Wittgenstein & Doubt: Can You Know What You Cannot Doubt?

  • Thread starter wittgenstein
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Doubt
In summary: There is a dependency. A blocked artery in the heart will cause tissue death and excite pain receptors and pathways. The pain of a heart attack (MI) is usually very characteristic in terms of location, pattern and qualitative description. One can...There is a dependency. A blocked artery in the heart will cause tissue death and excite pain receptors and pathways. The pain of a heart attack (MI) is usually very characteristic in terms of location, pattern and qualitative description. One can say that the pain of a heart attack is very similar to the pain of a toothache. The pain of a heart attack is due to a blocked artery and the pain of a toothache is due to a tooth that is not fixed into the jaw.
  • #1
wittgenstein
216
7
Wittgenstein often made the statement that if you cannot doubt that a thing is so, you cannot know it. For example ( the example he gives) , you cannot know that you are in pain because you cannot doubt it. You cannot say," This pain hurts but I doubt that I feel it."
I can understand how when you are in pain you cannot doubt that you are in pain. However, I do not see the leap from that and saying that you cannot know that you are in pain. Why cannot you know something that you cannot doubt? I have read a lot of Wittgenstein and have never found an answer to this. It seems like he just takes it as a given.
I thought that maybe it has something to do with the idea that if a statement refers to everything and nothing in particular it is a meaningless statement. Unfortunately, I have failed to make it connect to the idea that you cannot know something that you cannot doubt.
Help?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
wittgenstein said:
Wittgenstein often made the statement that if you cannot doubt that a thing is so, you cannot know it. For example ( the example he gives) , you cannot know that you are in pain because you cannot doubt it. You cannot say," This pain hurts but I doubt that I feel it."

I think he's using 'know' in a very specific sense. Knowledge is constructed, it has a structure, with dependencies. Sensation does not, sensation is what it is, you can't doubt it because it has no logical, or quantitative form. He talks about his in 'On Certainty'.

Doubt is part of the structure of knowledge, part of what gives the meaning. You can't understand pain, you can only feel it.
 
  • #3
JoeDawg said:
I think he's using 'know' in a very specific sense. Knowledge is constructed, it has a structure, with dependencies. Sensation does not, sensation is what it is, you can't doubt it because it has no logical, or quantitative form. He talks about his in 'On Certainty'.

Doubt is part of the structure of knowledge, part of what gives the meaning. You can't understand pain, you can only feel it.

You can still experience pain through subtle sensations you are not consciously aware of like internal bleeding right?
 
  • #4
noblegas said:
You can still experience pain through subtle sensations you are not consciously aware of like internal bleeding right?

Not sure what you mean.
 
  • #5
wittgenstein said:
Wittgenstein often made the statement that if you cannot doubt that a thing is so, you cannot know it. For example ( the example he gives) , you cannot know that you are in pain because you cannot doubt it. You cannot say," This pain hurts but I doubt that I feel it."
I can understand how when you are in pain you cannot doubt that you are in pain. However, I do not see the leap from that and saying that you cannot know that you are in pain.

Frankly the statement makes no sense to me when you're speaking of sensations like pain. The subject is the only one who can know if he or she is in pain. However, if you're talking about tautologies, I would agree. "Either it is raining or it is not raining". You cannot doubt this is true but it conveys no knowledge.

EDIT: I think we need to define "structured knowledge". Pain has location, intensity, pattern, duration, etc. Eliciting this structure from the subject is invaluable in diagnosis and treatment.
 
Last edited:
  • #6
From: On Certainty

41. "I know where I am feeling pain", "I know that I feel it here" is as wrong as "I know that I am in pain". But "I know where you touched my arm" is right.

What is the difference?

You can add 'because' to the end of the last sentence and justify what you say, because it has dependencies. The first three do not.
 
  • #7
JoeDawg said:
From: On Certainty

41. "I know where I am feeling pain", "I know that I feel it here" is as wrong as "I know that I am in pain". But "I know where you touched my arm" is right.

What is the difference?

You can add 'because' to the end of the last sentence and justify what you say, because it has dependencies. The first three do not.

Interesting philosophy. Wittgenstein (W) was very influential. I like his rigorous approach to philosophy. However, he is not infallible. Assuming the pain has an identifiable physical cause, it represents a signal from the site of the dysfunction to the brain just like any sense data, whether it originates from the eye, ear, or internal sensory nerves specific for pain.

There is a dependency. A blocked artery in the heart will cause tissue death and excite pain receptors and pathways. The pain of a heart attack (MI) is usually very characteristic in terms of location, pattern and qualitative description. One can justifiably say I have pain because...

