Does MWI Adequately Explain Observer Branching in Quantum Mechanics?

  • Thread starter Blue Scallop
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Mwi
In summary, the conversation discussed the concept of Many-Worlds Interpretation (MWI) and the confusion surrounding the use of the term "splitting" in relation to observers in the double slit experiment. Peterdonis corrected the misunderstanding that MWI assumes the brain is classical and explained that everything, including observers, is viewed as quantum in this interpretation. The environment and system do not split, but rather become entangled in a superposition of states. The term "splitting" is not the most accurate way to describe this process, and the use of mathematical language is preferred. The double slit experiment is not the best example to illustrate the concept of MWI, as it involves changing the experimental setup, while a measurement of spin would
  • #1
Blue Scallop
290
17
It seems many people even experts don't understand the basic of MWI. In the double slit.. what is wrong with the statement that "that observer will "split" as well--one version of him for each way the double slit experiment came out.". Peterdonis wrote it. And I included it in a thread as reference. But Nugatory stated whether it is based on a solid premise. And I'm getting confused. The environment doesn't split, only the system, yes? So the observer should "split". No? Other synonyms for "split"?

How do you use more accurate phrases to describe what happen to the observers in the double slit in MWI?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #3
bhobba said:
See:
http://www.anthropic-principle.com/preprints/manyworlds.html

Forget the double slit - its a red herring here.

Thanks
Bill

In Q8 in your article. It's written:

"The cat splits when the device is triggered, irreversibly. The
investigator splits when they open the box. The alive cat has no idea
that investigator has split, any more than it is aware that there is a
dead cat in the neighbouring split-off world. The investigator can
deduce, after the event, by examining the cyanide mechanism, or the
cat's memory, that the cat split prior to opening the box."

Why is this not a red herring and why is the double slit a red herring?
 
  • #4
Blue Scallop said:
Nugatory stated whether it is based on a solid premise

The problem with the thread that got closed wasn't your statement (referring to mine) about "splitting". It was your statement that "MWI assumes the brain is classical". It doesn't.

Nor is it really correct to view the different "worlds" that get split off in the MWI as classical. The MWI is an interpretation of quantum mechanics, not classical mechanics. It assumes that everything is quantum, including you and me.

Blue Scallop said:
The environment doesn't split, only the system, yes?

No. See below.

Blue Scallop said:
How do you use more accurate phrases to describe what happen to the observers in the double slit in MWI?

You don't. You use math.

The double slit is a bad example to use because there are not two distinct "results" of the experiment when it is run the same way multiple times. To change the result you have to change the experimental setup (close one of the slits, put measuring devices at the slits, etc.). That's not what the MWI is talking about.

A better example is a measurement of the spin of a spin-1/2 particle about a fixed axis. Such a measurement, when run the same way multiple times, will yield one of two results each time, which we can call "up" and "down" and denote by the symbols ##+## and ##-##. For each run, the measuring device starts out in a state we can call "ready" and denote by the symbol ##R##, and ends up in either the "measured spin up" state or the "measured spin down" state, which we can denote by the symbols ##U## and ##D##. Mathematically, we write this evolution of states during the measurement as follows:

$$
\vert \Psi \rangle \vert R \rangle = \left( a \vert + \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \right) \vert R \rangle \rightarrow \vert \Psi' \rangle = a \vert + \rangle \vert U \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

Here ##a## and ##b## are complex numbers that satisfy ##\vert a \vert^2 + \vert b \vert^2 = 1##.

The best ordinary language term to describe the above evolution is not "splitting" but "entanglement": the state of the measuring device gets entangled with the state of the measured system. The term "splitting" comes from focusing on the fact that the measuring device starts out in the state ##R##, but ends up in a superposition of states (more precisely, as factors in two terms of a superposition: the measuring device in the entangled state after the measurement does not have a state that is separable from the state of the measured system). But that is focusing on just a piece of the wave function instead of the whole wave function. And notice that the other piece, the state of the measured system, does not change at all; there are ##+## and ##-## terms in ##\Psi## and there are ##+## and ##-## terms in ##\Psi'##, with the same coefficients.

Also, the above evolution applies just as well if the "measuring device" is an observer like you or me: it just says that our state becomes entangled with the state of the measured system, so the states ##U## and ##D## are something like "I observed the spin to be up" and "I observed the spin to be down". So we ourselves, if we take the QM math at face value, end up in states that are not separable from the states of the things we observe.

