach-Tarski Paradox to work. A little insight would be much appreciated, thanks.
I don't know you could call it controversial. The issue is that it is an independent axiom.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_of_choice
 
  • Like
Likes RandomAllTime
  • #3
mathman said:
I don't know you could call it controversial. The issue is that it is an independent axiom.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_of_choice
I see. I guess it's because I heard that it sort of let's the Banach Tarski Paradox hold true. Thanks for the link.
 
  • #4
If you like Banach Tarski then you like Axiom of Choice. If you don't like Banach Tarski then you are free to trash the axiom of choice, and now no Banach Tarksi.

Axiom of Choice is usually thought to be a useful thing in mathematics since (a) it seems intuitive (b) it makes it easier to prove theorems claiming that certain things exists. Well that is fine as long as those are things you kind of like to exist, but at some point it also starts allowing things to exist which see counter-intuitive, and maybe you don't like that.

For most of practical mathematics, the axiom of countable choice is quite enough to do everything you want to do. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_of_countable_choice
And you even need it to make sure that the characterisation of epsilon-delta defined convergence in terms of sequences is indeed a true theorem.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier, FactChecker, RandomAllTime and 1 other person
  • #5
gill1109 said:
If you like Banach Tarski then you like Axiom of Choice. If you don't like Banach Tarski then you are free to trash the axiom of choice, and now no Banach Tarksi.

Axiom of Choice is usually thought to be a useful thing in mathematics since (a) it seems intuitive (b) it makes it easier to prove theorems claiming that certain things exists. Well that is fine as long as those are things you kind of like to exist, but at some point it also starts allowing things to exist which see counter-intuitive, and maybe you don't like that.

For most of practical mathematics, the axiom of countable choice is quite enough to do everything you want to do. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_of_countable_choice
And you even need it to make sure that the characterisation of epsilon-delta defined convergence in terms of sequences is indeed a true theorem.
I see. Thanks
 
  • #6
RandomAllTime said:
Hi guys. So I've been wondering, what's so controversial about the axiom of choice? I heard it allows the Banach-Tarski Paradox to work. A little insight would be much appreciated, thanks.
Banach Tarski requires the existence of uncountably-many atoms, which does not hold " in this universe" . And, AFAIK, it requires infinitely-many operations.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #7
Banach-Tarski uses a mathematical fact that the number of points in a sphere is uncountable, and with the axiom of choice it can be divided into a finite number of unmeasurable sets.
 
  • #8
mathman said:
Banach-Tarski uses a mathematical fact that the number of points in a sphere is uncountable, and with the axiom of choice it can be divided into a finite number of unmeasurable sets.
Isnt this equivalent to the existence of infinitely-many ( at least countably -) atoms? And isn't the cardinality of the operations resulting in the partition infinite?
 
  • #9
WWGD said:
Isnt this equivalent to the existence of infinitely-many ( at least countably -) atoms?
No, atoms do not form a continuum. In any case you cannot "prove" anything about the real world using maths.
 
  • #10
MrAnchovy said:
No, atoms do not form a continuum. In any case you cannot "prove" anything about the real world using maths.
I mean one can argue reasonably -well that a ball containing uncountably-many points will contain infinitely-many atoms. But , yes, this would have to be laid out carefully.
 
  • #11
WWGD said:
Isnt this equivalent to the existence of infinitely-many ( at least countably -) atoms?

Yes, the Banach-Tarski paradox assumes the existence of uncountably many atoms. Although the word atom is confusing, since it has nothing to do with the real world atoms. Here, atom is just an indivisible point with zero volume.

And isn't the cardinality of the operations resulting in the partition infinite?

I don't really know what you mean with this.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #12
micromass said:
Yes, the Banach-Tarski paradox assumes the existence of uncountably many atoms. Although the word atom is confusing, since it has nothing to do with the real world atoms. Here, atom is just an indivisible point with zero volume.
I don't really know what you mean with this.
I mean the number of steps needed to do the partition.
 
  • #13
What would be a step?
 
  • #14
A transformation on the Ball , to decompose it into the nonmeasurable parts. Let me see how to define it more clearly.
 
  • #15
Why would you need to transform the ball to partition it??
 
  • #16
micromass said:
Why would you need to transform the ball to partition it??
Because we are assumming it is a physical , "real world" ball. How else would we go from a standard ball into the collection of non-measurable pieces?
 
  • #17
I don't know, but Banach-Tarski isn't about how you would do it in practice. It involves the axiom of choice and thus an infinite amount of choices which is impossible in the real world anyway.
 
  • #18
micromass said:
I don't know, but Banach-Tarski isn't about how you would do it in practice. It involves the axiom of choice and thus an infinite amount of choices which is impossible in the real world anyway.
If it were possible, I would be rich by now, buying .1 oz of gold and doubling its volume many times. I don't know if there are physical models of non-measurable sets.
 
