- 8,695
- 4,758
A. Neumaier submitted a new PF Insights post
Causal Perturbation Theory
Continue reading the Original PF Insights Post.
Causal Perturbation Theory
Continue reading the Original PF Insights Post.
A. Neumaier said:But the perturbative expansion is not the whole story since there must be modifications in the IR, due to the fact that the physical electron is an infraparticle only.
A. Neumaier said:The physical electron in QED exists, but it is (like an electron in experiments, but unlike a - nonexistent - bare electron) inseparable from the electromagnetic field carried by its charge. This implies that the asymptotic states (which in perturbation theory are treated incorrectly as free Dirac states without a field) are in fact more complicated objects, called infraparticles. The latter exist in a far more real sense than the Dirac electrons. But their behavior is mathematically not fully understood. In a nonperturbative construction of QED, the infraparticle structure must be explicitly represented. This means that one would have to do perturbation theory starting in place of the Hilbert space of a free field with a Hilbert space featuring infraparticles instead. People have been trying to build such a Hilbert space but nobody so far has married it with a perturbative construction in the spirit of causal perturbation theory - except in case of an electron in an external electromagnetic field, which is already quite technical.
(Described in terms of bare stuff - which is frequently done though it is meaningless imagery - the infraparticle consists of a virtual bare electron plus a cloud of infinitely many virtual soft photons; this is manifested in traditional S-matrix calculations by summing over corresponding outgoing states to remove the IR divergences.)
A. Neumaier said:The physical electron in QED exists, but it is (like an electron in experiments, but unlike a - nonexistent - bare electron) inseparable from the electromagnetic field carried by its charge. This implies that the asymptotic states (which in perturbation theory are treated incorrectly as free Dirac states without a field) are in fact more complicated objects, called infraparticles. The latter exist in a far more real sense than the Dirac electrons. But their behavior is mathematically not fully understood.
>>>>>>
(Described in terms of bare stuff - which is frequently done though it is meaningless imagery - the infraparticle consists of a virtual bare electron plus a cloud of infinitely many virtual soft photons; this is manifested in traditional S-matrix calculations by summing over corresponding outgoing states to remove the IR divergences.)
You don't understand correctly. Both the electromagnetic field and the electron currents are real (measurable), photons are elementary excitations of the electromagnetic field, and electrons are elementary excitation of the electron current field, hence are as real. But they are not bare - the bare photons and electrons are meaningless auxiliary constructs that do not survive the renormalization limit.Feeble Wonk said:So, if I understand correctly, you are saying that the (bare) electron itself is a meaningless concept. According to the theory, the EM field is what is "real", and the electron is just a localized description of the field. Is that accurate?
Real in theoretical physics is what is gauge invariant, has a well-defined dynamics in time (since reality happens in time), approximates a real world situation (it is always to some extent an idealization).vanhees71 said:I don't know, what you mean by "real". It's a very confusing word
The whole construction happens in the asymptotic space, which even for an interacting theory is a Fock space, since asymptotic particles are free by definition. In Fock space, normal ordering is all that is required to render a polynomial, local operator meaningful. Thus you can start the induction with an arbitrary local polynomial in c/a operators.philosophus said:I do not understand the start of induction, unless some renormalization is hidden here to define the normal ordered power of the free fields
Is there a typo or omission in the last sentence of this paragraph:A. Neumaier said:In the light of the recent discussion starting here, I updated this Insight article, adding in particular detail to the section ''Axioms for causal quantum field theory''.
?Unfortunately, models proving that QED (or other interacting local quantum field theories) exists have not yet been constructed. On the other hand, there are also no arguments proving rigorously that such models exist. For a fully rigorous solution – a problem which for interacting 4-dimensional relativistic quantum field theories is open.
Thanks for pointing it out. Indeed, the paragraph was garbled. I corrected it and added some more information. Now the paragraph readsstrangerep said:Is there a typo or omission in the last sentence of this paragraph:
?
Unfortunately, models proving that QED (or another interacting local quantum field theory in 4 spacetime dimensions) exists have not yet been constructed. On the other hand, constructions are available in 2 and 3 spacetime dimensions, and no arguments are known proving rigorously that such models cannot exist in 4 dimensions. Finding a fully rigorous construction for an interacting 4-dimensional local quantum field theory or proving that it cannot exist is therefore a widely open problem. My bet is that a rigorous construction of QED will be found one day.