The two main types of QM interpretations are identical up to this point; where they differ is in what happens next. In no collapse interpretations like the MWI, nothing happens next; the wave function ##\Psi'## just keeps on undergoing unitary evolution, just as the process that goes from ##\Psi## to ##\Psi'## is unitary evolution. In collapse interpretations like Copenhagen, the state "collapses" from ##\Psi'## to one of the two terms in it; the probability of collapsing to each term is given by the squared modulus of its coefficient (##a## or ##b##).
 
  • Like
Likes Blue Scallop and bhobba
  • #5
PeterDonis said:
The double slit is a bad example to use because there are not two distinct "results" of the experiment when it is run the same way multiple times. To change the result you have to change the experimental setup (close one of the slits, put measuring devices at the slits, etc.). That's not what the MWI is talking about.

That's exactly what I meant - in discussing MW it's not a good example.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #6
PeterDonis said:
The problem with the thread that got closed wasn't your statement (referring to mine) about "splitting". It was your statement that "MWI assumes the brain is classical". It doesn't.

Nor is it really correct to view the different "worlds" that get split off in the MWI as classical. The MWI is an interpretation of quantum mechanics, not classical mechanics. It assumes that everything is quantum, including you and me.

I mentioned the brain was classical because I thought each world of MWI was collapsed. When you see airplanes and roads.. they definitely looked collapsed. But in Everett times. there was not any concept of Decoherence. So did Everett think each world/branch of MWI is collapsed or not? Even now. Decoherence concept says each world of MWI forms because of decoherence. But within a world/branch.. it's also sustained by internal decoherence (our automobile is not in two places at once because the environment measures each atoms of the automobile putting it in classical state) and so each world/branch is not really collapsed? Did Everett think of this originally? Or did he think automobile are collapsed because each world/branch is collapsed? But in Everett times, where concept of decoherence didn't exist. How could he think of world as not collapsed and how was it sustained (if not by decoherence processes inside each world/branch)?

Thanks for all below. I understood what you meant how spin was better example of two distinct results than double slit. 5 stars.
No. See below.
You don't. You use math.

The double slit is a bad example to use because there are not two distinct "results" of the experiment when it is run the same way multiple times. To change the result you have to change the experimental setup (close one of the slits, put measuring devices at the slits, etc.). That's not what the MWI is talking about.

A better example is a measurement of the spin of a spin-1/2 particle about a fixed axis. Such a measurement, when run the same way multiple times, will yield one of two results each time, which we can call "up" and "down" and denote by the symbols ##+## and ##-##. For each run, the measuring device starts out in a state we can call "ready" and denote by the symbol ##R##, and ends up in either the "measured spin up" state or the "measured spin down" state, which we can denote by the symbols ##U## and ##D##. Mathematically, we write this evolution of states during the measurement as follows:

$$
\vert \Psi \rangle \vert R \rangle = \left( a \vert + \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \right) \vert R \rangle \rightarrow \vert \Psi' \rangle = a \vert + \rangle \vert U \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

Here ##a## and ##b## are complex numbers that satisfy ##\vert a \vert^2 + \vert b \vert^2 = 1##.

The best ordinary language term to describe the above evolution is not "splitting" but "entanglement": the state of the measuring device gets entangled with the state of the measured system. The term "splitting" comes from focusing on the fact that the measuring device starts out in the state ##R##, but ends up in a superposition of states (more precisely, as factors in two terms of a superposition: the measuring device in the entangled state after the measurement does not have a state that is separable from the state of the measured system). But that is focusing on just a piece of the wave function instead of the whole wave function. And notice that the other piece, the state of the measured system, does not change at all; there are ##+## and ##-## terms in ##\Psi## and there are ##+## and ##-## terms in ##\Psi'##, with the same coefficients.

Also, the above evolution applies just as well if the "measuring device" is an observer like you or me: it just says that our state becomes entangled with the state of the measured system, so the states ##U## and ##D## are something like "I observed the spin to be up" and "I observed the spin to be down". So we ourselves, if we take the QM math at face value, end up in states that are not separable from the states of the things we observe.

