Summary of Frauchiger-Renner

  • I
  • Thread starter DarMM
  • Start date
  • Featured
In summary, the Frauchiger-Renner theorem derives a contradiction between:Validity of Probability One predictions of quantum theory, i.e. if QM says something has 100% chance of occurring it is certain.Single World, i.e. experiments have one objective outcomeInter-agent reasoning, i.e. I can obtain my predictions by reasoning about how you would use quantum theory.Intervention insensitivity for Classical Objects/Measurement results. As a superobserver your reasoning about measuring an observer is not affected by subsequent measurements by superobservers spacelike separated from you. In short this says that observers aren't to be considered as being entangled/Bell
  • #176
bhobba said:
I personally have no issue with QM can't satisfy the three claimed assumptions simultaneously and do not see what the fuss is about. Just me.
The original FR paper is quite odd the more I think about it. It has the superobservers model the observers as being in an entangled state, but has them reason about their outcomes in a way that ignores the implications of entanglement (i.e. ignores intervention sensitivity as Healey calls it).
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #177
kurt101 said:
In Gell-Mann's EPR interpretation, how are the branches of history selected?
Gell-Mann's views are very similar to those in Omnés's book "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics", not surprising as they are both formulators of the decoherent histories approach. Omnés says that which actual branch occurs lies outside mathematical or scientific comprehension, i.e. it is a part of reality that seems like it cannot be captured mathematically.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #178
Okay a basic sketch of how Copenhagen seems to avoid Masanes's theorem in light of Bub's paper and what @atyy has been saying.

So basically the whole proof relies on Carol and Dan make measurements on an entangled pair. Then the hyperobservers Alice and Bob reversing everything the observers Carol and Dan do with the entangled pair and then perform the measurement themselves. This allows two things to happen:

  1. A single run of this experiment has four outcomes, ##a,b,c,d##, meaning there is a probability of a specific set of outcomes ##P(a,b,c,d)##.
  2. However any single pair of outcomes is a complete measurement of entangled pairs and thus obey the Bell inequality violating statistics.

The contradiction as such is that (1.) means each pair of measurements has probabilities that can be derived as marginals of ##P(a,b,c,d)##, however being marginals means they can't have the correlations Quantum theory says they must from (2.). Hence a contradiction.

Or even briefer, the set up uses reversal to make a Bell experiment a marginal of a larger experiment. However the statistics of Bell experiments preclude the fact that they could be marginals.

So the rational thing to say here in the Copenhagen view is that it shows reversals are impossible. If Bell experiments cannot be marginals from their statistical properties and reversal allows you to make them marginals, what this really shows is that reversing measurements is indeed impossible, not anything about quantum theory being perspectival or there not being a single world. That is exactly what @atyy and Bub say. I'll discuss this in more detail now.

So how does Copenhagen get out of this?

Really as @atyy and Bub say, there is a quantum-classical cut. From Asher and Peres, this can be shifted a bit but not indefinitely. There are "sections" of the world that are Boolean in their logical properties as an objective fact, which is just a formalization of Bohr's idea of the classical side of the cut. If Carol and Dan are on the Boolean/Classical side then they have outcomes and you can model them Classically by putting them on the Classical side of the cut with yourself. If you decided to model them Quantum Mechanically anyway decoherence would grant them effective Boolean status (to the point of errors terms so small, it's questionable as to whether they have a physical meaning) and following Asher-Peres you could lower the cut, although due to decoherence it won't really matter for your predictions if you do or not.

So if they are on the classical side, in the original FR paper this means they'd have a chance of ##\frac{1}{4}## for the following superobserver measurements, either from being Boolean or via decoherence. In Masanes paper this means their outcomes cannot be reversed, so the superobservers cannot go on to obtain their ##c,d## outcomes and so there is no ##P(a,b,c,d)##.

