- #1
heusdens
- 1,738
- 0
AN OUTLINE OF PHILOSOPHY
BY TED TRIPP
Chapter 8
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
EMPIRICISM, which commenced with postulates of confidence, after Hume seemed to end in barren scepticism which not only affronted common sense but made science impossible. The German philosopher Kant became very conscious of the fact that Hume had precipitated a crisis in philosophy. Against empirical thinking as he was, Kant, nevertheless, declared himself profoundly influenced by Hume, whom, he said; "First awoke me from my dogmatic slumbers."
Hume had argued that there could be no empirical base for the supposition of an objective existence of permanent "substances or of casuality". Our knowledge, we do possesses such knowledge is impossible if it merely comes from sensation. What if we have knowledge independent of sense experience: knowledge whose truth is certain even before experience - a priori knowledge? The truth that every event has a cause would be irrefutable and scientific analysis made possible.
A Priori Knowledge
A priori knowledge was for Kant the search for knowledge that is universal and necessary and independent of experience. "My question is", he wrote, "what we can hope to achieve with reason, when all the material and assistance of experience are taken away." (Preface to Critique of Pure Reason) and in this work itself:
"Experience is by no means the only field to which our understanding can be confined. Experience tells us what is, but not that is must be necessarily what it is and not otherwise. It therefore never gives us any really general truths; and our reason, which is particularly anxious for this class of knowledge, is roused by it rather than satisfied. General truths, which at the same time bear the character of an inward necessity, must be independent of experience - clear and certain in themselves."
Kant believed that the discovery of such knowledge was to be found in mathematics and nature (physics), such discovery being made possible through the structure of the mind. This, then, is the basic problem which the Critique sets out to solve.
The types of a priori knowledge, Kant claimed, fell into two groups; analytic and synthetic. The analytic consists of propositions or judgements where the truth can be determined without any reference to experience; solely on the basis of the terms employed. For example, "A red rose is red", and "all bodies are extended". These are universally true because what is predicated of the subject is already contained in the definition of the subject.
For synthetic a priori knowledge the predicate of the judgement must contain some information not contained in the subject. The judgement must be the result of a synthesis of these two separate notions, one being the subject about which the other, the predicate, asserts. Propositions which assert facts are synthetic when they describe an immediate experience such as, "This is black". But, having regard to Hume, Kant was careful to disregard factual statements which ventured beyond immediate experience. For example, "This piece of paper is white"... This is synthetic in that the predicate contains a concept not included in the subject. However, this is not a priori judgement, it is not universal nor independent from experience. It could be false that this paper is white and even if true, it does not have to be true at all times and places. Similarly a factual synthetic statement can be upset through the discovery of a new fact, like the statement: "All crows are black". It is possible to deny this proposition if we can produce a white crow. We cannot say that a white crow is unthinkable or a contradiction. We may say that it is unlikely: we cannot say that it is impossible. Truth or falsehood thus depends on correspondence with facts. A synthetic a priori judgement must contain some information not purely of a logical nature, nor dependent on empirical information for its truth since, according to Hume - that would always render it less than completely certain, universal or necessary.
Kant maintained that in mathematics and physics such universal judgement independent of experience were to be found. Such was the elementary proposition 7 + 5 = 12. This, he insisted, was a truth that was not merely true because of the definition of the terms involved, but because it contained more information in the predicate than was included in the bare concept '7' and '5'. In combining these two concepts into another which is their sum, a kind of intuition must take place, which introduces something new in the conclusion.
"That 5 should be added to 7 was no doubt implied in my concept of a sum 7 + 5, but not that the sum should be equal to 12. An arithmetical proposition is, therefore, always synthetical, which is seen more easily still by taking larger numbers, where we clearly perceive that, turn and twist our conceptions as we may, we could never by means of the mere analysis of our concepts and without the help of intuition arrive at the sum wanted."
Similarly, in geometrical truths, Kant claimed that one finds the same sort of synthetic element: for example, in the proposition, "A straight line is the shortest distance between two points. Here the concept "Straight line" does not include the notion of it being the shortest distance between two points and yet the statement is a necessary and universal truth. And in physics he contended, it is also the case that there are propositions like, "Every event has a cause," which are synthetic and also a priori.