The two main types of QM interpretations are identical up to this point; where they differ is in what happens next. In no collapse interpretations like the MWI, nothing happens next; the wave function ##\Psi'## just keeps on undergoing unitary evolution, just as the process that goes from ##\Psi## to ##\Psi'## is unitary evolution. In collapse interpretations like Copenhagen, the state "collapses" from ##\Psi'## to one of the two terms in it; the probability of collapsing to each term is given by the squared modulus of its coefficient (##a## or ##b##).
 
Last edited:
  • #7
PeterDonis said:
The double slit is a bad example to use because there are not two distinct "results" of the experiment when it is run the same way multiple times. To change the result you have to change the experimental setup (close one of the slits, put measuring devices at the slits, etc.). That's not what the MWI is talking about.

Once the particle gets detected at position x_i on the screen (I'm keeping it discrete for convenience and because ultimately the screen is made of atoms anyway), there is some kind of signal that is the detected by the observer. Result: you get states of the form |particle detected at x_i>|observer saw light coming from position x_i>, so MWI does assert that the worlds do split, once for each detection event. So I don't think this example is misleading, or a "bad question", or anything like that.
 
  • #8
Blue Scallop said:
I mentioned the brain was classical because I thought each world of MWI was collapsed.

There is no collapse in the MWI. So evidently you were thinking of the MWI wrong.

Blue Scallop said:
When you see airplanes and roads.. they definitely looked collapsed.

They look the way they look, according to the MWI, because your state is entangled with their states. No collapse required.

Blue Scallop said:
Decoherence concept says each world of MWI forms because of decoherence.

No. Decoherence explains why each "world" (branch of the wave function) remains self-consistent. It is not needed to explain how each branch forms: that's just simple unitary evolution.

Blue Scallop said:
our automobile is not in two places at once because the environment measures each atoms of the automobile putting it in classical state

This is ok except for the last part: "putting in classical state". You should banish the word "classical" and anything connected with it from your thinking if you are trying to use the MWI. You should also banish the word "collapse", and banish the idea that decoherence has anything to do with collapse. It doesn't.
 
  • #9
PeterDonis said:
There is no collapse in the MWI. So evidently you were thinking of the MWI wrong.
They look the way they look, according to the MWI, because your state is entangled with their states. No collapse required.
No. Decoherence explains why each "world" (branch of the wave function) remains self-consistent. It is not needed to explain how each branch forms: that's just simple unitary evolution.

In your spin example. You mean even if we don't observe it (and entangling with it) or there is no measuring device.. the spin up and spin down still form a branch?

Does the Universal Wave Function has information on everything in the universe like the Higgs vacuum expectation values and all constant of nature? Or is the Universal Wave function just ignorant of them and separate from these information?

This is ok except for the last part: "putting in classical state". You should banish the word "classical" and anything connected with it from your thinking if you are trying to use the MWI. You should also banish the word "collapse", and banish the idea that decoherence has anything to do with collapse. It doesn't.
 
  • #10
Blue Scallop said:
You mean even if we don't observe it (and entangling with it) or there is no measuring device.. the spin up and spin down still form a branch?

No.

Blue Scallop said:
Does the Universal Wave Function has information on everything in the universe like the Higgs vacuum expectation values and all constant of nature?

The Higgs VEV is a property of quantum field interactions, so the wave function would include information about it. A constant like the fine structure constant--the coupling constant for electromagnetic interactions--isn't really a property of the wave function, it's a property of the Lagrangian.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #11
PeterDonis said:
No.

But you just mentioned that "No. Decoherence explains why each "world" (branch of the wave function) remains self-consistent. It is not needed to explain how each branch forms: that's just simple unitary evolution."

You said decoherence not needed to explain how each branch forms. So I thought the branch already there even without decoherence. So you are saying that indeed decoherence is really needed to explain how each branch forms? What you mean "self-consistent". Please clarify your statements. Thank you.

The Higgs VEV is a property of quantum field interactions, so the wave function would include information about it. A constant like the fine structure constant--the coupling constant for electromagnetic interactions--isn't really a property of the wave function, it's a property of the Lagrangian.
 
  • #12
Blue Scallop said:
I mentioned the brain was classical because I thought each world of MWI was collapsed.
Not at all... There is no collapse in MWI, and that is its biggest selling point.
 