Now the subject may not know the cause (dependency) but will know he has pain just as he knows what he sees or hears even though his eyes and ears. I saw a tree fall. Do I know the tree fell? I may not know the cause of the tree falling but I know the tree fell. Is W saying I can't know the tree fell because I don't know the cause? If that's the case we can't know anything based on sense data.
 
  • #8
Perhaps W simply meant you must have something to compare with, to judge you are in a certain state - of pain or something. And as soon as you are "comparing" you are "doubting" in some sense. I don't agree with that, but guess he must have meant something like that.

An other interesting thesis from him is said to be "The problems disappear if you don't think of them". That often works also in practical life, is my experience. Although it must be unwise relying on it... :rolleyes:
 
  • #9
M Grandin said:
Perhaps W simply meant you must have something to compare with, to judge you are in a certain state - of pain or something. And as soon as you are "comparing" you are "doubting" in some sense. I don't agree with that, but guess he must have meant something like that.

An other interesting thesis from him is said to be "The problems disappear if you don't think of them". That often works also in practical life, is my experience. Although it must be unwise relying on it... :rolleyes:

Well, people can certainly know pain free states. If they were in pain all the time, it would be "normal" and adaption might occur. There would be nothing to know. But since they experience both, they have a basis of reference.They know they're in pain because they doubt they are pain free.

It's strange to me that W picked this example. I think his basic idea is correct in that knowledge requires context. Also sense data can be misleading. The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Robert Audi ed, 1995) defines knowledge as a "justified true belief". However the quality of justification is not specified, and we mostly rely on heuristic methods based on context.

For example, the subject gives a history of pain suggestive of MI. Subsequent tests confirm the diagnosis based on established criteria. This is the justification of MI. The subject might only know it was chest pain, but did go the emergency ward, so he believed it might be significant. The chest pain alone was the justification for a level of concern. He was able to describe the pain, guided by the physician's questions, which lead to the ordering of tests. The subject certainly knew he had pain because it occurred in context. Moreover, he could describe the pain in terms of important details it so as to differentiate from others similar states, giving it structure (and possibly saving his life).
 
Last edited:
  • #10
SW VandeCarr said:
There is a dependency. A blocked artery in the heart will cause tissue death and excite pain receptors and pathways.
You don't feel a blocked artery, you feel pain.
You're conflating the two, sensation/explanation, whereas he is being very careful to avoid doing that.
 
  • #11
JoeDawg said:
You don't feel a blocked artery, you feel pain.
You're conflating the two, sensation/explanation, whereas he is being very careful to avoid doing that.

As I've said, pain is a sensation. So is vision and hearing. It's true pain is not may not be as discriminating as vision and hearing but one knows they have pain which can be described. They know they have pain because it's contextual. That is they have the experience of being pain free and can doubt they are pain free. That's the way I interpret W's position. If he did mean that we must doubt pain we sense, then we must doubt all sense data. All a posteriori knowledge is based on sense data or inferred from sense data. You're not going to say that W denied all a posteriori knowledge, are you?

If W was a physician (he did consider going to medical school), would he have told my subject with chest pain that he can't know he has chest pain and sent him home?

EDIT: I'm not conflating a blocked artery with the sensation of chest pain. The latter is dependent on the former.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
SW VandeCarr said:
one knows they have pain which can be described.
No, he's saying pretty much the opposite.

"I know where I am feeling pain",
"I know that I feel it here"
is as wrong as
"I know that I am in pain".

Its a similar distinction, I would say, to Kant's phenomenology. The thinginitself is unknowable. That doesn't mean we don't have knowledge of things.
Wittgenstein is saying knowledge is not about sense experience.
They know they have pain because it's contextual.
Knowledge is contextual, pain is not knowledge.
That is they have the experience of being pain free and can doubt they are pain free.
With regards to doubt, he is stating that you cannot doubt a sensation. You either experience pain or not. Its not open to doubt. Sensation is not, therefore, knowledge, since according to W, knowledge requires doubt.
You're not going to say that W denied all a posteriori knowledge, are you?
I'm going to say, that W distingished between an empirical proposition, and a sensation.

I am sitting in a chair, is an empirical proposition.
I am cold, is a sensation.

W can say, I know I am sitting in a chair.
W cannot say, I know I am cold.

There is no direct sense experience in the first.
I could be sitting on a stool, or the floor.
Doubt doesn't mean that something is not true.

But if I'm cold, I can't doubt that I am. I'm either cold or not. So it doesn't involve doubt, and therefore I can't 'know' it.

