Measurement results and two conflicting interpretations

In summary: It explains the experimentally observed probabilities and is thus one of the assumptions of the theory.In summary, the conversation discusses two different interpretations for the interpretation of measurement results. The thermal interpretation is based on the assumption that the measurement device is constructed to measure expectation values, and therefore the measurement results are a tautology. The Born's statistical interpretation, on the other hand, claims that the measurement results reveal eigenvalues in an unpredictable fashion with probabilities, and is consistent with the standard interpretation of quantum mechanics. The discussion also touches on the issue of interpretational problems in quantum mechanics, which is a social phenomenon that is still being debated.
  • #36
A. Neumaier said:
That's irrelevant.

The thermal interpretation never claims the caricature you take it to claim, namely that one always gets the q-expectation. It only claims that the measurement result one gets approximates the predicted q-expectation ##\langle A\rangle## with an error of the order of the predicted uncertainty ##\sigma_A##. When the latter is large, as in the case of a spin measurement, this is true even when the q-expectation vanishes and the measured values are ##\pm 1/2##!
That's simply not true! The precision of the measurement device is determined by the measurement device, not the standard deviation due to the preparation (i.e., the prepared state) of the measured system.

If you want to establish that the standard deviation of ##A## is ##\sigma_A## you have to measure with much higher precision than ##\sigma_A##, and you have to use a sufficiently large ensemble to gain "enough statistics" to establish that the standard deviation due to the state preparation is ##\sigma_A##.

Again for the SGE: If your resolution of the spin-##z##-component measurement resolves the measured values ##\pm 1/2## and the state is prepared such that ##\langle s_z \rangle=0##, you never find the result ##\langle s_z \rangle=0## with some uncertainty but you find with certainty either ##+1/2## or ##-1/2##, and to establish that the standard deviation is ##\sigma_{\sigma_z}## you have to simply do the measurement often enough on equally prepared spins to gain enough statistics to verify this prediction (at the given confidence level, which usually is ##5 \sigma_{\text{measurement}}## (where here ##\sigma_{\text{measurement}}## is the standard deviation of the measurement, not that of the quantum state!).
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
vanhees71 said:
Ok, fine with me, I know that you don't accept the minimal statistical interpretation, but I think it is important to clearly see that the claim that what's measured on a quantum system is always the q-expectation value is utterly wrong.

I do accept the minimal statistical interpretation :) the same as Dirac, L&L, Messiah, Cohen-Tannoudji etc, but maybe we should discuss this elsewhere.

Yes, the thermal interpretation completely baffles me (including the part about the measured result being a q-expectation), but maybe I'm missing something because I haven't spent a lot of time studying it.
 
  • #38
vanhees71 said:
But this is what you said! The "beable" is the q-expectation value and not the usual definition of an observable. If this is now all of a sudden not true anymore, we are back to the very beginning, since now your thermal interpretation is again undefined! :-(
No; this was never true. You were misreading the concept of a beable. Maybe this is the source of our continuing misunderstandings.

According to Bell, a beable of a system is a property of the system that exists and is predictable independently of whether one measures anything. A measurement is the reading of a measurement value from a measurement device interacting with the system that is guaranteed to approximate the value of a beable of that system within the claimed accuracy of the measurement device.

In classical mechanics, the exact positions and momenta of all particles in the Laplacian universe are the beables. and a measurement device for a particular prepared particle is a macroscopic body coupled to this particle, with a pointer such that the pointer reading approximates some position coordinate in a suitable coordinate system. Clearly, any given measurement never yields the exact position but only an approximation of it.

In a Stern-Gerlach experiment with a single particle, the beables are the three real-valued components of the q-expectation ##\bar S## of the spin vector ##S##, and the location of the spot produced on the screen is the pointer. Because of the semiclassical analysis of the experimental arrangement, the initial beam carrying the particle splits in the magnetic field into two beams, hence only two spots carry enough intensity to produce a response. Thus the pointer can measure only a single bit of ##\bar S##. This is very little information, whence the error is predictably large.