  • #13
Blue Scallop said:
You said decoherence not needed to explain how each branch forms. So I thought the branch already there even without decoherence.

Yes, but that just means branches form some other way. That other way is by entanglement via interactions and unitary evolution. When you have two subsystems that interact, unitary evolution entangles them. I showed how in post #4.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #14
PeterDonis said:
The problem with the thread that got closed wasn't your statement (referring to mine) about "splitting". It was your statement that "MWI assumes the brain is classical". It doesn't.

Nor is it really correct to view the different "worlds" that get split off in the MWI as classical. The MWI is an interpretation of quantum mechanics, not classical mechanics. It assumes that everything is quantum, including you and me.
No. See below.
You don't. You use math.

The double slit is a bad example to use because there are not two distinct "results" of the experiment when it is run the same way multiple times. To change the result you have to change the experimental setup (close one of the slits, put measuring devices at the slits, etc.). That's not what the MWI is talking about.

A better example is a measurement of the spin of a spin-1/2 particle about a fixed axis. Such a measurement, when run the same way multiple times, will yield one of two results each time, which we can call "up" and "down" and denote by the symbols ##+## and ##-##. For each run, the measuring device starts out in a state we can call "ready" and denote by the symbol ##R##, and ends up in either the "measured spin up" state or the "measured spin down" state, which we can denote by the symbols ##U## and ##D##. Mathematically, we write this evolution of states during the measurement as follows:

$$
\vert \Psi \rangle \vert R \rangle = \left( a \vert + \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \right) \vert R \rangle \rightarrow \vert \Psi' \rangle = a \vert + \rangle \vert U \rangle + b \vert - \rangle \vert D \rangle
$$

Here ##a## and ##b## are complex numbers that satisfy ##\vert a \vert^2 + \vert b \vert^2 = 1##.

The best ordinary language term to describe the above evolution is not "splitting" but "entanglement": the state of the measuring device gets entangled with the state of the measured system. The term "splitting" comes from focusing on the fact that the measuring device starts out in the state ##R##, but ends up in a superposition of states (more precisely, as factors in two terms of a superposition: the measuring device in the entangled state after the measurement does not have a state that is separable from the state of the measured system). But that is focusing on just a piece of the wave function instead of the whole wave function. And notice that the other piece, the state of the measured system, does not change at all; there are ##+## and ##-## terms in ##\Psi## and there are ##+## and ##-## terms in ##\Psi'##, with the same coefficients.

Above you emphasized that even without measuring device or observer that entangled with the measured system, there is still + and - or spin up and spin down in the superposition, why can't these spin up or spin down be called world/branches?

Also, the above evolution applies just as well if the "measuring device" is an observer like you or me: it just says that our state becomes entangled with the state of the measured system, so the states ##U## and ##D## are something like "I observed the spin to be up" and "I observed the spin to be down". So we ourselves, if we take the QM math at face value, end up in states that are not separable from the states of the things we observe.

The two main types of QM interpretations are identical up to this point; where they differ is in what happens next. In no collapse interpretations like the MWI, nothing happens next; the wave function ##\Psi'## just keeps on undergoing unitary evolution, just as the process that goes from ##\Psi## to ##\Psi'## is unitary evolution. In collapse interpretations like Copenhagen, the state "collapses" from ##\Psi'## to one of the two terms in it; the probability of collapsing to each term is given by the squared modulus of its coefficient (##a## or ##b##).
 
  • #15
Blue Scallop said:
Above you emphasized that even without measuring device or observer that entangled with the measured system, there is still + and - or spin up and spin down in the superposition

It's only a superposition because of the basis we picked. But without an actual measurement in that basis--i.e., without an interaction that entangles the system's state with that of a measuring device--there is no physical reason to choose that basis over any other. That basis is only picked out because of the measurement that gets made. So without a measurement being made, we can't say whether the state is a superposition or not.

Blue Scallop said:
why can't these spin up or spin down be called world/branches?

Because in the absence of a measurement, there is no entanglement of the system's state with the state of a measuring device. It's the entanglement that creates "branching", to the extent that term is applicable at all. See my post #4.
 
