Dismiss Notice
Join Physics Forums Today!
The friendliest, high quality science and math community on the planet! Everyone who loves science is here!

How can one event affect another instantly over a distance

  1. Aug 11, 2005 #1
    How can one event affect another instantly over a distance if there is no absolute concept of simultaneity? In which reference frame does the cause have a "simultaneous" effect?
    Last edited: Aug 12, 2005
  2. jcsd
  3. Aug 12, 2005 #2
    This is a pretty tough issue. Firstly let me state that when, in quantum mechanics, two measurements on the same wavefunction done at seperated locations can not really be seen as one measurement affecting the other, but we can say they are correlated to each other. Such correlation doesn't prescibe a chronical ordering like in the case of a causal interaction between both experiments, in which the 'cause' must ly within the past light-cone of the affected measurement according to special relativity.

    Now, this of course isn't the whole story, because we know that on conducting a measurement on the wavefunction, it will collapse/be projected to an eigenstate, which also affects the wavefunction localized at the location, where the other measurement is to take place. So wavefunctions themselves do not obey the causal relations as demanded by special relativity. We can get away with this by stating that the wavefunction is not a direct observable. It is, by examining both measurements, impossible to tell which one affected the other, or which one took place first.

    But ultimately it is true that quantum mechanics is flawed and that we need another theory which does obey the rules of special relativity, for instance quantum field theory.
  4. Aug 12, 2005 #3


    User Avatar

    But the "flaw" (non-locality) is present in quantum field theory as well. Indeed no known quantum theory that respects (what Bell dubbed) "serious Lorentz invariance" is known. Quantum non-locality isn't just some dismissable problem that afflicts non-relativistic quantum theories; it's inherent in quantum theory (and, as the combination of EPR and Bell's Theorem demonstrates) inherent in nature as well.

    So it seems that the most likely solution is to accept that quantum non-locality is real -- and to accept that it conflicts with what we thought relativity required -- and hence to back away from the traditional interpretation of relativity theory. This doesn't mean that all the standard relativistic formalism has to be dumped, but one apparently has to regard Lorentz invariance as some kind of emergent property -- emergent, that is, from an underlying reality that is fundamentally not relativistic.

    The obvious first cut at a way to do this is simply to return to something like the Lorentz ether theory -- a theory which actually predicts all the same formalism (Lorentz transformations, etc.) as standard relativity but does so on the assumption that there exists a preferred (ether) reference frame. What good does this do? It gives a definite *meaning* to the (near?)-simultaneous action-at-a-distance that is involved in quantum non-locality.

    Check out Bell's paper "How to Teach Special Relativity" for a nice, readable intro to some of these ideas. (It's reproduced in "Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics".) Also, for anyone who wants to understand quantum non-localilty and its relation to relativity, there is a spectacularly clear treatment of all of this in Tim Maudlin's book: "Quantum Non-Locality and Relativity." There are a lot of *bad* (muddled, unclear, wrong) books on this topic too, so if you really want to understand things you *have* to read Maudlin's book.
  5. Aug 12, 2005 #4


    User Avatar
    Staff Emeritus
    Gold Member
    Dearly Missed

    I don't think you can support an ether on the base of quantum nonlocality. Remember that QED, for example, is "manifestly covariant", i.e it does obey everything that relativity requires, and it also exhibits, as you say, quantum nonlocality. So either QED is inconsistent (which has NOT been shown!) or quantum nonlocality does not violate relativity requirements. What relativity requires is that CAUSE not be transfered FTL, and there is no transfer of cause in quantum nonlocality, just an after the fact correlation that shows up in the shared future light cone of the two particles.

    The view that this constitutes non locality in the relativistic sense is based on an unexamined tendency to view QM is a classical theory, to treat it as if it were in fact one of the hidden variable theories that the Bell inequalities ruled out.
  6. Aug 12, 2005 #5
    Nonlocality doesn't mean that an event at A causes an
    event at B, where A and B are spatially, maybe even spacelike,

    Nonlocal observational contexts are global contexts involving
    the correlation of two or more detection events. But, the
    detection events aren't correlated to each other, they're
    correlated to changes in a global, independent variable.