A. Neumaier said:However, the whole procedure makes perturbative sense also without these requirements.
In particular, for quantum field theory in curved space-time one sacrifices condition 1, with success; see work by Stefan Hollands.
Yes, it is different. Hollands is not doing causal perturbation theory since, as I said, in his work condition 1 (i.e., covariance) is sacrificed, by using a cutoff.atyy said:Which papers of Stefan Hollands? I took a quick look at https://arxiv.org/abs/1105.3375 which introduces an ultraviolet cutoff, then takes it to infinity, so it seems a bit different from causal perturbation theory which "nowhere introduces nonphysical entities (such as cutoffs, bare coupling constants, bare particles or virtual particles)".
It is generally used; I am not responsible for the name. I think it is called causal since causality dictates the axioms and the derived conditions for the distribution splitting.Tendex said:isn't referring to it as a "Causal theory" a bit of a misnomer?
Of course; I never claimed anything else. By making approximations, any computational scheme necessarily truncates the theory and hence violates locality. This even holds in 2D and 3D, where local QFTs have been constructed rigorously but computations still need to employ approximations.Tendex said:validity only term by term is quite a "truncation" of the theory
The complete, infinite order construction satisfies all axioms, and hence the local commutation rules, in the sense of formal power series. In this sense it is closer to nonperturbative local QFT.Tendex said:not constructing any theory that gets us closer to the nonperturbative local QFT.
Old perturbation theory only defines the perturbative S-matrix, but not the operators, and hence not the finite time dynamics. Thus it lacks much of what makes a quantum theory well-defined.Tendex said:if one assumes from the start the existence of the non-perturbative local QFT(this is what Dyson and Feynman did), this seems to me like an empty exercise in rigor and old perturbation theory was fine
This is a valid comparison. Indeed, the Riemann hypohesis, global existence of solutions of the the Navier-Stokes equations, and the construction of an interacting local QFT in 4D are three of the 6 open MIllnium problems. They share the fact that numerically, everything of interest is established without doubt but the mathematical techniques to produce rigorous arguments are not sufficiently developed to lead to success on this level.Tendex said:Perhaps an appropriate mathematical analogy is with numerical brute force searches of Riemann hypothesis zeros outside the critical line, that always remain equally infinitely far from confirming the hypothesis.
I had already answered this:vanhees71 said:What else do you gain in (vacuum) QFT than the S-matrix?
I think the name ''microcausality'' for the spacelike commutation rule, though quite common, is the real misnomer. The commutation rule is rather characteristic of locality (''experiments at the same time but different places can be independently prepared'') , as indicated by the title of Haag's book. Locality is intrinsically based on spacelike commutation and cannot be discussed without it or directly equivalent properties.Tendex said:not an exactly or completely causal (in the sense of microcausal) theory due to its perturbative limitations, isn't referring to it as a "Causal theory" a bit of a misnomer? I know there are historical reasons starting with the work of Bogoliubov and I guess that it refers to the global causality of asymptotic states rather than to the "in principle" exact (micro)causality usually explained in regular QFT textbooks when explaining the locality axiom
Scharf's QED is finite order by order, just as causal perturbation theory is causal order by order. Since Scharf does not produce finite results in the limit of infinite order you should complain against the appropriateness of the label ''finite'' with the same force as you complain against the label ''causal'' in causal perturbation theory.Tendex said:maybe that's why the title of Scharf's book uses first the less confusing phrase "Finite QED".
Yes, that's formally clear. What I don't see is what you gain physics wise. What is the physical observable related to finite-time dynamics. I also don't understand, why you say that in standard PT you don't get Wightman functions. Of course you can calculate them perturbatively within the usual formalism.A. Neumaier said:I had already answered this:
BPHZ perturbation theory, say, only defines the perturbative S-matrix, but neither operators nor Wightman N-point functions, and hence no finite time dynamics. Moreover nothing for states different from the ground states. Thus it lacks much of what makes a quantum theory well-defined. Quite independent of what can be measured.
For comparison, if all that ordinary quantum mechanics could compute for a few particle system were its ground state and the S-matrix, we would have the status quo of 1928, very far from the current state of the art in few particle quantum mechanics.