If they're on the Quantum side, they don't have any outcomes and so superposition is valid to use. In the FR paper this means the superobservers should assign a ##\frac{1}{12}## chance to their superobservable outcomes. In the Masanes version it means there are no ##a,b## outcomes from which to form ##P(a,b,c,d)##.

In short, if they are classical there are no ##c,d## outcomes, if they are quantum there are no ##a,b## outcomes. So ##P(a,b,c,d)## doesn't exist in either scenario and thus there is no contradiction.

Bub has a paper here:
https://www.mdpi.com/1099-4300/17/11/7374 (PDF is freely accesible)

It contains other examples of errors you'll obtain if you attempt to view experiments as reversible. Bub essentially describes reverisble experiments being incompatible with the "intrinsic randomness" of QM, the fact that information loss must occur when you make a measurement. The only special thing about the Masanes scenario then is that it shows this line of reasoning extends to superobservers as well.

Another point might be the general unreasonableness of the concept of a superobserver, it might be like taking an arbitrarily large observer in General Relativity and ignoring the fact that as they get larger they'd distort the spacetime. However I haven't thought enough about that.
 
Last edited:
  • #179
DarMM said:
True, what's the relation to Bub's point or are you just pointing that out? Or are you saying that demonstrates what Bohr and Bub are talking about?

To me Bub is speaking of the event algebra being Boolean at the macrolevel to permit a truth function having a clean definition and that's the real property of the non-Quantum side of the cut, i.e. you can assign true/false to macroevents even if they result from interaction with the microscopic.

I would have thought this is a separate issue as to whether you can use classical logic to reason about the mathematics of QM, unless I'm missing the point.
Mathematically, one can of course assume whatever one wants, including Boolean or non-Boolean projectors, calling them events. But I think the correct way of thinking about these is as commutative and noncommutative, not as different kinds of logic. In quantum logic, one does not even have a reasonable ''implication'' operation, and almost nothing of logical interest can be done with noncommuting ''events'' in the quantum sense.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM and bhobba
  • #180
A. Neumaier said:
Mathematically, one can of course assume whatever one wants, including Boolean or non-Boolean projectors, calling them events. But I think the correct way of thinking about these is as commutative and noncommutative, not as different kinds of logic. In quantum logic, one does not even have a reasonable ''implication'' operation, and almost nothing of logical interest can be done with noncommuting ''events'' in the quantum sense.
Okay I see what you mean. I think in a way this is Bub's point, that only when one has a commuting subalgebra do you have a Boolean structure that permits a truth function (as a two-valued homomorphism on the algebra) and hence that you have the concepts of outcomes and events that you can reason about logically. When looking at algebras that aren't Boolean you can't really view them as outcomes/events.

I think this is more a problem with my paraphrasing of him, in the sense that he means non-Boolean more as "not Boolean and thus not supporting the notion of events" rather than as a valid alternative logic, or such is what I took from his papers.

So I think the two of you might be saying basically the same thing, as he rejects there being non-Boolean events. This being part of the fact that he views quantum mechanics non-representationally.

He's not taking a Quantum Logic view if I have given that impression.
 
  • #181
bhobba said:
I find Murray's take on it much more lucid than the usual, IMHO overly sensationalist, takes on it like Henry Stapp:
This has nothing to do with physics as such, but I love in those videos how Gell-Mann attempts a native like pronunciation at everybody's names, rather than just saying them in English phonetics. You can see he really loves languages.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier and bhobba
  • #182
DarMM said:
Really as @atyy and Bub say, there is a quantum-classical cut. From Asher and Peres, this can be shifted a bit but not indefinitely.

The theory of indirect measurement, measurement ancilla etc is also about being able to shift the cut. But when the cut is shifted, what is real is also shifted.

One can see the different ideas of reality on each side of the cut in figure 1 of https://arxiv.org/abs/0706.1232 where the measurement outcomes are treated as real invariant events in the sense of classical special relativity, but the quantum state has no reality in that sense, eg. collapse is in a different plane of simultaneity in every Lorentz frame.