    For example, a common Bell test setup involves entangled
    photons, where you have an emitter, linear polarizers at each
    of two arms of the setup, and a photon detector behind each
    polarizer. Like this:

    detector A <--- polarizer <-- emitter --> polarizer --> detector B

    The determining variable in this setup is the value of
    Theta, which is the angular difference between the
    settings of the two polarizers.

    The probabilistic state of the entire system changes
    instantaneously (or simultaneously) with changes in
    Theta, and Theta changes instantaneously (simultaneously)
    as the setting of either polarizer is changed.

    If Theta is disregarded and we simply change
    the polarizer setting at A, then no corresponding change in
    the photon flux (rate of detection per unit of time) at B
    is seen. In fact, nothing done at A is seen to have any
    effect on the detection rate at B, or vice versa.

    It's only when the combined results, (A,B), are correlated
    wrt Theta that predictable changes in the rate of
    *coincidental* detection are seen.

    Results at A and B are paired or correlated initially via
    a coincidence interval defined by a common clock, and then
    those pairs are correlated to the specific Theta for that

    As should be evident, all of this transpires in real time
    in accordance with the constraints of special relativity.

    The problem is this: wrt the underlying reality of the
    polarizer-incident (emitted) optical disturbances that might
    be associated with paired photon detections, what are the
    necessary and sufficient preconditions at the submicroscopic
    level to produce predictable coincidence rates due to changes
    in Theta?

    Setups are prepared with the idea in mind that the disturbances
    incident on the polarizers must have a common cause (such as
    coming from the same oscillator) in order to get Bell inequality
    violating results.

    Violations of Bell inequalities tell us that this common
    origin, and a relationship between the two disturbances
    imparted therefrom, can't be the *cause* of the predictable
    changes in coincidence rates -- and it isn't.

    The changes in coincidence rate are caused by changes in

    It follows that the relationship (defined by, eg., conservation
    of angular momentum) between disturbances having
    a common origin is not varying from pair to pair, even though
    the specific motional properties (eg., angle of polarization, etc.)
    are varying randomly from pair to pair.

    It's this underlying relationship, imparted via common origin,
    that is the 'entanglement' of the polarizer-incident optical
    disturbances at the submicroscopic level.
    By itself, ala Bell, it can't account for the observed variable
    coincidence rates. Nor can the apparent random variablitity of
    specific motional properties from pair to pair.

    To account for (ie., to produce) predictable variable coincidence
    rates, you need a global, instrumental or observational variable,
    like Theta, the angular difference between the analyzing
  7. Aug 12, 2005 #6


    User Avatar
    Science Advisor
    Gold Member

    Nonlocality is a very difficult issue. Almost every angle of the discussion involves definitions, and few people will precisely agree about those definitions. So that is often the source of disagreements...

    You definitely do not "need" to hypothesize a global (nonlocal) variable called "theta" to explain the observed results. You need the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle, which still applies in cases of entanglement. You cannot extract more information about the particles than the HUP allows.

    Note that theta only explains about the polarization of entangled photons, and does not explain why the other photon attributes are also entangled. I.e. position, momentum, etc.

    The real question is: how do you explain the physicality of the results? I don't think non-local hidden variables is the answer. In fact, I am not sure there is an answer.
  8. Aug 12, 2005 #7


    User Avatar

    The objectionable non-locality is not in Schroedinger's equation (or its analog in the context of a relativistic quantum field theory like QED). So it is irrelevant that those equations are "manifestly covariant". The nonlocality in the orthodox theories is in the collapse postulate. This is something that doesn't get any explicit attention in QED/QFT textbooks because the assumption is, by the time you're learning QED, you already know enough QM to know that to calculate probabilities for things you only need to calculate the appropriate matrix elements. So the texts simply teach you how to calculate matrix elements for certain scattering processes and things like that.

    But the collapse postulate is still lurking as an inelimanble (if unmentioned) part of the theory, at least as long as you want to claim that QED is consistent with the fact that when you go into the lab and actually *do* one of the scattering experiments mentioned above, you get some definite outcome (e.g., a certain electron is detected to have scattered into a certain angle... as opposed to: the electron scatters into all angles simultaneously with the whole array of detectors all flashing "bing!" but in parallel universes).

