Solving ∀x(Fx → ∀y(Fy → y=x)) - Help Appreciated!

  • Thread starter nobahar
  • Start date
In summary: No, that's not the correct interpretation. The "domain" of y is the set of specific things you can set y equal to. Fy is presumably a statement function. When set y equal to some specific y1 then you can determine if Fy1 is true. If Fy1 is true then y1 = x, but Fy1 doesn't have to be true. So you can substitute things for y that aren't equal to x.
  • #1
nobahar
497
2
Hello!

This is pretty much my first venture into this notation, and I was wondering if someone could help me with this:

∀x(Fx → ∀y(Fy → y=x))

As far as I am aware, ∀y(Fy → y=x) means for all y, whatever y you plug in, its domain is limited to x, so y is x, and f(y) is f(x): i.e. it limits y to 'being' x.
Something like (Fx & ∀y(Fy → y=x)) makes sense, because its basically saying F can only be over x: there is only one F, namely x; if we tried to introduce something else, ∀y(Fy → y=x) tells us that it has to be x, so it can't be anything else, only x.

If ∀y(Fy → y=x) = u

then what does ∀x(Fx → u) mean? There's no u = x, is it over a domain?, or is it saying if F(x) is true then u? In which case the same notation is saying different things, which apparently it can; but in this case without clarification that this is is happening.
Or is it saying something like: for all x: for F(x), y in F(y) is limited to being x, and that this is true for all y?

Hopefully that makes sense.
Any help appreciated!
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
nobahar said:
As far as I am aware, ∀y(Fy → y=x) means for all y, whatever y you plug in, its domain is limited to x, so y is x, and f(y) is f(x): i.e. it limits y to 'being' x.

No, that's not the correct interpretation. The "domain" of y is the set of specific things you can set y equal to. Fy is presumably a statement function. When set y equal to some specific y1 then you can determine if Fy1 is true. If Fy1 is true then y1 = x, but Fy1 doesn't have to be true. So you can substitute things for y that aren't equal to x.
 
  • #3
nobahar said:
Hello!

This is pretty much my first venture into this notation, and I was wondering if someone could help me with this:

∀x(Fx → ∀y(Fy → y=x))

As far as I am aware, ∀y(Fy → y=x) means for all y, whatever y you plug in, its domain is limited to x, so y is x, and f(y) is f(x): i.e. it limits y to 'being' x.
Something like (Fx & ∀y(Fy → y=x)) makes sense, because its basically saying F can only be over x: there is only one F, namely x; if we tried to introduce something else, ∀y(Fy → y=x) tells us that it has to be x, so it can't be anything else, only x.

If ∀y(Fy → y=x) = u

then what does ∀x(Fx → u) mean? There's no u = x, is it over a domain?, or is it saying if F(x) is true then u? In which case the same notation is saying different things, which apparently it can; but in this case without clarification that this is is happening.
Or is it saying something like: for all x: for F(x), y in F(y) is limited to being x, and that this is true for all y?

Hopefully that makes sense.
Any help appreciated!

What are the axioms or definitions for "=" ??
 
Last edited:
  • #4
nobahar said:
Hello!

This is pretty much my first venture into this notation, and I was wondering if someone could help me with this:

∀x(Fx → ∀y(Fy → y=x))

As far as I am aware, ∀y(Fy → y=x) means for all y, whatever y you plug in, its domain is limited to x, so y is x, and f(y) is f(x): i.e. it limits y to 'being' x.
Something like (Fx & ∀y(Fy → y=x)) makes sense, because its basically saying F can only be over x: there is only one F, namely x; if we tried to introduce something else, ∀y(Fy → y=x) tells us that it has to be x, so it can't be anything else, only x.

If ∀y(Fy → y=x) = u

then what does ∀x(Fx → u) mean? There's no u = x, is it over a domain?, or is it saying if F(x) is true then u? In which case the same notation is saying different things, which apparently it can; but in this case without clarification that this is is happening.
Or is it saying something like: for all x: for F(x), y in F(y) is limited to being x, and that this is true for all y?

Hopefully that makes sense.
Any help appreciated!