There is also a little bit of implicit (not explicit) discussion of the issue in https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0509061, where Einstein mentions the option to make Alice not real in an EPR experiment, to deny the nonlocality of quantum mechanics.

DarMM said:
Another point might be the general unreasonableness of the concept of a superobserver, it might be like taking an arbitrarily large observer in General Relativity and ignoring the fact that as they get larger they'd distort the spacetime. However I haven't thought enough about that.

Interesting thought. So the relationship between BM (a full description of reality, where superobservers that can unitarily reverse measurements are allowed) and Copenhagen (measurements must be irreversible) is analogous to the relationship between full GR and the approximation with geodesics? There has been some speculation that the measurement problem has to be solved for quantum gravity to be solved (my very, very free reading of standard comments in string theory). Because Copenhagen QM needs an observer, and the observer needs a stable place to stand, that explains why quantum gravity has so far only been defined in AdS space, which provides a boundary for the observer to stand.
 
  • Like
Likes akvadrako
  • #183
Demystifier said:
@DarMM there is one additional question that I would like to discuss with you. Do we really need the undoing of measurement in the FR-Masanes-Leifer theorem? Or can we achieve the same just by preparing another copy of the system?

Let me explain. The basic common scheme in all these thought experiments is the following:
1. First prepare the system in the state ##|\Psi\rangle##.
2. Then perform a measurement described by a unitary operation ##U|\Psi\rangle##.
3. After that undo the measurement by acting with ##V=U^{-1}##, which gives ##VU|\Psi\rangle=|\Psi\rangle##.
4. Finally perform a new measurement ##U'|\Psi\rangle##.

But for the sake of proving the theorem, it seems to me that we don't really need the step 3. Instead, we can perform:

3'. Prepare a new copy of the state ##|\Psi\rangle##.

After that, 4. refers to this new copy. Note that ##|\Psi\rangle## is a known state, so the no-cloning theorem is not an obstacle for preparing a new copy in the same state.

The only problem I see with this is the following. The state ##|\Psi\rangle## is really something of the form
$$|\Psi\rangle=|\psi\rangle |{\rm detector \;\; ready}\rangle$$
which involves not only a simple state ##|\psi\rangle## of the measured system, but also a complex state ##|{\rm detector \;\; ready}\rangle ## of the macroscopic detector. In practice it is very very hard to have a control under all microscopic details of the macroscopic detector, meaning that it is very very hard to prepare two identical copies of ##|\Psi\rangle##. Nevertheless, it is not harder than performing the operation ##V##, which also requires a control under all microscopic details of the macroscopic detector to ensure that ##V## is exactly the inverse of ##U##. So for practical purposes, 3.' is as hard as 3. Yet the advantage of 3.' over 3. is that it is more intuitive conceptually.

So is there any reason why would theorem lose its power if we used 3'. instead of 3.?
Sorry for the late reply only got around to this now.

I would view that set up as a set of four measurements on the four particle state ##|\Psi,\Psi\rangle##, a product state of two Bell pairs.

In that situation ##E(a,d)## and ##E(b,c)## would vanish and there is no contradiction with Fine's theorem.

Or so it seems to me.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #184
DarMM said:
Sorry for the late reply only got around to this now.

I would view that set up as a set of four measurements on the four particle state ##|\Psi,\Psi\rangle##, a product state of two Bell pairs.

In that situation ##E(a,d)## and ##E(b,c)## would vanish and there is no contradiction with Fine's theorem.