    So... it's just what I said originally: orthodox quantum theory is non-local. It violates Bell's Locality condition ("Bell Locality"). And any attempt to blame this *apparent* non-locality on the non-completeness of the quantum mechanical description (i.e., any attempt to explain the correlations by reference to some local common cause that was un-accounted-for in the wave function) must fail. That's Bell's Theorem. Hence Bell Locality is false. Nature violates Bell Locality.

    And so to whatever extent Bell Locality accurately captures relativity's prohibition on superluminal causation (and Bell and I and many others think it captures it just perfectly), relativity is wrong. And as Bell pointed out, the cheapest way of dealing with this conflict is to combine something like Bohmian Mechanics and Lorentz ether theory.

    Hogwash. The view that violation of Bell Locality constitutes a problem for relativity is based on an analysis of relativity -- it's based on taking relativity *seriously* and not just spewing bromides about how relativity prohibits superluminal communication. It's true that relativity prohibits *at least* superluminal communication, but if that's *all* it prohibits, then all sorts of blatantly non-local theories (like orthodox QM and Bohmian Mechanics) which involve blatant non-local action-at-a-distance are rendered consistent with relativity. Bell was smart enough to figure out a way to define a stronger condition, a condition not just prohibiting some vaguely defined act that humans sometimes take ("communication"), but really identifying the guts of relativistic causality. To suggest that Bell's analysis was based on an "unexamined tendency to view QM is a classical theory" is preposterous and insulting to a great genius.

    Finally: your last sentence implies that Bell's Theorem rules out hidden variable theories, i.e., proves that QM is complete. That's wrong. Bohmian Mechanics is a counter example to that claim.
  9. Aug 12, 2005 #8


    User Avatar
    Science Advisor
    Gold Member

    Well said! :smile:

    Just as a reminder, Special Relativity is intended to apply within certain constraints. Within a particular reference frame, c is the speed of photons and other force carriers, and less than c is the speed of particles with mass. So just in case someone is bothered by the statement above that "relativity is wrong":

    1. We don't know if there are rolled up dimensions or other somethings (causal wormholes?) that would allow causes to propagate in apparent violation of Bell Locality.

    2. There are already known cases in which objects are receding from Earth at speeds in excess of 3c. This does not necessarily violate GR though.
  10. Aug 12, 2005 #9
    For sure. I was just offering my perspective on a small slice
    of the bigger pie ... so to speak. :-) Last night I did a search
    at arxiv.org on "entangled" and "entanglement" in quant-ph and
    got about 300 results. Tonight I'll try "nonlocality", etc.

    The number of variations on the basic theme, and the associated
    terminology seems to be expanding at a pretty fast rate.

    Theta isn't a hypothetical variable. It's the actual joint setting of
    the polarizers, and it determines the variable rate of coincidental
    detection. I used this type of setup as an example, because
    it's the most common Bell test setup, and a bit easier to visualize
    than some others you might be thinking of.

    Not sure what you mean by the "physicality of the results". But
    if you mean what I think you mean, then variations in Theta and
    a hidden constant would explain the results in the setup I presented.
    Theta is the angular difference between the crossed linear
    polarizers. It isn't a hidden variable. Bell's analysis holds.
    That is, the variable rotational properties of the optical
    disturbances incident on the polarizers can't be used to predict
    coincidence rates which vary as Theta varies.

    Such rotational properties (local hidden variables) could, however,
    if we knew what they were, according to Bell, be used to predict
    individual detection sequences at either A or B.
  11. Aug 12, 2005 #10
    Thanks! All these replies have been very helpful, but as usual with quantum mechanics the range of different ideas can be pretty frightenning and hard to make heads or tails of. So I'm still scratching my head on this one. :grumpy:

