B How Does Environmentally Induced Decoherence Affect Quantum State Reduction?

  • B
  • Thread starter Thread starter Feeble Wonk
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Decoherence
  • #151
rubi said:
Well, I believe that experimenters can provide us with a bunch of numbers, but I don't really commit to anything beyond that. Apparently, something is really odd about nature, since the idea that we can assign numbers to all properties of its parts in a consistent way must be given up, and I have no idea what that implies for the interpretation of the measurement results. This is of course an interesting philosophical question, but physicists must accept it as a fact, just like they must accept the constancy of the speed of light.

So you still have a cut - why do you think this is different from the Heisenberg cut you reject?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #152
atyy said:
So you still have a cut - why do you think this is different from the Heisenberg cut you reject?
I don't have a cut. It would be consistent with QM if the present me believes to have measured a bunch of numbers and the future me concludes that the present me was in a superposition of having measured one set of numbers and another set of numbers. That can happen if the observables that correspond to the knowledge of the present me and the future me don't commute. Hopefully decoherence comes to the rescue and ensures that the present me and the future me don't disagree so much.
 
  • #153
rubi said:
I don't have a cut. It would be consistent with QM if the present me believes to have measured a bunch of numbers and the future me concludes that the present me was in a superposition of having measured one set of numbers and another set of numbers. That can happen if the observables that correspond to the knowledge of the present me and the future me don't commute. Hopefully decoherence comes to the rescue and ensures that the present me and the future me don't disagree so much.

Why doesn't the present you believe yourself to be in a superposition?
 
  • #154
rubi said:
I don't have a cut. It would be consistent with QM if the present me believes to have measured a bunch of numbers and the future me concludes that the present me was in a superposition of having measured one set of numbers and another set of numbers. That can happen if the observables that correspond to the knowledge of the present me and the future me don't commute. Hopefully decoherence comes to the rescue and ensures that the present me and the future me don't disagree so much.
[emoji15] Ouch. Wouldn't it require a cut between the multiple "present you(s)" to arrive at the single later you?
 
  • #155
atyy said:
Why doesn't the present you believe yourself to be in a superposition?
Let's assume I can be described by quantum mechanics as well, just as any other kind of matter in the universe. Let's work in the Heisenberg picture. There is a time-independent quantum state ##\Psi##. Let's assume for simplicity that my knowledge at time ##t## of the measurement results is encoded by a single observable ##X(t)## for every ##t##. It might be that ##\Psi## is an eigenstate of ##X(10)##: ##X(10)\Psi = x\Psi##. The information of the future me (##t=10##) about the measurement results is encoded in the real number ##x##. However, it might be that ##[X(0),X(10)]\neq 0##, so they don't share a common basis of (generalized) eigenvectors and thus the vector ##\Psi##, expanded in the eigenbasis of ##X(0)## might be given by a superposition ##\Psi=\sum a_i \phi_i##. Of course, if the ##X(t)## commute, this isn't an issue.
 
  • #156
rubi said:
Let's assume I can be described by quantum mechanics as well, just as any other kind of matter in the universe. Let's work in the Heisenberg picture. There is a time-independent quantum state ##\Psi##. Let's assume for simplicity that my knowledge at time ##t## of the measurement results is encoded by a single observable ##X(t)## for every ##t##. It might be that ##\Psi## is an eigenstate of ##X(10)##: ##X(10)\Psi = x\Psi##. The information of the future me (##t=10##) about the measurement results is encoded in the real number ##x##. However, it might be that ##[X(0),X(10)]\neq 0##, so they don't share a common basis of (generalized) eigenvectors and thus the vector ##\Psi##, expanded in the eigenbasis of ##X(0)## might be given by a superposition ##\Psi=\sum a_i \phi_i##. Of course, if the ##X(t)## commute, this isn't an issue.

Isn't that the reply for why your future self believes the present self to be in a superposition?

How does it explain why the present self believes the present self not to be in a superposition?
 
  • #157
Feeble Wonk said:
[emoji15] Ouch. Wouldn't it require a cut between the multiple "present you(s)" to arrive at the single later you?
I don't need a cut. I have a quantum state ##\Psi## and lots of observables that account for any question that I could ask. If some of these observables don't commute, then they can't have definite values at the same "time". Of course, it's very uncommon to include actual physicists into the description of the quantum system.
 
  • #158
atyy said:
Isn't that the reply for why your future self believes the present self to be in a superposition?

How does it explain why the present self believes the present self not to be in a superposition?
It doesn't explain anything. It just describes it. As I said earlier, I have no idea how to interpret the fact that nature prohibits us to describe it using a bunch of numbers that can be known simultaneously. I'm just saying that it is internally consistent, although it may seem pretty weird sometimes. QM has made many weird predictions in the past and all of them have been shown to be consistent with experiments.
 