The thermal interpretation predicts everything: the spin vector, the two beams, the two spots, and the (very low) accuracy with which these spots measure the beable ##S_3##.
 
  • #39
atyy said:
I do accept the minimal statistical interpretation :) the same as Dirac, L&L, Messiah, Cohen-Tannoudji etc, but maybe we should discuss this elsewhere.

Yes, the thermal interpretation completely baffles me (including the part about the measured result being a q-expectation), but maybe I'm missing something because I haven't spent a lot of time studying it.
Well, the problem is that the "thermal interpretation" is either wrong for very obvious reasons or not clearly defined yet since now again we learned that the measured result is not the q-expectation value although we discuss precisely this earlier statement for weeks in several different forks of the initial thread. I'm also baffled, but for obviously different reasons.
 
  • #40
vanhees71 said:
you never find the result ##\langle s_z \rangle=0## with some uncertainty but you find with certainty either ##+1/2## or ##-1/2##
If I find the result ##+1/2## or ##-1/2## with certainty, I can be sure that the measurement error according to the thermal interpretation is exactly ##1/2##, since this is the absolute value of the difference between the measured value and the true value (defined in the thermal interpretation to be the q-expectation ##0##). As a consequence, I can be sure that the standard deviation of the measurement results is also exactly ##1/2##.
 
Last edited:
  • #41
A. Neumaier said:
No; this was never true. You were misreading the concept of a beable. Maybe this is the source of our continuing misunderstandings.

According to Bell, a beable of a system is a property of the system that exists and is predictable independently of whether one measures anything. A measurement is the reading of a measurement value from a measurement device interacting with the system that is guaranteed to approximate the value of a beable of that system within the claimed accuracy of the measurement device.

In classical mechanics, the exact positions and momenta of all particles in the Laplacian universe are the beables. and a measurement device for a particular prepared particle is a macroscopic body coupled to this particle, with a pointer such that the pointer reading approximates some position coordinate in a suitable coordinate system. Clearly, any given measurement never yields the exact position but only an approximation of it.

In a Stern-Gerlach experiment with a single particle, the beables are the three real-valued components of the q-expectation ##\bar S## of the spin vector ##S##, and the location of the spot produced on the screen is the pointer. Because of the semiclassical analysis of the experimental arrangement, the initial beam carrying the particle splits in the magnetic field into two beams, hence only two spots carry enough intensity to produce a response. Thus the pointer can measure only a single bit of ##\bar S##. This is very little information, whence the error is predictably large.

The thermal interpretation predicts everything: the spin vector, the two beams, the two spots, and the (very low) accuracy with which these spots measure the beable ##S_3##.
It's always dangerous to use philosophically unsharp definitions. If this is what Bell refers to as "beable" it's not subject of physics, because physics is about what's observed objectively in nature. Kant's "Ding an sich" is a fiction and not subject of physics!

In your 3rd paragraph you already redefine the word "beable" as to have the usual meaning of "observable". Why then not using the clearly defined word "observable".

All this contributes to the confusion rather than the clarification what your "thermal interpretation" really is meant to mean! If you are not able to express it in standard physics terms and always refer to unsharp notions of philosophy it's of course hard to ever come to a conclusion about it.
 
  • #42
vanhees71 said:
In your 3rd paragraph you already redefine the word "beable" as to have the usual meaning of "observable".
I don't understand. Where precisely do I do it?
vanhees71 said:
Why then not using the clearly defined word "observable".
I cannot, because the word observable is loaded in quantum mechanics with the traditional interpretation.
vanhees71 said:
If you are not able to express it in standard physics terms and always refer to unsharp notions of philosophy
The word 'observable' is also an unsharp and philosophical notion, with very different meanings in classical and quantum mechanics.
 
  • #43
vanhees71 said:
Kant's "Ding an sich" is a fiction and not subject of physics!
It is only as fictional as your idealized measurements from
vanhees71 said:
It's of course true that any measurement device has some imprecision, but you can in principle measure as precisely as you want, and theoretical physics deals with idealized measurements. The possible outcomes of measurements are the eigenvalues of the operator of the measured observable.
 