    This is what bothers me. If you say that Bell's theorem proves that there is some sort of instantaneous information exchange (of any kind) over vast distances, that would mean that you are talking about some sense of "simultaneity", but of course in special relativity you have to have a reference frame from which to state something is "simultaneous". In another reference frame, such things won't be simultaneous. Is there a specific reference frame from which the exchange can be said to happen simultaneously or is it supposed to apply to all reference frames? If it is the former then there would be reference frames in which causality is violated. If it is the latter then the relativity of simultaneity must be wrong, which is very troubling because Minkowskian spacetime and general relativity are built from a framework in which relativity of simultaneity is true. Perhaps this is the reason string theorists are attempting to find a different approach to gravitation... But if relativity is so obviously wrong why haven't we reverted back to an ether theory as someone suggested? Although it is commonly known that relativity and quantum mechanics don't agree in situations where they are both pushed to their limits (black holes, big bang), this seems to be a bit more of a substantial disagreement. And while black holes and the big bang may point to flaws in general relativity and the need to find a theory of quantum gravity, the disagreement between locality and non-locality seems to show that not even special relativity can be valid, unless of course Bell's theorem is wrong. So it seems to me that before we even try to come up with a theory of quantum gravity, we need to know if special relativity is even correct. And if special relativity is valid, then it seems there must be some vital flaw in quantum theory. :confused:
  12. Aug 12, 2005 #11


    User Avatar
    Science Advisor
    Gold Member

    What I am saying is that there is no problem applying QM where it is supposed to be applied, and there is no problem applying SR where is it supposed to be applied. The apparent conflicts may not be real, they may derive from trying to make one theory fit where it shouldn't.

    Keep in mind: Bell's Theorem also assumes "reality" as well as "locality". Locality is not ruled out if you accept that reality is observer dependent. Of course, I have no idea what such "non-reality" actually is... but the point is that there is definitely an escape route out of the conflict.
  13. Aug 12, 2005 #12


    User Avatar
    Science Advisor
    Gold Member

    Theta is a number, I agree with that. But it is not a fundamental observable, it is derived from 2 other fundamental observables. Those two observables are redundant, because the HUP limits information about any particle.

    In some ways, our disagreement is semantic. Theta acts "as if" it were real. But that is not how QM gets to that point. Once you measure particle A, you learn about B. Using that information about B, you measure B at some other polarizer angle but gain absolutely NO information in that process. The resulting stats are no different than if you measured any single photon's spin at 2 angles - which forms the exact same Theta you describe. So Theta has nothing but a tangential relationship to entanglement - it is not required to be fundamental to it.

    So to summarize: HUP applies to single particles and entangled systems. Theta also applies to single particles and entangled systems. But Theta can be derived using the HUP, while the HUP cannot be derived from Theta. So decide for yourself which is more fundamental. Don't forget that the HUP also covers position and momentum, while Theta does not.
  14. Aug 12, 2005 #13


    User Avatar

    I think you are using "information" here in its most general sense, right? Usually people in this field define "information" more narrowly, though -- as the "knowledge stuff" that humans sometimes transfer to one another by talking, etc. There is a certain precise definition of locality that is based on this idea. It's called "signal locality" or "information locality" and means simply that one cannot send a message or signal faster than light. It's possible to write down a certain mathematical condition equivalent to this, and then to ask whether or not various theories satisfy the condition. Regular quantum theory, for example, passes the test -- it is "signal local". And so does Bohmian Mechanics. It too is "signal local". This just means that, according to these theories, it is impossible in principle to transmit a message to another person faster than light. So in that sense of "locality" both of these theories (and of course many others too) are consistent with relativity.

    But Bell and others felt that this condition was too weak. As I said before, there's no question that relativity requires at least signal locality. But the two signal local theories I mentioned (orthodox QM and Bohmian Mechanics) are both non-local in another obvious kind of way. In OQM, the collapse postulate seems to rather blatantly violate some kind of common sense notion of local causality. Likewise, in Bohmian Mechanics, the dynamical laws are blatantly non-local: the trajectory of a given particle can depend on the fields or whatever encountered by another entangled particle, even if the other one is very far away. And yet both these theories are consistent with signal locality! So clearly, by example, it's possible to have a theory that seems to rather blatantly violate the no-faster-than-light-causation requirement of relativity, but which, nevertheless, cannot be harnessed by humans to build faster-than-light telephones. This is what motivated Bell to define another mathematical condition ("Bell Locality") which is supposed to test whether a theory is *really* consistent with relativity or not. Orthodox QM turns out to violate Bell Locality. So does Bohmian Mechanics. And Bell proved an amazing theorem: *any* theory that agrees with the (empirically verified) predictions of quantum theory has to violate Bell Locality.

