vanesch
Staff Emeritus
Science Advisor
Gold Member
- 5,109
- 20
I will now, based upon my first calculation, show how this is related to a Copenhagen view of things.
We had, at t1, the measurement of Bob ; this can partly be done again with the unitary evolution operator, but (if we apply the Heisenberg cut at the level of "Bob"):
With 50% chance, bob is bob+, and we have then (after renormalization):
|psi(t1+)> = - sin(thb)/sqrt(2) |alice0> |bob+> |cable0> |z+> |sys0>
- cos(thb)/sqrt(2) |alice0> |bob+> |cable0> |z-> |sys0>
(and with 50% chance, we had bob- and another state which I won't write out).
HERE YOU SEE THE NON-LOCALITY AT WORK.
Indeed, the decision to go to the bob+ state affected immediately the amount of |z+> and |z-> (the Alice particle) in the state !
This wasn't the case when we kept the entire state |psi(t1)>: you can verify that the total length of the vector containing |z+> was still 50% in that case.
So the mechanism of the projection introduces the non-locality, in that the length of tensor product components (hilbert spaces of remote components) has suddenly changed. The evolution with Alice will be similar, but the main EPR effect occurred right here, in the Copenhagen view.
Alice's measurement:
from t1 to t2, Alice measures system 1 along direction th_a, so we have
an evolution operator U_a which acts:
U_a |alice0> |tha+> -> |alice+>|sys0>
U_a |alice0> |tha-> -> |alice->|sys0>
U_a acts only on H_alice x H_sys1
Rewriting psi(t1+):
|psi(t1+)> = - sin(thb)|alice0>|bob+>|cable0>(cos(tha) |tha+> + sin(tha) |tha->)|sys0>
- cos(thb) |alice0>|bob+>|cable0>(-sin(tha) |tha+> + cos(tha) |tha->)|sys0>
and applying U_a:
|psi(t2)> = - sin(thb) cos(tha)|alice+>|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
- sin(thb) sin(tha)|alice->|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
+ cos(thb) sin(tha)|alice+>|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
- cos(thb) cos(tha)|alice->|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
or:
|psi(t2)> = {(-sin(thb) cos(tha) + cos(thb) sin(tha) ) |alice+>|bob+>
+(-sin(thb) sin(tha) - cos(thb) cos(tha) ) |alice->|bob+>}|cable0> |sys0>|sys0>
or:
|psi(t2)> = { sin(tha-thb) |alice+> |bob+>
-cos(tha-thb) |alice-> |bob+>} |cable0> |sys0>|sys0>
After this measurement, again we have to use the projection postulate: with sin^2(tha-thb) probability, alice will have measured a + state (we already know bob had a + state and this is taken into account: we have here a conditional probability for alice), and the state will be, after normalization:
|psi(t2+)> = |alice+>|bob+> |cable0> |sys0>|sys0>
The whole "mystery" resides then in 2 things:
1) what about this non-locality ? Clearly it is contained in the quantum formalism (a la Copenhagen) and clearly also it doesn't correspond to any specific dynamics. One cannot say that it is "due to a force yet to be discovered", because it *is* already present in the formalism, and it is NOT some dynamics of unknown sort.
2) How does it come that Bob changes the states in such a way at Alice's that a) this directly influences the probabilities of outcomes Alice will observe, but b) that the mixture of influences that Bob prepares for Alice (when repeating the experiment) is exactly such, that, when weighting with Bob's mixture of outcomes, Alice finds finally a 50/50 probability AS IF Bob didn't influence her stuff. That, to me, sounds like a serious conspiracy :-)
It is here that I see a certain superiority of the MWI view: we know why this has to remain 50/50 because after the unitary evolution at Bob, the length of the vectors at Alice weren't influenced.
cheers,
Patrick.
We had, at t1, the measurement of Bob ; this can partly be done again with the unitary evolution operator, but (if we apply the Heisenberg cut at the level of "Bob"):
we have to apply the projection postulate now.vanesch said:This means that a time evolution operator U_b acts,
such that:
U_b |bob0> |thb+> -> |bob+> |sys0>
U_b |bob0> |thb-> -> |bob-> |sys0>
U_b acting only on H_bob x H_sys2.