Intuition
The general problem confronting Kant was the question: "How are synthetic a priori judgements possible? His first answer is the claim that with every order or form of experience it takes the form of an a priori characteristic, which arises from the mind and not the outside world. Thus to Kant, the mind was not as it appeared to Locke and Hume, just "passive was", but active in organising, moulding and classifying perceptions it receives in the ordering of thought. The agent for selection of this ordering and classification of the material presented to it Kant claims to be the sense of space and the sense of time. The mind, in allocating its sensations in space and time attributes them to this object here or that object there. To this present time or to that past time. Space and time are not things perceived but or modes of perception - our tools for putting sense into sensation. Space and time are organs of perception. A priori, because all ordered experience involves and presupposes them. Without them sensations could never grow into perceptions. A priori, because it is inconceivable that we should ever have any future experience that will not involve them.
Categories
Besides the forms of intuition Kant believed that there must be principles or concepts for organising the general content of any possible experience in order to recognise it as a coherent proposition. Hume has shown that there were no necessary features in experience which could supply these factors, consequently says Kant, since we are capable of attaining organised and intelligible information about the world, we must have within ourselves the organising principles. Our minds structure and interpret the observations of our senses. Further, there must be a general conceptual scheme by which the types of items that we are acquainted with are ordered and related. These are what Kant calls the categories which he lists into four groups of three, involving such notions as causality, substance, accident, possibility etc. With the categories Kant claimed he had selected those basic ideas that are indispensable to thought and common to all mankind. When we think of the bewildering large number of words we use it seems almost impossible to select just those basic ideas that are indispensable to thought. Kant's solution is ingenious but out of fashion today. Modern physics dispenses with some of the categories. It can manage without causation and instead of space and time, Relativity employs intervals. The categories may be necessities at a certain level of thinking; but all of them are not essential in the most advanced field of science.
To summarise; We note sensation as being unorganised stimulus; perception as sensation organised; conception as organised perception, each a greater degree of order, sequence and unity. "Perceptions without conceptions", says Kant, "are blind!" If perceptions (sensations) wove themselves automatically into ordered thought, if mind were not an active effort hammering out order from chaos, how could the same sense experience leave one man mediocre, and another clever? Thus Kant claimed that he had made objects conform to the mind, whereas previous philosophers had made mind conform to objects.
[to be continued]
BY TED TRIPP
Chapter 8
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
EMPIRICISM, which commenced with postulates of confidence, after Hume seemed to end in barren scepticism which not only affronted common sense but made science impossible. The German philosopher Kant became very conscious of the fact that Hume had precipitated a crisis in philosophy. Against empirical thinking as he was, Kant, nevertheless, declared himself profoundly influenced by Hume, whom, he said; "First awoke me from my dogmatic slumbers."
Hume had argued that there could be no empirical base for the supposition of an objective existence of permanent "substances or of casuality". Our knowledge, we do possesses such knowledge is impossible if it merely comes from sensation. What if we have knowledge independent of sense experience: knowledge whose truth is certain even before experience - a priori knowledge? The truth that every event has a cause would be irrefutable and scientific analysis made possible.
A Priori Knowledge
A priori knowledge was for Kant the search for knowledge that is universal and necessary and independent of experience. "My question is", he wrote, "what we can hope to achieve with reason, when all the material and assistance of experience are taken away." (Preface to Critique of Pure Reason) and in this work itself:
"Experience is by no means the only field to which our understanding can be confined. Experience tells us what is, but not that is must be necessarily what it is and not otherwise. It therefore never gives us any really general truths; and our reason, which is particularly anxious for this class of knowledge, is roused by it rather than satisfied. General truths, which at the same time bear the character of an inward necessity, must be independent of experience - clear and certain in themselves."
Kant believed that the discovery of such knowledge was to be found in mathematics and nature (physics), such discovery being made possible through the structure of the mind. This, then, is the basic problem which the Critique sets out to solve.
The types of a priori knowledge, Kant claimed, fell into two groups; analytic and synthetic. The analytic consists of propositions or judgements where the truth can be determined without any reference to experience; solely on the basis of the terms employed. For example, "A red rose is red", and "all bodies are extended". These are universally true because what is predicated of the subject is already contained in the definition of the subject.