  • #16
PeterDonis said:
It's only a superposition because of the basis we picked. But without an actual measurement in that basis--i.e., without an interaction that entangles the system's state with that of a measuring device--there is no physical reason to choose that basis over any other. That basis is only picked out because of the measurement that gets made. So without a measurement being made, we can't say whether the state is a superposition or not.

There is no word "basis" in your post #4. How do you use the example of spin + and - in this superposition and basis connection? Or how do you insert this basis business in your post#4? You are incredible helpful, thanks a lot!

Because in the absence of a measurement, there is no entanglement of the system's state with the state of a measuring device. It's the entanglement that creates "branching", to the extent that term is applicable at all. See my post #4.
 
  • #17
Blue Scallop said:
There is no word "basis" in your post #4.

A basis is any set of mutually orthogonal vectors that span the space of all possible states of the system. In the case of spin for a spin-1/2 particle, the "up" and "down" states for any axis form a basis. So the states I called ##+## and ##-## in post #4 are a basis. But the only thing that picks out that particular basis is our choice of a particular axis about which to measure the spin; and that only has physical meaning if we actually make the measurement.
 
  • #18
PeterDonis said:
A basis is any set of mutually orthogonal vectors that span the space of all possible states of the system. In the case of spin for a spin-1/2 particle, the "up" and "down" states for any axis form a basis. So the states I called ##+## and ##-## in post #4 are a basis. But the only thing that picks out that particular basis is our choice of a particular axis about which to measure the spin; and that only has physical meaning if we actually make the measurement.

Oh, going back to your "It's only a superposition because of the basis we picked". Can you give an example of basis we picked that won't make it a superposition?
 
  • #19
Blue Scallop said:
Can you give an example of basis we picked that won't make it a superposition?

Sure, just pick the basis in which the state ##a \vert + \rangle + b \vert - \rangle##, which is the state that the system starts out in in post #4, is one of the basis states. The other basis state will then be ##b \vert + \rangle - a \vert - \rangle##. It's easy to show that these two states are orthogonal, just as the ##+## and ##-## states are orthogonal.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #20
I wrote earlier: "You said decoherence not needed to explain how each branch forms. So I thought the branch already there even without decoherence."

PeterDonis said:
Yes, but that just means branches form some other way. That other way is by entanglement via interactions and unitary evolution. When you have two subsystems that interact, unitary evolution entangles them. I showed how in post #4.

So Decoherence is not in Unitary Evolution and not having "entanglement via interactions"? Because you said branches could form some other way. But Decoherence is entanglement of environment and subsystem so why can't it is referred as "entanglement via interactions"? And Decoherence is entanglement of environment and subsystem which is not dissimilar to two subsystems so like you mentioned above.. "unitary evolution entangles" them. So decoherence also obeys unitary evolution and it is intanglement via interactions. Yet you seemed to state Decoherence is neither of the two. Please clarify your statements. I greatly appreciated all the amount of help.
 
  • #21
Blue Scallop said:
So Decoherence is not in Unitary Evolution

No.

Blue Scallop said:
and not having "entanglement via interactions"?

No.

This issue is really not a "B" level issue. You really need to spend some time working through a recent QM textbook. But even in this thread, in my post #4, which I have now referred to repeatedly, I explained how unitary evolution + entangement via interactions forms branches. There is no decoherence anywhere in that post. So decoherence is not required to form branches.

Heuristically, decoherence comes in when we ask what happens next to the state we ended up with in post #4. For example, what prevents us from simply applying the reverse interaction to the one I described in post #4? Unitary evolution is always reversible, so such an interaction must exist. And that interaction would "undo" the entanglement that formed due to measurement (just reverse the arrow I gave in post #4).

If we are dealing only with microscopic quantum systems and devices, like electrons and photons and beam splitters and so forth, we can actually do this in some cases. But in most real cases, we can't. Why not? Because the state we ended up with in post #4 interacts with the environment, which contains huge numbers of degrees of freedom that we can't keep individual track of. And because we can't keep individual track of all the environment degrees of freedom, we can't reverse the interaction any more, because it would not just be a matter of reversing the microscopic interaction I described in post #4, but of reversing all of the huge numbers of interactions (and entanglements) that take place between the system and the measuring device and the environment. And that process--the process of interactions becoming effectively irreversible due to interactions and entangments with a huge number of degrees of freedom in the environment--is decoherence.