    So (assuming you believe the experiments, and the loopholes are awfully narrow), it's just a fact that Bell Locality is violated in nature. Some people (like me) think this is a problem. Bell certainly thought so:

    "For me then this is the real problem with quantum theory: the apparently essential conflict between any sharp formulation and fundamental relativity. That is to say, we have an apparent incompatibility, at the deepest level, between the two fundamental pillars of contemporary theory..."

    Other people disagree that Bell Locality is an appropriate test for relativistic causality. For example, some think that the weaker "signal locality" condition is *all* that relativity requires. So they conclude that there is really no conflict between QM and SR. But then, about 99% of these same people would say that Bohmian Mechanics (and other hidden variable theories) should be rejected because those theories have to be (as proved by Bell's Theorem) non-local. Hopefully you can see now why that's such a preposterous view!

    An excellent question, one that should be asked about the collapse postulate to any advocate of orthodox QM!

    More generally, you're thinking along exactly the right lines here. If you agree that nature's violation of Bell Locality means that there is some kind of instantaneous (or near-instantaneous... much faster than light is all that really matters here) causality-at-a-distance in nature, it just doesn't make sense that nature can be fundamentally relativistic. There would have to be some special frame in which the instantaneous causality *happens* -- some particular frame relative to which "instantaneity" is *defined*. And relativity says there's no such thing.

    I think this is all review at this point, but hopefully it clarifies exactly what the problem is and why some people are so resistant to seeing it. Relativity has served physicists well for a hundred years, so you can understand why they're hesitant to admit that, after all, it turns out to be wrong (or at least not as fundamental as everyone thought). This is surely what motivates some of the obfuscation and inconsistency you find everywhere on this issue.


    Actually, the inconsistency between relativity and QM that motivates string theory is a different issue, much more technical. String theory is definitely not motivated by an attempt to reconcile quantum non-locality with relativity. But I agree completely with the sentiment you express below:
    it seems premature to be working on some extremely high-level, technical unification of the quantum and relativistic formalisms, if we haven't even figured out how to reconcile them in terms of basic, elementary concepts. Of course, it's possible that fixing the technical details will turn out to lead to some kind of resolution at the level of the fundamentals, too; but to me it seems more like rearranging deck chairs into a very fancy pattern on a titanic that's sinking. Fix the fundamentals first, then worry about the super advanced complicated unifications and such.

    It's a bit too simple to say "relativity is wrong." Surely the *equations* of relativity are right, or at least are right in the kinds of situations where we know they're right because we've tested the theory's predictions there. The question is more whether the standard conceptual structure motivating those equations (in particular the so-called "principle of relativity") is true. Part of the problem is that many physicists suffer from a "shut up and calculate" attitude that makes them very resistant to even taking fundamental conceptual or interpretational or foundational issues seriously. Unfortunately, this leaves them susceptible to the kind of obfuscation and muddle-headed thinking I indicated above (e.g., "There's no conflict between QM and SR because you can't use QM to send a signal faster than light; but we shouldn't consider hidden variable alternatives to QM like Bohmian Mechanics, for, as Bell's Theorem proves, those theories are non-local and hence in conflict with SR."). But that's a whole 'nuther can of worms, as they say.
  15. Aug 12, 2005 #14
    I was under the impression that the collapse postulate is only considered an approximation, since it does not define precisely what constitutes "measurement". So if all nonlocality in QM flows from the collapse postulate, then the nonlocality may not be physically real, just an artifact of the approximation.

    In the many-worlds approach, for example, there is no need for the notion of nonlocality. I am still trying to understand dynamical collapse theories, so I don't know if they make nonlocality go away as well. Maybe someone who understands them better can answer -- do dynamical collapse theories eliminate the apparent nonlocality of orthodox QM?
  16. Aug 12, 2005 #15
    I enter this discussion because I am confused about statements concerning importance of "locality" to physics and science in general. Perhaps it has to deal with definition. Here is a definition that makes sense to me as a scientist, from this link:http://www.mtnmath.com/whatrh/node76.html

    "Locality is the denial of action at a distance.

    It requires that all the information useful in predicting what will happen at a given location and time is contained in a sphere of influence. For an event that will occur in one second the sphere has a radius of 300,000 kilometers, the distance light travels in one second.

    Locality is the most powerful simplifying assumption in physics. Without it any event no matter how distant can influence any other event. Prediction would be impossible without locality or some other powerful restriction on what events can affect other events. Otherwise one would need to know the state of the universe to predict anything.

