MHB Well Orders and Total Orders .... Searcoid Definition 1.3.10 ....

  • Thread starter Thread starter Math Amateur
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Definition
Math Amateur
Gold Member
MHB
Messages
3,920
Reaction score
48
I am reading Micheal Searcoid's book: "Elements of Abstract Analysis" ... ...

I am currently focused on understanding Chapter 1: Sets ... and in particular Section 1.3 Ordered Sets ...

I need some help in fully understanding some remarks by Searcoid following Definition 1.3.10 ...

Definition 1.3.10 and the remarks following read as follows:
View attachment 8427
View attachment 8428In Searcoid's remarks following Definition 1.3.10 we read the following ...

"... ... every well ordered set is totally ordered ... ... Can someone please help me to prove that every well ordered set is totally ordered ... ...Help will be appreciated ...

Peter

=======================================================================

It may help MHB memebers reading the above post to have access to Definition 1.3.4 ... so I am providing access to the same ... as follows ...
View attachment 8429
Hope that helps ...

Peter
 

Attachments

  • Searcoid - Definition 1.3.10 ... .....png
    Searcoid - Definition 1.3.10 ... .....png
    9 KB · Views: 124
  • Searcoid - 2 - Definition 1.3.10 ... .....PART 2 ... ....png
    Searcoid - 2 - Definition 1.3.10 ... .....PART 2 ... ....png
    9.1 KB · Views: 136
  • Searcoid - Definition 1.3.4 ... ....png
    Searcoid - Definition 1.3.4 ... ....png
    28.5 KB · Views: 118
Physics news on Phys.org
Hi Peter,

You just have to apply the definition to subsets of two elements.

More explicitly, if $S$ is well ordered and $\{x,y\}\subset S$ with $x\ne y$, then $\{x,y\}$ has a smallest element. If that element is $x$, then $x<y$; if that element is $y$, then $y<x$.
 
castor28 said:
Hi Peter,

You just have to apply the definition to subsets of two elements.

More explicitly, if $S$ is well ordered and $\{x,y\}\subset S$ with $x\ne y$, then $\{x,y\}$ has a smallest element. If that element is $x$, then $x<y$; if that element is $y$, then $y<x$.

Sorry to butt in.. But what if $S$ is singleton? They also have a minimum value since no number is greater than itself (...). How do we compare it to a totally ordered set which (seems to) require at least two elements?

edit: i.e. if it doesn't make sense consider a totally ordered set which is singleton, how can we say all well ordered sets are totally ordered? (I'm assuming we can't and that I've missed a definition or am thinking something really silly)..
 
Joppy said:
Sorry to butt in.. But what if $S$ is singleton? They also have a minimum value since no number is greater than itself (...). How do we compare it to a totally ordered set which (seems to) require at least two elements?

edit: i.e. if it doesn't make sense consider a totally ordered set which is singleton, how can we say all well ordered sets are totally ordered? (I'm assuming we can't and that I've missed a definition or am thinking something really silly)..
Hi Joppy,

A singleton set is totally ordered, because the definition is vacuously true.

The definition of a totally ordered set $S$ is equivalent to: if $\{x,y\}\subset S$ and $x\ne y$, then $x<y$ or $y<x$.

If $S$ is a singleton, the condition $x\ne y$ is always false. As the antecedent of the implication is false, the implication itself (the definition) is true.

Note that it is quite common to define an order relation as a reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive relation (like $\le$), and to modify the definitions accordingly. In that case, things are a little simpler.
 
Hi all, I've been a roulette player for more than 10 years (although I took time off here and there) and it's only now that I'm trying to understand the physics of the game. Basically my strategy in roulette is to divide the wheel roughly into two halves (let's call them A and B). My theory is that in roulette there will invariably be variance. In other words, if A comes up 5 times in a row, B will be due to come up soon. However I have been proven wrong many times, and I have seen some...
Thread 'Detail of Diagonalization Lemma'
The following is more or less taken from page 6 of C. Smorynski's "Self-Reference and Modal Logic". (Springer, 1985) (I couldn't get raised brackets to indicate codification (Gödel numbering), so I use a box. The overline is assigning a name. The detail I would like clarification on is in the second step in the last line, where we have an m-overlined, and we substitute the expression for m. Are we saying that the name of a coded term is the same as the coded term? Thanks in advance.
Back
Top