  • #19
WWGD said:
If it were possible, I would be rich by now, buying .1 oz of gold and doubling its volume many times.

Not necessarily. Just because it is possible doesn't mean it's practically feasible. Physics still doesn't know whether there are nonmeasurable sets out there. So they might still exist.
 
  • #20
micromass said:
Not necessarily. Just because it is possible doesn't mean it's practically feasible. Physics still doesn't know whether there are nonmeasurable sets out there. So they might still exist.
Well, maybe contrived, but if I can come up with a way and convince someone of it, pretty sure I can borrow enough to have it done. But this may be far OT. And this practically feasible aspect has to see with the fact that this cannot be done in a finite number of steps, if at all. EDIT: maybe tautological, but if it could be done in a number of steps, it would be feasible.
 
  • #21
so, if we are an ultrafinitist, we needn't bother with the axiom of choice?
 
  • #22
glaucousNoise said:
so, if we are an ultrafinitist, we needn't bother with the axiom of choice?

Indeed, the axiom of choice is something that arises from the notion of infinity.
 
  • #23
hmm, what's the use of infinity, as a pure notion, rather than a practical one?

for a physicist, infinity is "a scale >> the characteristic scale of the system", but it's always actually a finite number.

when I say use, I mean for a mathematician asking a pure mathematical question, since for an applied mathematician it's clearly only useful as an approximation (except in rare philosophical circumstances where one ponders whether or not space is actually continuous etc).
 
  • #24
What's the use of anything in pure mathematics? Sure, pure math has nice applications. But when you talk about "usefulness" in pure mathematics, you must elaborate what that would be to you.
 
  • #25
What motivates mathematicians to retain this philosophically difficult definition of infinity?
 
  • #26
Because mathematicians don't find it difficult at all. Mathematically, infinity is very well understood.
 
  • #27
hmm, so why did it stop being controversial?
 
  • #28
Because it is now very well understood and it shows up in all of pure mathematics.
 
  • #29
sorry, I was referring to the axiom of choice and was unclear
 
  • #31
glaucousNoise said:
What motivates mathematicians to retain this philosophically difficult definition of infinity?
I think it is useful in e.g., probabilities, where sample spaces are often infiite, i.e., there are infnitely-many possible outcomes.
 
  • #32
The Banach-Tarski theorem needs the axiom of choice. The axiom of choice is independent of the other axioms of set theory. If you don't like the axiom of choice you can say that you don't want to have it. Instead, you can have a different axiom making all sets measurable and making Banach-Tarski theorem false. So whether or not the Banach-Tarski theorem is true has got nothing whatsoever to do with the real world but only to do with reasoning about infinite sets. What rules do we accept and what rules do we not accept?
 
  • #33
WWGD said:
I think it is useful in e.g., probabilities, where sample spaces are often infiite, i.e., there are infnitely-many possible outcomes.
but are there? suppose you take a sample of heights, and then fit a continuous distribution to those heights. When you calculate the probability of sampling a height between two data values, you're really making a guess based upon the data. Heights among humans may actually vary in discrete increments, but these increments may be so tiny (maybe on the order of nanometers) that it's reasonable to just come up with a rule (a distribution) that produces a value for any interval of rational numbers you feed it, even if it's actually invalid for small intervals (on the order of a nanometer, perhaps).

Is there a need for a notion of real numbers here? Your rule assigns a value to any rational number you give it, and there are as many of those as you'd like, but there's a discrete scale at which the distribution is effective anyway. In real statistical applications you normally need to numerically integrate anyway, which requires discretizing your continuous distribution.
 
  • #34
glaucousNoise said:
Is there a need for a notion of real numbers here?

No, there absolutely isn't. Everything you can do with real numbers is something you can do with rational numbers. But working with real numbers makes things vastly more simple, and that's why we work with them.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #35
glaucousNoise said:
but are there? suppose you take a sample of heights, and then fit a continuous distribution to those heights. When you calculate the probability of sampling a height between two data values, you're really making a guess based upon the data. Heights among humans may actually vary in discrete increments, but these increments may be so tiny (maybe on the order of nanometers) that it's reasonable to just come up with a rule (a distribution) that produces a value for any interval of rational numbers you feed it, even if it's actually invalid for small intervals (on the order of a nanometer, perhaps).

Is there a need for a notion of real numbers here? Your rule assigns a value to any rational number you give it, and there are as many of those as you'd like, but there's a discrete scale at which the distribution is effective anyway. In real statistical applications you normally need to numerically integrate anyway, which requires discretizing your continuous distribution.

How would you deal with numbers like ## e, \pi ## , which are not "made in a lab " (i.e., they come about from "real world" scenarios/situations)? Would you approximate them by Rationals to the needed level of accuracy?
 

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
5
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
13
Views
4K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
4
Views
2K
  • General Math
Replies
1
Views
734
Back
Top