  • #44
I've read through your paper and it's not clear to me exactly what predictions you can make about experimental results. In particular, the thermal interpretation appears to hinge on the distinction of what you define as point causality, joint causality and extended causality.

Start with an example. Consider two antennas which the emission of radiation is spacelike and a point in the future in which I am going to measure the radiation arriving at my antenna. Do the amplitudes sum coherently or incoherently? Quantum mechanically, since phases are not measurable quantities, the difference is whether or not you can determine which wave corresponds to which source. The epr experiment is simply the same experiment except by exchanging past and future. The correlations at spacelike points only occur if the two photons have a common causal origin and behave like a single entity.

The Born rule is buried in the notion of extended causality. Since phases are not measurable quantities, you cannot specify a configuration of entities on a spacelike surface which meet the conditions required to be extendedly causal, since such a configuration would require specifying the phases of those entities. An intereference pattern that is actually deterministic would then require each point in the interference pattern (including the nulls) to be the coherent sum of of different extendedly causal configurations differing by phases. Instead of the Born rule being used to give a probability directly from the amplitudes associated with a past configuration in which all physical quantities are measurable, the Born rule in this case, gives a probability of which past configuration is being measured where each past configurtion differs by a quantity which is not measurable.

Since it's the unmeasurability of phases that gives rise to QFT, I'm not sure where that leaves the thermal interpreation in that regard. Phases are well defined classically, so I cannot see anyway around having to deal with an quantum mechanically unmeasurable quantity to obtain classical determinism unless you can define an experiment that makes that quantity measurable, in which case, you have actually surpassed quantum mechanics by making it truly classical.

The only out here for extended causality is the extended causality that results from a point causalty in the past of the extendedly causal entities, which leaves you back at standard quantum mechanics.
 
  • #45
bobob said:
the thermal interpretation appears to hinge on the distinction of what you define as point causality, joint causality and extended causality.
Only with regard to explaining long-distance correlation experiments. In terms of prediction, it is identical to standard quantum mechanics, as it only imposes a different interpretation of it, rather than modifying it (as Bohmian mechanics or GWR).
 
  • #46
bobob said:
Consider two antennas which the emission of radiation is spacelike

How can emission of radiation be spacelike?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #47
PeterDonis said:
How can emission of radiation be spacelike?

Phased array radar. Emission of photons from sources which are spacelike seperated. I could have worded that better as emission from sources which are spacelike seperated.
 
Last edited:
  • #48
A. Neumaier said:
Only with regard to explaining long-distance correlation experiments. In terms of prediction, it is identical to standard quantum mechanics, as it only imposes a different interpretation of it, rather than modifying it (as Bohmian mechanics or GWR).
Right, but that is point here. Those notions of causality are ultimately just pointlike causality. There is no difference since the extended causality requires a common origin in a past point causality. The difference would only be meaningful if you could specify an extended causality completely and independently from one with a common origin.
 
  • #49
bobob said:
Emission of photons from sources which are spacelike seperated

Ah, ok, that makes sense.
 
  • #50
bobob said:
Those notions of causality are ultimately just pointlike causality. There is no difference since the extended causality requires a common origin in a past point causality. The difference would only be meaningful if you could specify an extended causality completely and independently from one with a common origin.
For independent point sources, point causality and etended causality are the same. For extended nonclassical sources not, because of the entanglement of their constituents.
 
  • #51
Sir Roger Penrose posits a new physics in the area between classical and quantum. The penrose diosi theorum suggests observer independent gravitationally induced collapse of the wave function. Might this have some experimental validity?
 
  • #52
A. Neumaier said:
No; this was never true. You were misreading the concept of a beable. Maybe this is the source of our continuing misunderstandings.

According to Bell, a beable of a system is a property of the system that exists and is predictable independently of whether one measures anything. A measurement is the reading of a measurement value from a measurement device interacting with the system that is guaranteed to approximate the value of a beable of that system within the claimed accuracy of the measurement device.