Note, btw, that the "environment" here can actually be part of what, in ordinary language, we would consider to be the measuring device. For example, in many photon experiments we use a device called a photomultiplier to detect photons at the end of an experiment. From the standpoint of post #4 and the above, the photomultiplier is an "environment": by the time you observe an output from the photomultiplier, the photon that was detected has already interacted with and been entangled with a huge number of degrees of freedom, i.e., with an "environment" in the sense I was using the term above. The "environment" in this case is all of the atoms inside the photomultiplier, the electrons inside the circuit that amplifies the photon detection, etc. The "measuring device" in the sense of post #4, the thing whose state goes from ##R## to ##U## or ##D##, is more like the first atom inside the photomultiplier that interacts with the photon, and whose state gets entangled with it. But it is only a very small fraction of a second before that atom's interaction with the photon has cascaded into a huge number of interactions inside the photomultiplier, so that the overall interaction is irreversible and decoherence has occurred.
 
  • Like
Likes Jilang, Blue Scallop and bhobba
  • #22
PeterDonis said:
So decoherence is not required to form branches.

Decoherence is necessary, together with locality, for solving the basis selection problem, which is crucial to "branching".
 
  • #23
I asked "Can you give an example of basis we picked that won't make it a superposition?
You answered:

PeterDonis said:
Sure, just pick the basis in which the state ##a \vert + \rangle + b \vert - \rangle##, which is the state that the system starts out in in post #4, is one of the basis states. The other basis state will then be ##b \vert + \rangle - a \vert - \rangle##. It's easy to show that these two states are orthogonal, just as the ##+## and ##-## states are orthogonal.

Can you give an example of basis we picked that WILL make it a superposition? This is just to make your statements complete and make sure I understood it right. Thanks.

And oh, how come a measuring device can't entangled with both spin up and spin down at same time? so if the states
##U## = "I observed the spin to be up"
##D## = "I observed the spin to be down".

why is "I observed the spin to be up and down" forbidden?
 
  • #24
Blue Scallop said:
Can you give an example of basis we picked that WILL make it a superposition?

The basis I originally wrote the state down in, where ##+## and ##-## are the basis states.

Blue Scallop said:
how come a measuring device can't entangled with both spin up and spin down at same time?

Because of the physical nature of the device. More precisely, the name "spin measuring device" is a label we put on a device whose physical nature we have determined, by experiments, to be such that it always gives "up" or "down" as a result, never both. We have not found any physical device that gives a result "both up and down". And our current understanding of QM says that no such device should be possible.

Mathematically, the operation of a measuring device is modeled as a Hermitian operator that describes the device. Applying that operator to the initial state, before the measurement, is how you mathematically compute the state after the measurement; that's how you would derive the time evolution I gave in post #4. There is no Hermitian operator that gives a time evolution where "I observed the spin to be both up and down" is a possible result.
 
  • Like
Likes Blue Scallop
  • #25
PeterDonis said:
The basis I originally wrote the state down in, where ##+## and ##-## are the basis states.
Because of the physical nature of the device. More precisely, the name "spin measuring device" is a label we put on a device whose physical nature we have determined, by experiments, to be such that it always gives "up" or "down" as a result, never both. We have not found any physical device that gives a result "both up and down". And our current understanding of QM says that no such device should be possible.

Mathematically, the operation of a measuring device is modeled as a Hermitian operator that describes the device. Applying that operator to the initial state, before the measurement, is how you mathematically compute the state after the measurement; that's how you would derive the time evolution I gave in post #4. There is no Hermitian operator that gives a time evolution where "I observed the spin to be both up and down" is a possible result.

Thanks for the clarifications. Let's say the spin up and down is exposed to the environmental heat bath (or decoherence) so a photon is entangled to spin up, another photon is entangled to spin down.. and another one to spin up and down and so on. If we view the system, would we see spin up or spin down?
 
  • #26
Blue Scallop said:
Let's say the spin up and down is exposed to the environmental heat bath (or decoherence) so a photon is entangled to spin up, another photon is entangled to spin down.. and another one to spin up and down and so on. If we view the system, would we see spin up or spin down?

What state did the system (the original system, not the heat bath) start out in? And what measurement was made on it?

Those questions have to be answered before you even try to analyze what decoherence does.
 