  • #159
rubi said:
It doesn't explain anything. It just describes it. As I said earlier, I have no idea how to interpret the fact that nature prohibits us to describe it using a bunch of numbers that can be known simultaneously. I'm just saying that it is internally consistent, although it may seem pretty weird sometimes. QM has made many weird predictions in the past and all of them have been shown to be consistent with experiments.

No, I don't mean "explain" in that sense. I would like to know where in the formalism it says that the present self believes itself not to be in a superposition.
 
  • #160
atyy said:
No, I don't mean "explain" in that sense. I would like to know where in the formalism it says that the present self believes itself not to be in a superposition.
It doesn't need to believe that. The formalism says that the present me will use one of of the eigenvalues of ##X(0)## correpsonding to the eigenvectors ##\phi_i## as the information about the measurement results and if I were to repeat this experiment many times, this choice will be distributed according to the probabilities ##|a_i|^2##.
 
  • #161
rubi said:
It doesn't need to believe that. The formalism says that the present me will use one of of the eigenvalues of ##X(0)## correpsonding to the eigenvectors ##\phi_i## as the information about the measurement results and if I were to repeat this experiment many times, this choice will be distributed according to the probabilities ##|a_i|^2##.

But you never actually get a measurement result, do you? At least not from the viewpoint of future you?
 
  • #162
atyy said:
But you never actually get a measurement result, do you? At least not from the viewpoint of future you?
The observables ##X(t)## encode my knowledge of the measurement results. The measurement results themselves are contained in an observable ##A## corresponding the the apparatus. At every point in time, I believe to have obtained a measurement result. Quantum theory doesn't predict, which one. It's just that this knowledge isn't consistent over time unless the observables commute (which is hopefully ensured by decoherence).

---
By the way, I'm not convinced that the domain of applicability of QM extends to such scenarios, but one can pretend it does and see what follows from it. In principle, the matter that consitutes the physicist should be governed by the same laws as the rest of the universe and the knowledge of the physicist should somehow be encoded in the motion of the particles in his brain, so in principle it should be possible to eliminate the cut completely. Of course, this is nowhere near practical. In quantum gravity, such considerations are forced upon us, because we are dealing with a fully constrained Hamiltonian system and all physics is supposed to arise from looking at correlations.
 
Last edited:
  • #163
If we consider that we have |dead><dead| and|alive><alive| can we get an inner composition law thar generalises the superposition law?
bhobba said:
That's impossible - utterly impossible. A cat can never - never be alive and dead. Cats are decohered to have definite position. The position of the constituent parts of a cat are different for alive and dead cats.

The sum of |dead><dead| and|alive><alive| is diagonal . Why are you talking about dead AND alive?
Did you read the link to Manko's paper?
 
  • #164
rubi said:
In principle, the matter that consitutes the physicist should be governed by the same laws as the rest of the universe and the knowledge of the physicist should somehow be encoded in the motion of the particles in his brain, so in principle it should be possible to eliminate the cut completely.
I'm clearly missing something critical here. My understanding was that the "warm and noisy" environment of the brain essentially guarantees decoherence and associated state reduction.
Regardless of your interpretational preference, I'm still confused by the idea that the "post-observation" physicist could retrospectively view his brain as being in superposition (with respect to the observation outcome) at the time of observation.
How does this differ from opening the box and seeing whether the cat is dead or alive, then closing the box and claiming that it's state is still unknown?
 
Last edited:
  • #165
A. Neumaier said:
Unitary dynamics for small quantum systems is extremely well disproved - people in quantum optics always have to work with dissipative, nonunitary dynamics to describe their small systems quantitatively. Thus it is an experimental fact that small quantum systems cannot be described by unitary evolution.
The reason is that they are almost never isolated enough to justify the unitary approximation. The state reduction or collapse accounts for that.

On the other hand, if one makes a quantum system big enough that its interaction with the neglected environment can be ignored (which is often the case in macroscopic situations) or can be described by classical external interaction terms then unitary dynamics is valid to a very good approximation.

Thus state reduction (= collapse) is not in contradiction with the unitary dynamics of an isolated system.
Thanks. But the question is, what do we mean by an "isolated system"? Standard approaches cannot explain what gives rise to non-unitary collapse. Under TI, unitary dynamics takes place in the absence of responses from absorbing systems. As soon as you have absorber response, you get the non-unitary von Neumann measurement transition.
I've provided a quantitative (albeit fundamentally indeterministic) criterion for the conditions under which this occurs--basically, these are decay probabilities. (See http://arxiv.org/abs/1411.2072 for the basic idea and relevant references)
 
  • #166
Just to make clear:
From decoherence you get what looks like classical probabilities. However, as stated in 'Quantum Enigma' they are NOT probabilities of something that actually exists. Decoherence is simply the entanglement of quantum systems to the environment (system(s) + environment = 'system2'). You trace over the environment and you are left with mathematics describing -part- of 'system2'. So no cat, or pointer, or macroscopic object, has a definite position as a result of decoherence (as has been claimed), because 'system2' is still in superposition. All decoherence can show is 'apparent collapse'. Apparent collapse and definite observables (e.g. position) are two completely different things.