Or so it seems to me.
Interesting argument, but I disagree because I wouldn't say that ##E(a,d)## and ##E(b,c)## would vanish. For definiteness, let me concentrate on ##E(a,d)##. Clearly, it does not vanish if ##a## and ##d## are measured on the same copy of ##|\Psi\rangle##. In the original version of the thought experiment, the non-vanishing ##E(a,d)## corresponds to an experimental procedure in which ##a## and ##d## are measured without undoing any of the measurements. It is only ##corr(a,d)## (which is different from ##E(a,d)##) that involves undoing of measurements.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #185
Demystifier said:
Interesting argument, but I disagree because I wouldn't say that ##E(a,d)## and ##E(b,c)## would vanish. For definiteness, let me concentrate on ##E(a,d)##. Clearly, it does not vanish if ##a## and ##d## are measured on the same copy of ##|\Psi\rangle##. In the original version of the thought experiment, the non-vanishing ##E(a,d)## corresponds to an experimental procedure in which ##a## and ##d## are measured without undoing any of the measurements. It is only ##corr(a,d)## (which is different from ##E(a,d)##) that involves undoing of measurements.
Sorry yes, I should say ##corr(a,d)##.
##E(a,d)## being the Bell correlations with those same angles ##a## and ##d##, which would be ##corr(a,d)##'s numerical value if you believe in a interpretation satisfying Masanes's conditions.

So let me be more clear.

##corr(a,d)## in Masanes's set up would have the value ##E(a,d)## if you believe in an interpretation satisfying his conditions. It doesn't have to in all interpretations as we have already discussed, Bohmian Mechanics and Retrocausal theories could have ##corr(a,d) \neq E(a,d)##. It is the fact that ##corr(a,d) = E(a,d)## that ultimately leads to the contradiction with Fine's theorem.

In the version you propose ##a,d## are measurements on separate Bell pairs, not a measurement on the same Bell pair after one has been measurement reversed. Thus ##corr(a,d) = 0## due to it being product state and hence there is no contradiction with Fine's theorem.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #186
DarMM said:
In the version you propose ##a,d## are measurements on separate Bell pairs, not a measurement on the same Bell pair after one has been measurement reversed. Thus ##corr(a,d) = 0## due to it being product state and hence there is no contradiction with Fine's theorem.
Fine, but then I think that ##corr(a,d) = 0## also in the Masanes's version. In particular, ##corr(a,d) = 0## is compatible with Eq. (31). Is there anything in the paper that contradicts my claim that ##corr(a,d) = 0## in the Masanes's setup?
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #187
Demystifier said:
Fine, but then I think that ##corr(a,d) = 0## also in the Masanes's version. In particular, ##corr(a,d) = 0## is compatible with Eq. (31). Is there anything in the paper that contradicts my claim that ##corr(a,d) = 0## in the Masanes's setup?
Once Alice has reversed Carol's measurement, then the entanglement between the two photons is restored and thus Alice's measurement on the first photon and Dan's measurement on the second photon proceed as if Carol hadn't done anything, thus it is a typical Bell measurement and ##corr(a,d) = E(a,d) = -cos(a - d)##.

This is unlike your case where Alice is performing a measurement on the first photon of a separate pair to Dan rather than the first photon of the same pair and thus you'd expect no correlation.
 
  • #188
DarMM said:
Once Alice has reversed Carol's measurement, then the entanglement between the two photons is restored and thus Alice's measurement on the first photon and Dan's measurement on the second photon proceed as if Carol hadn't done anything, thus it is a typical Bell measurement and ##corr(a,d) = E(a,d) = -cos(a - d)##.
But we agreed that ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)## for some ##i,j##. So if ##corr(a,d) = E(a,d)##, then for which ##i,j## do we have ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)##?
 
  • #189
Demystifier said:
But we agreed that ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)## for some ##i,j##. So if ##corr(a,d) = E(a,d)##, then for which ##i,j## do we have ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)##?
##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)## for some ##i,j## only for interpretations breaking one of Masanes's assumptions.
 
  • #190
DarMM said:
##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)## for some ##i,j## only for interpretations breaking one of Masanes's assumptions.
Fine, so let us consider one such interpretation. For definiteness, let it be Bohmian mechanics. Then for which ##i,j## do we have ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)##?
 