  • #27
PeterDonis said:
What state did the system (the original system, not the heat bath) start out in? And what measurement was made on it?

Those questions have to be answered before you even try to analyze what decoherence does.

Lets take your example in post #4 with the particle in superposition of spin up and spin down then it is subjected to environmental heat bath or decoherence. If you try to measure it. Would you see spin up or spin down?
 
  • Like
Likes edguy99
  • #28
Blue Scallop said:
Lets take your example in post #4 with the particle in superposition of spin up and spin down then it is subjected to environmental heat bath or decoherence. If you try to measure it.

You're missing the point of what I said before. Measurement happens before decoherence. So asking what happens if you try to measure the particle after it's been subjected to decoherence doesn't make sense.
 
  • #29
PeterDonis said:
You're missing the point of what I said before. Measurement happens before decoherence. So asking what happens if you try to measure the particle after it's been subjected to decoherence doesn't make sense.

If you want to "look" at the system after decoherence, what word do you use then instead of "measurement"?

Let's say you want to look if the spin-1/2 particle is spin up or spin down after decoherence.. maybe you can see random (say spin up).. so the other spin down is in another world/branch, yes?
 
  • #30
Blue Scallop said:
If you want to "look" at the system after decoherence, what word do you use then instead of "measurement"?

I'm not sure what you mean by "looking" at the system, other than what has already been discussed. The "environment" we talked about in reference to decoherence includes the states of conscious observers that have "looked at" the results of the measurement. There is no separate "looking" process.
 
  • #31
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure what you mean by "looking" at the system, other than what has already been discussed. The "environment" we talked about in reference to decoherence includes the states of conscious observers that have "looked at" the results of the measurement. There is no separate "looking" process.

Our bicycles are decohered objects. And we can look at them. So officially what language should one use to describe looking at bicycles (or decohered spin-1/2 particles?
 
  • #32
Blue Scallop said:
Our bicycles are decohered objects.

Why?

Blue Scallop said:
And we can look at them.

What happens when we look at them? Is there any quantum uncertainty involved?
 
  • #33
PeterDonis said:
Why?

Because Bicycles are exposed to the environment like sun rays, CMBR, thermal photons, etc.

What happens when we look at them? Is there any quantum uncertainty involved?

I'm just asking what language to use to refer to observe decohered objects like bicycles or spin-1/2 particles. If "measurements" are reserved for that occur before decoherence. What language to use just to observe the one after decoherence. And if "observation" is more appropriate term. Let's say you want to observe if the spin-1/2 particle is spin up or spin down after decoherence.. maybe you can observe random (say spin up).. so the other spin down is in another world/branch, yes? If your answer if we can't observed decohered objects.. but we can observe bicycles.. don't we.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes edguy99
  • #34
Blue Scallop said:
Because Bicycles are exposed to the environment like sun rays, CMBR, thermal photons, etc.

You're missing the point. What quantum measurement do bicycles undergo after which they then become decohered? What is the analogue, in the case of the bicycle, to the spin measurement, which results in either up or down, in the case we were discussing?

Blue Scallop said:
I'm just asking what language to use to refer to observe decohered objects like bicycles or spin-1/2 particles.

And I'm trying to get at what physical process you are talking about when you say "observe decohered objects".
 
  • #35
PeterDonis said:
You're missing the point. What quantum measurement do bicycles undergo after which they then become decohered? What is the analogue, in the case of the bicycle, to the spin measurement, which results in either up or down, in the case we were discussing?
And I'm trying to get at what physical process you are talking about when you say "observe decohered objects".

We observe decohered bicycles by photons reflecting of it. I was just inquiring whether we would observe spin up or spin down in the decohered spin-1/2 particle. I put this question yesterday because I was wondering if during superposition of the spin-1/2 particle. Does the spin up and spin down really can separately entangled to different photons in the environment.. it's as if there are really different copies of the spin 1/2 particle being up or down. And if is. Then after decoherence. When we observe the particle as spin up.. does it mean it has separate spin down in another branch or world. If my language are rough. Please correct the language I should use as I don't understand why you can't get what I mean by simply observing the bicycles or spin-1/2 particle after decoherence. Former physical process is photon reflecting it. The latter physical process is instrument to detect spin up or spin down.
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
966
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
4
Replies
105
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
1K
Back
Top