Are indirect proofs always necessary in mathematics?

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of indirect proofs in mathematics and whether a direct proof exists in all cases where an indirect proof exists. Participants also mention the use of intuitionistic logic and Gödel's incompleteness theorem in relation to this topic. They also bring up the idea of elegant programs and how they relate to Gödel's theorem. The question of what makes a proof indirect is also briefly discussed.
  • #1
ila
4
0
Hi, I don't know if this has been discussed (or is trivial or even silly). I was wondering sometimes there is reliance on indirect proofs in mathematics. I was wondering can it be proven in any case where an indirect proof exists that a direct proof does not?
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I don't think your question is either trivial, or silly. I'm afraid that I don't know the answer, if there is one, hopefully, someone like Hurkyl or HallsofIvy might provide one.
 
  • #3
I agree it is a very interesting question but depends on what we mean by "direct" proof. What makes a proof direct or indirect?

Certainly in mathematics one can prove the existence of certain objects and constructions without actually constructing them. In certain proofs, a heavy reliance on the axiom of choice can certainly lead to a an existence proof without any hope of actually constructing the example "hands on". (for example see the Banch Tarski paradox http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Banach%E2%80%93Tarski_paradox" )
I'm not sure if an example like this would be classified as an indirect proof though.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #4
I concur with Tzar's comment -- the question itself is somewhat vague. But I will try to give an answer that I think is in the spirit of the question!


Intuitionistic logic does not use all of the rules of inference you use in Boolean algebra. A couple particular things is that (P or (not P)) isn't a tautology, and P is not equivalent to not (not P).

In intuitionistic logic, you can still use the law of noncontradiction to prove a negative. In other words, if you devise a proof
P ==> Q and (not Q)​
then you can validly infer (not P). But if you were to try and prove a positive by deriving
(not P) ==> Q and (not Q)​
then you can only infer (not (not P)). In intuitionistic logic, this does not allow us to infer P!

A specific example of an interesting theorem that cannot be proven in intuitionistic set theory is this:
There exists a discontinuous function​
(where 'function' means a real-valued function whose domain is the reals)

In fact, there are models of intuitionistic set theory in which every such function is actually continuous.
 
  • #5
Hmm, that's an interesting idea. You mean something like inductive versus deductive?

It's reminiscent of http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gödel's_incompleteness_theorem#First_incompleteness_theorem":
Gödel said:
Any effectively generated theory capable of expressing elementary arithmetic cannot be both consistent and complete. In particular, for any consistent, effectively generated formal theory that proves certain basic arithmetic truths, there is an arithmetical statement that is true, but not provable in the theory.
(emphasis mine)
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #6
I've always struggled to understand that statement made by Godel. It makes sense (to me) that you can always ask a question which can not be proved nor disproved by your axioms. However, how can you claim a statement is true, if it is not provable in your theory?
 
  • #7
Oh, I should have mentioned, I have no clue about what it actually means either, nor have I even tried to follow Gödel's proof. I didn't mean to be name-droppy, I was just pointing out the resemblance to ila's idea.

I see what you're saying, Tzar, and I've had the same thoughts; it seems to violate the basic concept of mathematical systems as being foundations upon Euclidean-geometry-like axioms. Maybe it has to do with the definition of "consistent, effectively generated formal theory", or perhaps the proof of the incompleteness theorem itself serves as the proof of the statements in question.
 
  • #8
Godel's result states that in any axiomatic system there will always be questions which cannot be answered (problems that cannot be resolved) within that system
 
  • #9
Hmmm, I noticed that in Wikipedia there's a footnote qualifying the quotation I posted above:
Wikipedia said:
The word "true" is used disquotationally here; the Gödel sentence GT states that no natural number with a certain property exists, and to say GT is true simply means that, in fact, no number with that property exists (see Franzén 2005 pp. 28–33). It is also possible to read "GT is true" in the formal sense that it is a theorem of primitive recursive arithmetic that Con(T)→GT, where Con(T) is a canonical sentence asserting the consistency of T (Smoryński 1977 p. 840, Kikuchi and Tanaka 1994 p. 403)
 
  • #10
Tzar said:
I've always struggled to understand that statement made by Godel. It makes sense (to me) that you can always ask a question which can not be proved nor disproved by your axioms. However, how can you claim a statement is true, if it is not provable in your theory?

It's misleading to say "there is a statement which is true, but not provable from within the theory". Truthiness is relative to the set of axioms you're working with. A system with more axioms might in fact be able to prove it, but no necessarily so!

It's more appropriate to say those statements can be neither be proven nor disproven in your formal system. They are not true. They are not false. They don't even show up to the party!
 
  • #11
http://www.umcs.maine.edu/~chaitin/eesti.html"

We all know what computer programs are. We define an elegant program to be a program such that no smaller program gives exactly the same output.


http://www.umcs.maine.edu/~chaitin/eesti.html#18"

So, you encounter Gödel every day if you ask why downloading a certain program takes such a long time and if it was really not possible to have a significantly shorter program that would do the same job. Because if it is not possible, then the proof of that fact doesn't exist.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #12
An indirect proof, as I understand it, is a proof that relies on reductio ad absurdum. That is, a non-constructive proof.