W is trying to distinguish between a common understanding of knowing and his very strict understanding of it.
 
  • #13
SW VandeCarr said:
I'm not conflating a blocked artery with the sensation of chest pain. The latter is dependent on the former.

In a medical sense, yes the chest pain is a result of the blocked artery, but this is not what W is referring to.

I can doubt your theory of medicine.
I can't doubt the pain I'm having.
 
  • #14
JoeDawg said:
No, he's saying pretty much the opposite.

"
I am sitting in a chair, is an empirical proposition.
I am cold, is a sensation.
If you mean that sitting in a chair is something that can be observed by others, than I agree. However. both the observation of another and your own sensations are based on sense dat

W can say, I know I am sitting in a chair.
W cannot say, I know I am cold.

There is no direct sense experience in the first.
I could be sitting on a stool, or the floor.
Doubt doesn't mean that something is not true.

But if I'm cold, I can't doubt that I am. I'm either cold or not. So it doesn't involve doubt, and therefore I can't 'know' it.

The only sensible thing I can extract from this is that some states can be observed by others (objective) and others states can only be known to the subject (subjective). But in both cases, knowledge is mediated by sense data. How do you know you are sitting in a chair? Because of visual and proprioceptive sense data. How do you know you are cold? Because of sense data from the skin and muscles, How does someone else know you are sitting in a chair. Because of visual sense data. It's true that the other can't know you are cold (unless you're shivering) unless you tell him. But the other gets that information by hearing you.

I've already said that only the subject can know his own sensations, but they do know them. You're confusing a binary variable with a tautology. In the former, the subject knows he is in one of two possible states. In the latter. if you say I'm either cold or not cold, that's a tautology which cannot be doubted.

If the subject tells someone else that he is cold, that's subject to doubt by the other. Are you saying that the other knows the subject is cold because he has doubt, but subject himself can't know if he's cold because he has no doubt?

EDIT: I believe there has to be a distinction between logical tautologies which cannot be doubted but convey no knowledge, and subjective knowledge which only the subject can know without doubt. If you doubt this, please address the apparent contradiction in the previous paragraph.
 
Last edited:
  • #15
SW VandeCarr said:
The only sensible thing I can extract from this is that some states can be observed by others (objective) and others states can only be known to the subject (subjective).
He's not talking about states, he's talking about knowledge. You're confusing epistemology and ontology.

W would say 'we have pain', but 'we don't know pain'.
He sees knowing something as requiring 'doubt'.

And no, when it comes to words like 'doubt' and 'know', he is not using dictionary definitions. If you haven't already, you should read 'On Certainty'. Otherwise we'll just be going round and round.
How do you know you are sitting in a chair? Because of visual and proprioceptive sense data.
Sigh. No, its not that simple.

I know the sun will come up tomorrow. How? By inductive reasoning, not sense data.
If I limited knowledge to sense data, I could never say I know the sun will come up tomorrow. I could only state that 'I know' what is right in front of me.

And I couldn't say I know there are neurons inside my skull, unless I opened up my skull and looked. And if I sowed it back up, I couldn't say I know they are still there, because I can't see them any more, and they are no longer part of my sense data.

So you are wrong, what we call 'knowledge' is not mediated by sense data. We use logic and reasoning as well.
How do you know you are cold?
You don't, according to W, you either 'feel' cold or not.
It has nothing to do with nerve cells. You don't feel nerve cells. You feel cold.
I've already said that only the subject can know his own sensations
Fine, but that's not the issue.
You're confusing a binary variable with a tautology. In the former, the subject knows he is in one of two possible states. In the latter. if you say I'm either cold or not cold, that's a tautology which cannot be doubted.
W is saying: I cannot doubt I am in pain, when I am in pain.
I cannot doubt the sensations that I have.

The reason this is important, is because I can doubt other things.
And part of knowing something is being able to doubt it.
If the subject tells someone else that he is cold, that's subject to doubt by the other.
But that is not what W is talking about.
He is saying: If I am in pain, then I can't doubt that I am in pain.
And therefore I don't know pain, because knowing something requires that it can be doubted.
It has nothing to do with other subject vs. object.
Are you saying that the other...
There is no other here. This is about me.

I feel pain.
I know I am sitting at a desk.

No others needed here, you are just complicating the issue.

*I* can't doubt pain, because, it is part of raw experience.
*I* can doubt my understanding of a situation, because that understanding is not a raw sensation.

I can have sensations while sitting at a desk, and certain sensations lead me to believe that I am sitting at a desk, but 'sitting at a desk' is not a sensation. I can doubt 'sitting at a desk'.
 