Rewriting psi(t0):
|psi(t0)> = |alice0>|bob0>|cable0>(|z+>(-sin(thb) |thb+> + cos(thb) |thb->) -
|z->( cos(thb) |thb+> + sin(thb) |thb->) )/sqrt(2)
Applying U_b
|psi(t1)> = {- sin(thb)|alice0>|bob+>|cable0>|z+>|sys0>
+ cos(thb) |alice0>|bob->|cable0>|z+>|sys0>
- cos(thb) |alice0>|bob+>|cable0>|z->|sys0>
- sin(thb) |alice0>|bob->|cable0>|z->|sys0>}/sqrt(2)
With 50% chance, bob is bob+, and we have then (after renormalization):
|psi(t1+)> = - sin(thb)/sqrt(2) |alice0> |bob+> |cable0> |z+> |sys0>
- cos(thb)/sqrt(2) |alice0> |bob+> |cable0> |z-> |sys0>
(and with 50% chance, we had bob- and another state which I won't write out).
HERE YOU SEE THE NON-LOCALITY AT WORK.
Indeed, the decision to go to the bob+ state affected immediately the amount of |z+> and |z-> (the Alice particle) in the state !
This wasn't the case when we kept the entire state |psi(t1)>: you can verify that the total length of the vector containing |z+> was still 50% in that case.
So the mechanism of the projection introduces the non-locality, in that the length of tensor product components (hilbert spaces of remote components) has suddenly changed. The evolution with Alice will be similar, but the main EPR effect occurred right here, in the Copenhagen view.
Alice's measurement:
from t1 to t2, Alice measures system 1 along direction th_a, so we have
an evolution operator U_a which acts:
U_a |alice0> |tha+> -> |alice+>|sys0>
U_a |alice0> |tha-> -> |alice->|sys0>
U_a acts only on H_alice x H_sys1
Rewriting psi(t1+):
|psi(t1+)> = - sin(thb)|alice0>|bob+>|cable0>(cos(tha) |tha+> + sin(tha) |tha->)|sys0>
- cos(thb) |alice0>|bob+>|cable0>(-sin(tha) |tha+> + cos(tha) |tha->)|sys0>
and applying U_a:
|psi(t2)> = - sin(thb) cos(tha)|alice+>|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
- sin(thb) sin(tha)|alice->|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
+ cos(thb) sin(tha)|alice+>|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
- cos(thb) cos(tha)|alice->|bob+>|cable0> |sys0> |sys0>
or:
|psi(t2)> = {(-sin(thb) cos(tha) + cos(thb) sin(tha) ) |alice+>|bob+>
+(-sin(thb) sin(tha) - cos(thb) cos(tha) ) |alice->|bob+>}|cable0> |sys0>|sys0>
or:
|psi(t2)> = { sin(tha-thb) |alice+> |bob+>
-cos(tha-thb) |alice-> |bob+>} |cable0> |sys0>|sys0>
After this measurement, again we have to use the projection postulate: with sin^2(tha-thb) probability, alice will have measured a + state (we already know bob had a + state and this is taken into account: we have here a conditional probability for alice), and the state will be, after normalization:
|psi(t2+)> = |alice+>|bob+> |cable0> |sys0>|sys0>
The whole "mystery" resides then in 2 things:
1) what about this non-locality ? Clearly it is contained in the quantum formalism (a la Copenhagen) and clearly also it doesn't correspond to any specific dynamics. One cannot say that it is "due to a force yet to be discovered", because it *is* already present in the formalism, and it is NOT some dynamics of unknown sort.
2) How does it come that Bob changes the states in such a way at Alice's that a) this directly influences the probabilities of outcomes Alice will observe, but b) that the mixture of influences that Bob prepares for Alice (when repeating the experiment) is exactly such, that, when weighting with Bob's mixture of outcomes, Alice finds finally a 50/50 probability AS IF Bob didn't influence her stuff. That, to me, sounds like a serious conspiracy :-)
It is here that I see a certain superiority of the MWI view: we know why this has to remain 50/50 because after the unitary evolution at Bob, the length of the vectors at Alice weren't influenced.
cheers,
Patrick.