What do you man? The Hamiltonian together with the Schrödinger equation tell how a state changes in a finite time. But in the textbook formalism, the Hamiltonian comes out infinite and cannot be used.vanhees71 said:Yes, that's formally clear. What I don't see is what you gain physics wise. What is the physical observable related to finite-time dynamics.
The textbook formalism only gives the time-ordered N-point functions. How do you time-unorder them?vanhees71 said:I also don't understand, why you say that in standard PT you don't get Wightman functions. Of course you can calculate them perturbatively within the usual formalism.
If you are only interested in the interpretation of collision experiments, nothing. But if you want to do simulations in time of what happens, you need it. You are doing such simulations, so it is strange why you ask.vanhees71 said:The question is what I gain from finite-time states in QFT.
But there is no Dyson series for them, so Feynman rules cannot be derived in the textbook way.vanhees71 said:The "fixed-ordered Wightman functions" should be calculable by deriving the corresponding Feynman rules for them
I basically agree with the above. There is a degree of mixing between the different terms in certain contexts though. In the free theory like in the classical you mention there is a causality and microcausality trivial overlapping, that relativistically is reinforced by the symmetries that include time reversals and spacetime translations, the latter is also in the putative non-perturbative local QFT. There you have the triad of Poincaré covariance, locality and unitarity inextricably united through the analytic dispersion relations extended from the Kramers relations to the whole complex plane.A. Neumaier said:I think the name ''microcausality'' for the spacelike commutation rule, though quite common, is the real misnomer. The commutation rule is rather characteristic of locality (''experiments at the same time but different places can be independently prepared'') , as indicated by the title of Haag's book. Locality is intrinsically based on spacelike commutation and cannot be discussed without it or directly equivalent properties.
On the other hand, the relation between causality and spacelike commutation is indirect, restricted to relativistic QFT. Moreover, the relation works only in one direction since spacelike commutation requires a notion fo causality for its definition, while causality can be discussed easily without spacelike commutation.
Indeed, causality (''the future does not affect the past'') is conceptually most related to dispersion relations (where causal arguments enter in an essential way throughout quantum mechanics, even in the nonrelativistic case) and to Lorentz invariance (already in classical mechanics where ''microcausality'' is trivially valid). Both figure very prominently in causal perturbation theory.
Well, I think I complained about the concepts behind it(which is what I care about) enough in other threads to get my point across. My comment as I said was purely about the word "causal" and its connotations and conflation with locality and (micro)causality that are known to create endless confusions in Bell-like discussions.Scharf's QED is finite order by order, just as causal perturbation theory is causal order by order. Since Scharf does not produce finite results in the limit of infinite order you should complain against the appropriateness of the label ''finite'' with the same force as you complain against the label ''causal'' in causal perturbation theory.
Yes, but he had asked what can be computed from approximate field operators that are not accessible by standard perturbative theory. I gave as examples the unordered N-point correlation functions. These are defined independent of the Wightman axioms; the latter just specify their desired covariance and laocality conditions.Tendex said:Wightman propagators obviously belong to the axiomatic QFT proposal, I guess by what you get with "the standard perturbative theory" vanhees71 refers to the plain Feynman propagator.
It is a physically motivated renormarization scheme replacing old-fashioned QFT, making regularization unnecessary. Why should one still want to regularize?HomogenousCow said:Since CPT is UV-complete, does it suggest a physically motivated regularization scheme for old-fashioned QFT?
Yes, I'm doing simulations what's going on in heavy-ion collisions, but it's far from the claim that you have a physical interpretation of "transient states". Take, e.g., the calculations I've done for dilepton production, i.e., the production of ##\text{e}^+ \text{e}^-##- and ##\mu^+ \mu^-##-pairs from a hot and dense strongly interacting medium.A. Neumaier said:If you are only interested in the interpretation of collision experiments, nothing. But if you want to do simulations in time of what happens, you need it. You are doing such simulations, so it is strange why you ask.
As you well know, this goes far beyond BPHZ, which is the textbook material that was under discussion above. Simulations in time are usually done with the CTP formalism, which can produce all required information in a nonperturbative way, given some pertubatively computed input.
The latter must be renormalized, which is done in an a nonrigorous hoc way. Presumably it can be placed on a more rigorous basis by using the causal techniques.
This may even resolve some of the causality issues reported in the CTP literature. (This was maybe around 10 years ago; I haven't followed it up, are these problems satisfactorily resolved by now?)