  • #16
OK. We can end this now. W is not using the definition of knowledge that I quoted from the Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. It's not mainstream philosophy. The standard definition is a "justified true belief". Knowledge is a belief. You believe the sun will rise to tomorrow because it always has. You have observed it consistently. It may not one day due some cosmic catastrophe.

http://absentpresent.blogspot.com/2008/12/wittgenstein-critique-of-certainty-and.html

Go back and read my last post If you tell someone you're cold, the other can reasonably doubt you are cold. You however cannot. You are saying the other has doubt and therefore can know you are cold, but you can't know you are cold because you don't doubt it. That's simply absurd. You cannot just eliminate the other person. If you were isolated from birth in an empty windowless room, fed by a caretaker who never spoke, how much would you know after ten years? W is elevating some sense data above others without justification.

http://univie.academia.edu/MartinKu...stein--On-Certainty--and-Epistemic-Relativism
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #17
JoeDawg said:
He's not talking about states, he's talking about knowledge. I can have sensations while sitting at a desk, and certain sensations lead me to believe that I am sitting at a desk, but 'sitting at a desk' is not a sensation. I can doubt 'sitting at a desk'.

This is a good example. Are you saying you can doubt sitting at a desk because you doubt your senses or because you could be doing something else at that moment in time? If its the latter, I agree with you because it's one of many possibilities. As long as these possibilities are exhausted and not linked to each other by either/or conjunctions, this is contextual knowledge. If it's the former, you are doubting the validity of all sense data.

You can doubt the validity of a particular sense datum just as you can doubt the validity of a measurement. Observations, both scientific and common, can be wrong, but we must rely on them, coupled with reason, to have reliable knowledge.

I don't understand the distinction between the belief that you are sitting at a desk and the statement: "I am sitting at a desk". Is this not a statement of your justified belief?
 
  • #18
SW VandeCarr said:
you are doubting the validity of all sense data.
W would probably say all sense data is 'valid'. What might not be valid is the value we give sense data, the way we arrange it.

I can doubt the meaning I give sense data, but I can't doubt the sensation.
I can doubt my concept of 'I', 'chair' and 'sitting', but I can't doubt the various sensations that I use to construct those concepts.

There is nothing about 'hard' or 'soft' that equals 'something to sit on'. Knowledge is constructed, sensation is not.

'I am sitting on a chair' relies on a huge number of interlinking concepts, all of which I can doubt to one degree or another. This is knowledge. Doubt does not equal denial. This is not an ontological argument about solipsism. Its about knowledge.
I don't understand the distinction between the belief that you are sitting at a desk and the statement: "I am sitting at a desk". Is this not a statement of your justified belief?

Justification implies the need to justify, it implies that one could doubt.

In On Certainty, W addresses the difference between belief and knowledge in some length.

The important part with regards to doubt, is that all knowledge can be doubted. Doubt is an implicit part of knowledge.

I can doubt my concept of self: that I am distinct from the world, mind is distinct from body
I can doubt my conception of objects and how the interact: chair and sitting.
But I can't doubt the sensations involved in sitting.

That absolutely does not mean I am 'denying' that I am sitting in a chair.

Compare Descartes 'certain knowledge' (with regards to Cogito Ergo Sum.)
Wittgenstein would call that a contradiction in terms. Knowledge requires doubt.
 
  • #19
JoeDawg said:
Justification implies the need to justify, it implies that one could doubt.

OK. If you want to say that justification implies doubt, then I have to agree with you and in fact we can doubt our senses. If you read the links I provided (post 16) W's positions in On Certainty are viewed as fairly radical and certainly a departure from mainstream philosophy.

My understanding has always been that we can have direct knowledge through sense data, and indirect knowledge based on deduction, induction and authority.

Direct Knowledge: The car is in the garage. Justification: I can see it and I can feel it.
The car's horn works. Justification: I can hear it.
The car is cold. Justification: I can feel it.

Indirect knowledge is usually acquired by way of language which is mediated primarily through the visual and auditory sensory apparatus and requires the a priori ability to learn language. One can debate whether the ability to reason is a priori or learned a posteriori. Ir's probably bit of both.

For example: They speak Swedish in Sweden. Justification: Authority, unless I've actually been in Sweden. If I have, I would still need to understand Swedish to confirm they are speaking Swedish. They all might in fact be speaking Norwegian.
 
Last edited:
  • #20
SW VandeCarr said:
in fact we can doubt our senses.

We can doubt what our senses 'tell us'.
We can't doubt that we experience sensation.
 