For synthetic a priori knowledge the predicate of the judgement must contain some information not contained in the subject. The judgement must be the result of a synthesis of these two separate notions, one being the subject about which the other, the predicate, asserts. Propositions which assert facts are synthetic when they describe an immediate experience such as, "This is black". But, having regard to Hume, Kant was careful to disregard factual statements which ventured beyond immediate experience. For example, "This piece of paper is white"... This is synthetic in that the predicate contains a concept not included in the subject. However, this is not a priori judgement, it is not universal nor independent from experience. It could be false that this paper is white and even if true, it does not have to be true at all times and places. Similarly a factual synthetic statement can be upset through the discovery of a new fact, like the statement: "All crows are black". It is possible to deny this proposition if we can produce a white crow. We cannot say that a white crow is unthinkable or a contradiction. We may say that it is unlikely: we cannot say that it is impossible. Truth or falsehood thus depends on correspondence with facts. A synthetic a priori judgement must contain some information not purely of a logical nature, nor dependent on empirical information for its truth since, according to Hume - that would always render it less than completely certain, universal or necessary.
Kant maintained that in mathematics and physics such universal judgement independent of experience were to be found. Such was the elementary proposition 7 + 5 = 12. This, he insisted, was a truth that was not merely true because of the definition of the terms involved, but because it contained more information in the predicate than was included in the bare concept '7' and '5'. In combining these two concepts into another which is their sum, a kind of intuition must take place, which introduces something new in the conclusion.
"That 5 should be added to 7 was no doubt implied in my concept of a sum 7 + 5, but not that the sum should be equal to 12. An arithmetical proposition is, therefore, always synthetical, which is seen more easily still by taking larger numbers, where we clearly perceive that, turn and twist our conceptions as we may, we could never by means of the mere analysis of our concepts and without the help of intuition arrive at the sum wanted."
Similarly, in geometrical truths, Kant claimed that one finds the same sort of synthetic element: for example, in the proposition, "A straight line is the shortest distance between two points. Here the concept "Straight line" does not include the notion of it being the shortest distance between two points and yet the statement is a necessary and universal truth. And in physics he contended, it is also the case that there are propositions like, "Every event has a cause," which are synthetic and also a priori.
Intuition
The general problem confronting Kant was the question: "How are synthetic a priori judgements possible? His first answer is the claim that with every order or form of experience it takes the form of an a priori characteristic, which arises from the mind and not the outside world. Thus to Kant, the mind was not as it appeared to Locke and Hume, just "passive was", but active in organising, moulding and classifying perceptions it receives in the ordering of thought. The agent for selection of this ordering and classification of the material presented to it Kant claims to be the sense of space and the sense of time. The mind, in allocating its sensations in space and time attributes them to this object here or that object there. To this present time or to that past time. Space and time are not things perceived but or modes of perception - our tools for putting sense into sensation. Space and time are organs of perception. A priori, because all ordered experience involves and presupposes them. Without them sensations could never grow into perceptions. A priori, because it is inconceivable that we should ever have any future experience that will not involve them.
Categories
Besides the forms of intuition Kant believed that there must be principles or concepts for organising the general content of any possible experience in order to recognise it as a coherent proposition. Hume has shown that there were no necessary features in experience which could supply these factors, consequently says Kant, since we are capable of attaining organised and intelligible information about the world, we must have within ourselves the organising principles. Our minds structure and interpret the observations of our senses. Further, there must be a general conceptual scheme by which the types of items that we are acquainted with are ordered and related. These are what Kant calls the categories which he lists into four groups of three, involving such notions as causality, substance, accident, possibility etc. With the categories Kant claimed he had selected those basic ideas that are indispensable to thought and common to all mankind. When we think of the bewildering large number of words we use it seems almost impossible to select just those basic ideas that are indispensable to thought. Kant's solution is ingenious but out of fashion today. Modern physics dispenses with some of the categories. It can manage without causation and instead of space and time, Relativity employs intervals. The categories may be necessities at a certain level of thinking; but all of them are not essential in the most advanced field of science.
To summarise; We note sensation as being unorganised stimulus; perception as sensation organised; conception as organised perception, each a greater degree of order, sequence and unity. "Perceptions without conceptions", says Kant, "are blind!" If perceptions (sensations) wove themselves automatically into ordered thought, if mind were not an active effort hammering out order from chaos, how could the same sense experience leave one man mediocre, and another clever? Thus Kant claimed that he had made objects conform to the mind, whereas previous philosophers had made mind conform to objects.
[to be continued]