  • #191
Demystifier said:
Fine, so let us consider one such interpretation. For definiteness, let it be Bohmian mechanics. Then for which ##i,j## do we have ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)##?
I don't know, I don't know Bohmian Mechanics well enough to carry out the computation. This paper here: https://arxiv.org/abs/1809.08070, shows how it avoids the original Frauchiger-Renner argument. Probably a similar calculation will show what occurs in Masanes's version, an empty wave comes along and causes ##corr(i,j) \neq E(i,j)## for some ##i,j##.

However I don't think it matters because Bohmian Mechanics doesn't obey the assumptions of the theorem and thus isn't susceptible to it. It's not a theorem that shows anything about Bohmian Mechanics.

What it does counter are views like those of Healey himself (which is why Healey is concerned with it), Cutless Objective Copenhagen views, i.e. views that want QM to be an objective generalized probability calculus and no more.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #192
Hold the phone!

I was just reading this paper here:
https://arxiv.org/pdf/1901.10331.pdf

Which agrees with you that ##corr(b,c) = 0## for Alice's frame (and similar at least one vanishes for every frame) and that no real contradiction is reached even for views like Healey's (which would mean Healey is wrong about his own incorrectness!)

I'd be interested to hear your thoughts.

If that paper is valid, then my original post could be modified to
"Summary of Frauchiger-Renner: Don't bother!" :eek:

EDIT:
From a proper read of their paper they basically say once Carol obtains a result, the ##b## result will be correlated with it via the normal predictions for a Bell pair ##E(c,b) = -cos(c - b)##.

However once you reverse the measurement, you restore the first particle back to its original state and could result in any value upon Alice's ##a## measurement. This reversal then decouples the value of ##b## from the value of ##c## and thus ##E(c,b) = 0##, because for predicting ##b## it is as if ##c## never occurred.

Similarly for ##E(a,d)##. Thus there is no contradiction with Fine's theorem.

This seems pretty valid to me and would render Masanes's result fairly powerless.

Open to correction though.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes atyy and Demystifier
  • #193
@DarMM It seems interesting, but I need some time to study it in detail.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #194
No worries. In short I think it validates your example. If you totally reverse the measurement it is like preparing a new state because you've completely undone any effects. So the event ##c## becomes completely detached from the event ##b## and similarly ##d## from ##a##. Hence ##E(b,c) = E(a,d) = 0##
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #195
DarMM said:
No worries. In short I think it validates your example. If you totally reverse the measurement it is like preparing a new state because you've completely undone any effects. So the event ##c## becomes completely detached from the event ##b## and similarly ##d## from ##a##. Hence ##E(b,c) = E(a,d) = 0##
Did you mean ##corr(b,c) = corr(a,d) = 0##?
 
  • Like
Likes atyy and DarMM
  • #196
Ha! Sorry, yes indeed ##corr(b,c) = corr(a,d) = 0##.

The papers themselves aren't very careful in making that distinction in their notation just to warn you.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy and Demystifier
  • #197
DarMM said:
Ha! Sorry, yes indeed ##corr(b,c) = corr(a,d) = 0##.
So, whatever the Masanes theorem proves, the same thing can also be proved without undoing measurements, by using two copies of the state. Do we agree now?
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #198
Yes and I think that means Masanes proves very little.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy and Demystifier
  • #199
DarMM said:
Yes and I think that means Masanes proves very little.
Yes, I have concluded it already in #44, while my later arguments only served to refine that conclusion. Thank you very much for the discussion, without you I would never understood all that. :smile:
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #200
The final summary:

What do the Frauchiger-Renner-Masanes-Leifer-Healey (FRMLH) theorems actually prove?