If a fact can be proved, we may always find an indirect proof of it. The proof of this is trivial:

1. Premise: S can be proved. Call its proof P(S).
2. Begin a proof of S by contradiction: Assume ~S.
3. But P(S) is a proof of S; therefore, S.
4. This gives (S and ~S), a contradiction.
5. Therefore the assumption in (2) is false.
6. Therefore S.

So, given that S has a proof, we can construct a (rather trivial) indirect proof of S.

However, given that S has a proof, we cannot necessarily find a direct proof of S. As someone else mentioned, there are many theorems in math on the existence of objects that cannot be directly constructed.

Therefore, when first attempting to prove some fact, you will probably have the most success by attempting a proof by contradiction. However, the proof you find might not be very satisfactory; i.e., it might not give you much intuition as to why the result is so.
 
  • #13
Suppose we can prove that a proof exists without exhibiting it. Then can we prove THAT without exhibiting it? This would be something akin to "meta" or "2nd order" math/logic. It may have to do with the fact that we'd need to quantify over all proofs.
 
  • #14
First, people dis category theory... then people get Gödel wrong... :cry::cry::cry:


First off, the notion of axioms, provability, logical deduction -- these do not deal with 'truth'. Truth only comes into play when you decide to use a 'truth valuation' -- a function that assigns to each logical statement a 'truth value'. This happens most often when you consider a specific 'structure', and you 'interpret' logical statements as saying something about your structure, calling a statement 'true' iff it's a correct statement about your structure.


(Assuming number theory is consistent) A 'model' of number theory is a structure for which each of the axioms of number theory are correct. In this model, every statement of number theory is either true or false. Any statement that can be proven will be true, and any statement that can be disproven will be false. Those that can be neither proven nor disproven could go either way.


Logical theories can be 'complete' -- be such that all logical statements are either provable or disprovable. It's easy to construct trivial examples. For example, consider any model of number theory; we can take the set of all correct statements about this model and use them as the axioms for a logical theory. Gödel's incompleteness theorem says that if we use this trick, there doesn't exist any algorithmic method for identifying whether a statement is or isn't an axiom.

There are nontrivial examples of complete theories. (First-order) Euclidean geometry is a wonderful example (see Tarski's axioms for Euclidean geometry). Equivalently, the theory of real number arithmetic is also complete (see the axioms for a real closed field). Gödel's theorem, in this case, tells us that these theories are incapable of talking about number theory.

More explicitly -- you cannot use the arithmetic real numbers to ask question
Given a real numebr x, is it an integer?​



The basic idea of Gödel's proof is actally somewhat straightforward, and comes in several guises. The one I can state off the top of my head goes as follows:

* Describe how to do text processing with integer arithmetic
* Show how to use text processing to simulate the operation of a computer
* Write down the condition Halt(p) that expresses whether the program p ever finishes
* Write a program that is capable of computing Halt(p) whenever Halt(p) is provable or disprovable
* Invoke the fact, in general, the halting problem is not computable
 
  • #15
ila said:
Hi, I don't know if this has been discussed (or is trivial or even silly). I was wondering sometimes there is reliance on indirect proofs in mathematics. I was wondering can it be proven in any case where an indirect proof exists that a direct proof does not?
The specific question asked here can easily be answered in the negative: there exist very simple statements that can be proven both directly and indirectly.

A more interesting question is whether any statement that can be proved indirectly must have a direct proof. I think, but am not certain, that the answer to that is also "no". You might want to google on "constructive mathematics", a logical position that rejects indirect proofs entirely.
 

1. What is the process for proving the existence of a proof?

The process for proving the existence of a proof varies depending on the specific proof being considered. However, in general, it involves formulating a hypothesis, gathering evidence, and using logical reasoning to demonstrate that the hypothesis is valid. This may also involve using mathematical or scientific principles to support the proof.

2. How do you determine if a proof is valid?

A valid proof is one that follows logical principles and is supported by evidence. This can include using deductive reasoning, mathematical equations, or scientific experiments to demonstrate the truth of the proof. It is also important to consider any potential counterarguments or flaws in the proof before determining its validity.

3. Can a proof ever be considered 100% certain?

While a proof can be considered very strong evidence for the truth of a hypothesis, it is rare for it to be considered 100% certain. This is because new evidence or information may arise in the future that could potentially disprove the proof. However, a proof can still be considered highly reliable and widely accepted if it has been rigorously tested and has withstood scrutiny from the scientific community.

4. How does the concept of falsifiability apply to proving the existence of a proof?

Falsifiability is the idea that a hypothesis or theory must be testable and have the potential to be proven false in order to be considered valid. This concept applies to proving the existence of a proof, as a proof must be based on evidence and logical reasoning that can be scrutinized and potentially disproven. If a proof cannot be falsified, it is not considered a valid or reliable proof.

5. What role do peer review and replication play in proving the existence of a proof?

Peer review and replication are important aspects of the scientific process that help to ensure the validity and reliability of a proof. Peer review involves having experts in the field critically evaluate a proof before it is published, providing feedback and identifying any potential flaws. Replication involves other scientists attempting to reproduce the results of a proof to confirm its validity. This process helps to strengthen the evidence and confidence in a proof's validity.

Similar threads

  • General Math
Replies
22
Views
1K
  • General Math
Replies
12
Views
1K
Replies
9
Views
433
  • General Math
Replies
11
Views
1K
Replies
13
Views
1K
  • General Math
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
33
Views
5K
  • General Math
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
18
Views
3K
Replies
72
Views
4K
Back
Top