    Quantum mechanics is a local theory in configuration space but not in physical space."

    Now, if the above holds, then clearly QM and Relativity will not find conflict in questions dealing with "configuration space", but they may very well be in conflict within "physical space"--which is also called "real space". If I read the above correctly, QM attributes of an entity must have "non-local" affects only within physical space.

    But what is configuration space and how does it differ from "real space" ? One answer is from Nick Herbert, 1985, Quantum Reality, pp. 135, 169-170. According to Herbert, it is only within configuration space that exist the attributes of "position and momentum" of the waveform. Within "real space" (physical space) the major attribute is spin orientation Sx, Sy, Sz in three orthogonal directions.

    Next, Herbert makes an important statement (p 169-170) that I quote:

    "The reason that quantum waves become phase-entangled and ordinary waves don't is that quantum waves do not make home in ordinary three-dimensional space (e.g. the place of spin orientation--my added) but in a place called configuration space".

    Thus, Herbert seems to suggest (correct me if I error) that the QM concept of the waveform only applies to the configuation space aspect of Reality, and DOES NOT EXIST within the physical space of Reality--in short--as known by Einstein, QM is a theory with a limit, and that limit is called physical reality. This outcome obtains because QM holds most dear the concept of "phase entanglement"--which is a process that is limited to configuation space.
  17. Aug 12, 2005 #16
    Associative simultanianeous events

    Forgive me for even typing near you guys but, I would interject that a "region" or locale does not necessarily mean all in one area. It can also apply to the commonality of events and thier common, root causes. Those events of a similar origin will occur, sometimes simultaneously, in a region of homogeneous but random "locations". The "relative" distance between them is not "distance" as we see it but is another type of "region" we call "distance" that is an arbitrary boundary for an infinitely varied number of other "regional events". I don't know if this helps.
    Last edited: Aug 12, 2005
  18. Aug 12, 2005 #17
    It seems to me that if we hold as true the statement: Locality exists if <reality is observer dependent>, then by logic we must conclude that non-locality exist if <non-reality is observer independent>.

    For example, travel > c (an aspect of non-locality) is possible for entities that are non-reality and which exist independent of observer [e.g., think virtual pions within proton which exist in essence in the zero point vacuum (configuration space) but not in fact (physical space of the valence quarks)]. I think this line of reason helps explain what "non-reality actually is " (or may be) in terms of QM.
  19. Aug 13, 2005 #18
    Theta is the angular difference between the polarizer settings.
    In the joint observational context, it's a single variable correlated
    to (A,B).

    I'm not familiar with Bell tests that require HUP. That is, I don't
    recall HUP being mentioned in the experiments that I have copies
    of here (Aspect et al., and a few others). So, I'm not sure
    what you're saying.

    Theta doesn't "act as if" it were real. It is real. It's an
    instrumental setting that defines the observational context.
    The context, so defined, is a nonlocal context.

    This context isn't looking at individual particles. It's looking
    at the combined results, (A,B), and how these results are
    related to Theta.

    In the observational context that I described (the one that has
    been most commonly used in Bell tests), we're not looking at
    individual results. QM isn't describing individual results at A or
    individual results at B in this context, because (A,B) and Theta
    (the angular difference between the polarizers) are one system.

    Theta is analyzing (measuring) a common (global) property of the
    polarizer-incident optical disturbances that isn't varying, and
    isn't present in the individual measurement context.

    Bell's analysis showed that formulations based on treating
    A and B as separate systems with variations in (A,B) being
    determined by a variable global Lambda are inadequate.
    This doesn't necessarily mean that a variable global Lambda
    isn't present in the joint context -- but it does mean that
    even if it is present, it isn't relevant to (A,B). What *is*
    determining (A,B) is the variable Theta. This observational
    fact allows for some reasonable inferences about some
    general characteristics of what the polarizers are jointly
    analyzing in the combined context.

    Hence, experimental violations of Bell inequalities are taken to be
    an indicator of the presence of a global, emission-imparted property
    (a hidden constant), ie. the presence of entanglement.

    Tests of Bell inequalities are comparing the efficacy of a
    separable formulation to a nonseparable formulation.