They just prove contextuality, that is the already known fact that the process of measurement can change the properties of the system.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #201
Demystifier said:
Yes, I have concluded it already in #44, while my later arguments only served to refine that conclusion. Thank you very much for the discussion, without you I would never understood all that. :smile:
Thanks to you as well and also @atyy . I've learned a lot from this thread, including having a much better grasp of Old/Classic Copenhagen. I've come to have a better understanding of the need for the Heisenberg Cut and through discussions here and Bub's papers a better understanding of the strange implications of reversibility and how you have to be careful when reasoning about reversed results.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #202
A. Neumaier said:
Just a comment that is often overlooked: Until at least the end of 1927 (Solvay conference), the quantum physicists in Göttingen and Copenhagen had a realistic view of quantum mechanics in which particles were always in stationary states (characterized by energy and momentum) and performed quantum jumps guided by the wave function. Thus in their writing, state = stationary state and not = wave function up to a phase! And only the wave function was sort of epistemic...
A. Neumaier said:
I haven't seen my claim explicitly researched on from a comparative historical point of view. But I am doing a historical study myself, and have plenty of detailed evidence, that will be the content of a paper to be finished later this year. Once one realizes what I wrote, many otherwise difficult to understand things get a straightforward sense.
Auto-Didact said:
Nice, can't wait to read it!
The essence is now here, rather than in a paper.
 
  • Like
Likes Auto-Didact
<h2>1. What is the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?</h2><p>The Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment is a hypothetical scenario proposed by physicists Markus Frauchiger and Renato Renner. It aims to demonstrate the limitations of quantum mechanics and the existence of multiple inconsistent realities.</p><h2>2. How does the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment work?</h2><p>In the thought experiment, a quantum system is measured by two different observers, Alice and Bob. Each observer obtains a different measurement outcome, leading to two different realities. However, when the observers share their results, they find that both outcomes cannot be true simultaneously, revealing a contradiction in the laws of quantum mechanics.</p><h2>3. What is the significance of the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?</h2><p>The thought experiment challenges the widely accepted interpretation of quantum mechanics and raises questions about the nature of reality and the role of observers in quantum systems. It also has implications for the development of future theories that can better explain the behavior of quantum systems.</p><h2>4. What conclusions can be drawn from the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?</h2><p>The thought experiment suggests that quantum mechanics may not be a complete theory and that there may be underlying principles or laws that govern the behavior of quantum systems. It also highlights the importance of considering the role of observers in quantum mechanics and the need for a more comprehensive understanding of the nature of reality.</p><h2>5. Are there any criticisms of the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?</h2><p>Some physicists have criticized the thought experiment for being too abstract and not reflecting real-world scenarios. Others argue that the conclusions drawn from the experiment may not be applicable to all interpretations of quantum mechanics. Additionally, there is ongoing debate about the validity of the assumptions made in the thought experiment and whether they accurately reflect the behavior of quantum systems.</p>

1. What is the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?

The Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment is a hypothetical scenario proposed by physicists Markus Frauchiger and Renato Renner. It aims to demonstrate the limitations of quantum mechanics and the existence of multiple inconsistent realities.

2. How does the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment work?

In the thought experiment, a quantum system is measured by two different observers, Alice and Bob. Each observer obtains a different measurement outcome, leading to two different realities. However, when the observers share their results, they find that both outcomes cannot be true simultaneously, revealing a contradiction in the laws of quantum mechanics.

3. What is the significance of the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?

The thought experiment challenges the widely accepted interpretation of quantum mechanics and raises questions about the nature of reality and the role of observers in quantum systems. It also has implications for the development of future theories that can better explain the behavior of quantum systems.

4. What conclusions can be drawn from the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?

The thought experiment suggests that quantum mechanics may not be a complete theory and that there may be underlying principles or laws that govern the behavior of quantum systems. It also highlights the importance of considering the role of observers in quantum mechanics and the need for a more comprehensive understanding of the nature of reality.

5. Are there any criticisms of the Frauchiger-Renner thought experiment?

Some physicists have criticized the thought experiment for being too abstract and not reflecting real-world scenarios. Others argue that the conclusions drawn from the experiment may not be applicable to all interpretations of quantum mechanics. Additionally, there is ongoing debate about the validity of the assumptions made in the thought experiment and whether they accurately reflect the behavior of quantum systems.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
27
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
42
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
846
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
577
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
18
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
6
Replies
175
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
35
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
12
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
4
Views
1K
Back
Top