In classical mechanics, the exact positions and momenta of all particles in the Laplacian universe are the beables. and a measurement device for a particular prepared particle is a macroscopic body coupled to this particle, with a pointer such that the pointer reading approximates some position coordinate in a suitable coordinate system. Clearly, any given measurement never yields the exact position but only an approximation of it.

In a Stern-Gerlach experiment with a single particle, the beables are the three real-valued components of the q-expectation ##\bar S## of the spin vector ##S##, and the location of the spot produced on the screen is the pointer. Because of the semiclassical analysis of the experimental arrangement, the initial beam carrying the particle splits in the magnetic field into two beams, hence only two spots carry enough intensity to produce a response. Thus the pointer can measure only a single bit of ##\bar S##. This is very little information, whence the error is predictably large.

The thermal interpretation predicts everything: the spin vector, the two beams, the two spots, and the (very low) accuracy with which these spots measure the beable ##S_3##.
Then "beable" is an empty phrase, because we cannot know about any property of a system without measuring (or observing) it. Physics deals with what's observable and measuarable and not philosophical fictitions that cannot be observed and measured.

In classical mechanics as well as in quantum mechanics the positions and momenta of all particles are observables that can (in principle) always be measured as precisely as you wish. There's no difference between classical and quantum mechanics here (of course with the caveat that there are no point particles existing and thus to measure the "position" must sometimes be specified more precisely, but let's keep it at the simple level).

Spin is in some sense special, because it's an observable without a classical analogon. Within non-relativistic quantum theory spin is an observable axial-vector quantity with the properties of an angular momentum. The three components are thus observables (within non-relativistic QT). I don't see, why you emphasize the semiclassical description (i.e., keeping the description of the external magnetic field classical) so much. That's unimportant for the very general issue we are discussing here. I've never thought about a quantum-field theoretical description of the SGE. It's perhaps even an interesting formal question, but it's totally irrelevant for the issues we are discussing here.

Now, in the SGE what's measured is one of the spin components (or to be very precise the component of the magnetic moment related to this spin component) wrt. the direction determined by the magnetic field. The pointer variable is the position of the particle, the inhomogeneous magnetic field designed such that it leads to a (nearly) 100% entanglement between position and this spin component. In this way it's even a preparation procedure for this spin component (or in other words the polarization state of the particle). The error is practically negligible, if the experiment is well designed.

I think, already the interpretation of the SGE in terms of the thermal interpretation is orthogonal to what's really achieved in the lab already in 1922 by Stern and Gerlach, while the minimal standard interpretation precisely describes these findings very well.
 
  • #53
A. Neumaier said:
If I find the result ##+1/2## or ##-1/2## with certainty, I can be sure that the measurement error according to the thermal interpretation is exactly ##1/2##, since this is the absolute value of the difference between the measured value and the true value (defined in the thermal interpretation to be the q-expectation ##0##). As a consequence, I can be sure that the standard deviation of the measurement results is also exactly ##1/2##.
This contradicts the empirical outcome of the SGE. Even in the lab at university with its rather limited budget you can get very well separated beams of Ag atoms!
 
  • #54
vanhees71 said:
Even in the lab at university with its rather limited budget you can get very well separated beams of Ag atoms!
Yes, but the spots are supposed to measure a very tiny spin of the order of ##\hbar##. On a scale where the positions of the two silver spots represent the numbers ##\pm \hbar/2##, these positions are approximations of any number of the order of ##\hbar## with an error of the order ##\hbar##, in particular, one of the q-expectation of the spin, as the thermal interpretations claims.
vanhees71 said:
This contradicts the empirical outcome of the SGE.
There cannot be a contradiction in cases where no significant relative accuracy is claimed!
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
727
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
9
Replies
309
Views
8K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
24
Replies
826
Views
70K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
94
Views
11K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
47
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
76
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
21
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
2K
Back
Top