  • #21
JoeDawg said:
We can doubt what our senses 'tell us'.
We can't doubt that we experience sensation.

How about: I'm cold. Justification: I can feel it
 
  • #22
SW VandeCarr said:
How about: I'm cold. Justification: I can feel it

What is the difference between being cold and feeling cold?
 
  • #23
JoeDawg said:
What is the difference between being cold and feeling cold?

A younger W would probably point out the semantic difference: "I am cold because I feel cold". In fact you could doubt this statement because feeling and being are two different verbs expressing two different things. Therefore there can be doubt.

If sense data is valid, then why should there be a difference in validity between feeling, hearing and vision? Is there any fundamental difference between saying the 'The car is cold' and "I am cold'?

I'm fairly sure W would have agreed with this in his earlier life. When he wrote "On Certainty" he was near the end of his life. By most accounts, his positions were much more radical at this time. Read the second link in post 16. What you're reading now (OC) is not mainstream epistemology even now.
 
Last edited:
  • #24
SW VandeCarr said:
"I am cold because I feel cold". In fact you could doubt this statement because feeling and being are two different verbs

Like I said, you're not using the word 'doubt' the way W is.
And in your example they are very different.
One describes a state of being, one describes an experience.

It is the latter that W is referring to, when he says you cannot doubt pain.

'I feel cold' cannot be doubted.

All you did was construct a strawman.
I think we're done.
 
  • #25
wittgenstein said:
I can understand how when you are in pain you cannot doubt that you are in pain. However, I do not see the leap from that and saying that you cannot know that you are in pain. Why cannot you know something that you cannot doubt? I have read a lot of Wittgenstein and have never found an answer to this.

I think W had changed his views. He had, by the time he wrote OC, repudiated much of his earlier positions based on his Tractatus. The younger W rejected "metaphysical" statements in favor of statements that could, in principle, be validated. Such statements, I presume, would be knowledge. Sense, data, in the context of reading the output of experiments, would seem to central to acquiring knowledge. I agree sense data per se is not knowledge (at least not propositional knowledge), but it can be the justification for knowledge. If you can interpret pain (its pattern of manifestation) you can justify a belief; and "justified true belief" remains the mainstream definition of knowledge regardless of what W has asserted.

If you're philosophy major, the following link may be just a review for you, but I found it a good summary of the philosophical debates regarding sense data.

http://www.utm.edu/research/iep/s/sense-da.htm
 
Last edited:

1. What is Wittgenstein's view on doubt?

Wittgenstein believed that doubt is a natural and necessary part of human thinking and language. He argued that doubting is a linguistic activity that involves the use of language and that we cannot doubt everything because we must have some basic beliefs that we take for granted.

2. Can we know what we cannot doubt according to Wittgenstein?

No, according to Wittgenstein, we cannot know what we cannot doubt. He believed that our knowledge is limited to what we can express and understand through language, and if we cannot doubt something, then we cannot talk or think about it, and therefore we cannot know it.

3. What is the relationship between language and doubt in Wittgenstein's philosophy?

For Wittgenstein, language and doubt are closely interconnected. He argued that doubt is a linguistic activity, and that our doubts and beliefs are expressed through language. He also believed that the meaning of language is determined by its use, and that we cannot doubt something if we do not have the words to express it.

4. How does Wittgenstein's view on doubt differ from Descartes' view?

Wittgenstein's view on doubt differs from Descartes' in several ways. While Descartes saw doubt as a method for finding certain knowledge, Wittgenstein saw it as a natural and necessary part of human thinking. Additionally, Descartes believed that there are certain things that we can know with absolute certainty, while Wittgenstein argued that our knowledge is limited by the boundaries of language.

5. What is the significance of Wittgenstein's philosophy of doubt?

Wittgenstein's philosophy of doubt has had a significant impact on the fields of philosophy, linguistics, and psychology. His ideas have influenced theories on language, meaning, and knowledge, and have challenged traditional notions of certainty and doubt. His emphasis on the role of language in shaping our understanding of the world has also had a profound impact on the way we think about and communicate ideas.

Similar threads

  • General Discussion
Replies
17
Views
2K
Replies
32
Views
3K
  • General Discussion
Replies
22
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
2
Replies
38
Views
2K
  • General Discussion
Replies
3
Views
811
  • Precalculus Mathematics Homework Help
Replies
8
Views
232
  • Mechanical Engineering
Replies
7
Views
531
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • General Discussion
Replies
3
Views
651
  • General Discussion
2
Replies
46
Views
2K
Back
Top