Let : Fx denote for example : x is a fish.Then using the axiom two different fish cannot be identical we can prove that:

∀x(Fx → ∀y(Fy → y=x)) is not true
 
  • #5
Thanks for the responses.

Here it is in 'context':

∃x(Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx)

So looking at this component, two requirements are made on x:

Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x)

The ∀y(Fy → y=x) component was the one we were addressing. I meant to say maps the domain of y onto the codomain x; but thinking about it, this doesn't make sense here, as you are not mapping y on to x; and the notation is not quite the same, although similar. It doesn't appear to be a Boolean valued function either, even though the notation again looks similar. What does the arrow denote here, exactly? What is it called?

So if you can plug in some y, which doesn't equal x, then ∀y(Fy → y=x) is not true and therefore the requirements that some x meets Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x) is not fulfilled; so the whole statement is false?

This would mean my understanding of what something like ∃x(Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx) is saying is false. I understood it to be stating something unchanging, that ∀y(Fy → y=x) 'states' that there is a unique F(x); instead, it appears as a function that can change and can be render the statement ∃x(Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx) true or false.
Do you see what I mean?:
In one understanding, my initial one, ∃x(Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx) says that there is some x such that it is uniquely F(x) becuase ∀y(Fy → y=x) means any y has to be x, so that F is limited to being x (i.e. it is unique).
In the second understanding, you are saying that a y can be plugged in that does not equal x, and so it renders the 'dynamic' statement ∃x(Fx [itex]\wedge[/itex] ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx) false because ∀y(Fy → y=x) is false. This is subtly different; since, although it restricts the values of y to x in order to render it true, it is a slightly different statement - a kind of dynamic statement. It's no longer saying explicitly that F(x) is unique, but says that, if y isn't equal to x, then the statement is false. Does that make sense? Admittedly, it seems to amount to the same thing, but I think there is a conceptual difference. In the second case its more dynamic; as you say, it can accept values for y not equal to x; rendering the statement false, but acceptable none the less. In the first it is saying you cannot even plug in values of y not equal to x, since they have to equal x.

Any further help appreciated.
 
  • #6
Hello nobahar
First, in ∃x(Fx ∧ ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx) what does ∧ mean if it is different than &? It looks like two different notations for conjunction so I'll assume the interpretation ∃x(Fx & ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx).

Ala Russell's 1905 paper "On Denoting", let's take F to be "is the king of France" and B to be "is bald". Then what ∃x(Fx & ∀y(Fy → y=x) & Bx) states is that
1. There is at least one king of France
2. There is at most one king of France
3. The thing that is the king of France is bald.
There are a number of ways in which this can be false, in particular:
1. It is false when there is no king of France
2. It is false when there are many kings of France
3. It is false when the king of France is not bald.

As for the string ∀y(Fy → y=x) = u. This is not typically considered well-formed. '=' must be flanked by terms.
 

What does the equation ∀x(Fx → ∀y(Fy → y=x)) mean?

The equation represents a logical statement that can be interpreted as "For all x, if x has property F, then for all y, if y has property F, then y is equal to x." Essentially, it is saying that if every object in a set has a certain property, then any two objects in that set must be equal.

How can this equation be solved?

This equation cannot be solved in the traditional sense, as it is a logical statement rather than a mathematical one. However, it can be analyzed and evaluated using logical methods and rules.

What is the purpose of this equation?

This equation is often used in mathematical logic to demonstrate the concept of universal instantiation and the principle of identity, which are important concepts in the study of logic and set theory.

Can you provide an example of how this equation can be applied?

For example, if we have a set of all even numbers (represented by Fx) and we take any two even numbers from this set (represented by y and x), the equation would hold true because both y and x have the property of being even and therefore must be equal.

Are there any practical applications for this equation?

While this equation may not have direct practical applications, the concepts it represents are important in fields such as computer science, mathematics, and philosophy. It can also be used to understand and analyze other logical statements and arguments.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
735
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
15
Views
998
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
4K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
12
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
5
Views
964
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
17
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
2
Replies
56
Views
2K
  • Introductory Physics Homework Help
Replies
13
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
9
Views
1K
Back
Top