    A and B are not being related to each other, but rather (A,B) is
    being related to variations in a global instrumental variable (Theta).
    So, Theta must be analyzing some global property of the
    incident optical disturbances. It's logical to assume that
    this global property is created via common cause or local
    interaction and carried by the optical disturbances to the
    polarizers. Bell's lhv formulation doesn't contradict this idea.
    What Bell's lhv formulation contradicts is the idea that, in
    the global context, the global property of the optical disturbances
    that is determining variable rates of coincidental detection
    is a variable. It isn't. It can't be, because Theta is the variable
    that's determining variable rates of coincidental detection.
  20. Aug 13, 2005 #19
    If you want to model the system-dependent behavior
    of two spatially separated objects (that are part of the
    same encompassing behavioral system) in terms of the
    separated behaviors of the individual objects, then you'll
    need some sort of instantaneous signal propagating between
    the two in order to get the right joint predictions.

    But you don't have to do it that way. :-)

    Consider two points on opposite sides of the circumference
    of a circle in some coordinate system. Rotate the circle.
    Did the points change coordinates in a predictable way
    because they're communicating with each other, or because
    of the rotation of the circle and their unchanging relationship
    wrt each other on the circumference of the circle?

    Although this is an oversimplification, the principle here
    is the same wrt nonlocality (qm or Bohmian or whatever).
    It has to do with system-dependent behavior.

    In typical optical Bell tests, paired photons don't need to
    be sending any sort of signals back and forth to each
    other. They just need to have a more or less unvarying
    relationship wrt each other prior to hitting the polarizers.

    In Bell's lhv formulation, Lambda (the global property of the
    incident optical disturbances) is a hidden variable in the
    global context. Bell showed that such a formulation doesn't
    adequately describe the global context. Why? Is it because
    the global property of the incident optical disturbances
    isn't due to a common cause or local interaction? Or, is
    it because the relevant global property of the incident
    optical disturbances, in the system-dependent view, isn't

    Qm correctly describes the observational context (albeit
    somewhat incompletely describing the physical reality, so that
    there are still problems with collapse and projection, etc.),
    because it treats the emission-produced *relationship* between
    the incident optical disturbances as a constant rather than a
  21. Aug 13, 2005 #20


    User Avatar

    Say you have a 2-particle system. Each particle is able to move around in the usual 3 dimensions of space, to to specify the precise configuration of the system at some point you'd have to specify x1, y1, z1, and x2, y2, and z2 -- that is, the coordinates for each particle. Configuration space is just an abstract space which (in this example) is 6 dimensional -- the 6 dimensions being x1, y1, z1, x2, y2, and z2. Thus, the configuration of the whole system can be specified by specifying a *point* in the configuration space. This is really just a mathematical device. Sometimes it's convenient to think abstractly of the system configuration as a single "particle" that just moves around (in time) in the configuration space. But there is no more or no less meaning to this than: each indidvidual particle is just moving around in some way in regular 3d physical space.

    So the claim that QM is non-local in physical space but local in configuration space is really pretty inane. It is admittedly possible to give a meaning to the latter part of the statement, but it certainly isn't a meaning that reduces in any way the tension between QM and relativity. To be local in configuration space is still to permit instantaneous action at a distance between separated particles in real physical space. So it's just a red herring or diversion tactic.

    One answer is from Nick Herbert, 1985, Quantum Reality, pp. 135, 169-170. According to Herbert, it is only within configuration space that exist the attributes of "position and momentum" of the waveform. Within "real space" (physical space) the major attribute is spin orientation Sx, Sy, Sz in three orthogonal directions.

    Next, Herbert makes an important statement (p 169-170) that I quote:

    "The reason that quantum waves become phase-entangled and ordinary waves don't is that quantum waves do not make home in ordinary three-dimensional space (e.g. the place of spin orientation--my added) but in a place called configuration space".

    Thus, Herbert seems to suggest (correct me if I error) that the QM concept of the waveform only applies to the configuation space aspect of Reality, and DOES NOT EXIST within the physical space of Reality--in short--as known by Einstein, QM is a theory with a limit, and that limit is called physical reality. This outcome obtains because QM holds most dear the concept of "phase entanglement"--which is a process that is limited to configuation space.[/QUOTE]
Know someone interested in this topic? Share this thread via Reddit, Google+, Twitter, or Facebook

Have something to add?