Addressing why we don't see macroscopic objects in superposition: clearly 'measurement' has taken place which is why we see an alive cat, as opposed to a dead cat. Where this measurement occurs is still in dispute. Technically there is an observable of system+apparatus+environment which can tell us whether those 3 are in superposition or not.
 
  • #167
bhobba said:
That I am not sure of.

Regarding Zurek it boils down to the typical modelling thing - there are hidden assumptions in Zurek for sure - but if they are 'benign' or not is the debate. An example is the decision theoretic approach of Wallace. I have read his book and its pretty tight if you accept using decision theory is a valid approach. For some (me include) its rather obvious - for others - it makes no sense. Personally I find Zurek just another interpretation - and not my favoured one.

Thanks
Bill
Did you see my discussion of Wallace's 'auxiliary condition' as ostensibly part of the 'bare' (Unitary-only) theory? http://arxiv.org/abs/1603.04845
That is not 'benign' in the sense that it presupposes the very quasi-classical separability that is supposedly being explained by 'decoherence'. The same goes for Zurek's basic assumptions of initially separable, localizable systems. They are putting in classicality to get classicality out.
They cannot help themselves to 'typical modeling' because they are claiming to demonstrate the emergence of the very conditions that permit us to identify separable systems in the lab--those that allow us to do the modeling in the first place. The most general quantum initial universe would have nonlocally entangled degrees of freedom with no way to identify a 'system of study' as distinct from the environment.
 
  • #168
naima said:
The sum of |dead><dead| and|alive><alive| is diagonal . Why are you talking about dead AND alive?

Because that is what was said with or without capitals. There is no sum of dead and alive - there is a density matrix with dead and alive on diagonals, but if that's what was meant then that's what should have been said.

No - I did not read the paper. How about you give a precis of it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #169
rkastner said:
Did you see my discussion of Wallace's 'auxiliary condition' as ostensibly part of the 'bare' (Unitary-only) theory? http://arxiv.org/abs/1603.04845

'However, classicality is implicitly contained in 2 and 3 through the partitioning of the universal degrees of freedom into separable, localized substructures interacting via Hamiltonians that do not re-entangle them, so (given U-O) one has to put in classicality to get classicality out'

That's the factorisation issue. Its a legit issue but as I have said many times far too much is made of it IMHO. We do the same thing in classical mechanics for example but no one jumps up an down about that.

That said I have read Wallaces book and he uses an approach based on histories that seems to bypass it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #170
naima said:
If we consider that we have |dead><dead| and|alive><alive| can we get an inner composition law thar generalises the superposition law?
Well, you can add them and if you properly normalize them, it corresponds to a statistical mixture of dead and alive.

Feeble Wonk said:
I'm clearly missing something critical here. My understanding was that the "warm and noisy" environment of the brain essentially guarantees decoherence and associated state reduction.
Yes, the brain is a pretty classical object and there should be a lot of decoherence. That's why the phenomenon I described should be very unlikely. State reduction is only apparent, but that doesn't cause problems, since the relative frequencies predicted by state reduction and apparent state reduction are the same and only those are observable.

Regardless of your interpretational preference, I'm still confused by the idea that the "post-observation" physicist could retrospectively view his brain as being in superposition (with respect to the observation outcome) at the time of observation.
How does this differ from opening the box and seeing whether the cat is dead or alive, then closing the box and claiming that it's state is still unknown?
It doesn't differ. It's the same phenomenon as in the Schrödinger cat experiment, but now applied to physicists at different times. In both situations, decoherence is supposed to account for the observed classicality.
 
  • #171
rubi said:
Well, you can add them and if you properly normalize them, it corresponds to a statistical mixture of dead and alive.

Bhobba did not read the manko paper. Did you?
Manko gives a recipe to get all the ways to "add" the density matrices. the first is to add rhe density matrices. another corresponds to add the vectors. And between them you have other inner composition laws with various fringe visibility.
He uses a trick to manage the phases.
The week end is coming. Take the time to read it!
arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0207033

Abstract
An addition rule of impure density operators, which provides a pure state density operator, is for-
mulated. Quantum interference including visibility property is discussed in the context of the density
operator formalism. A measure of entanglement is then introduced as the norm of the matrix equal to
the difference between a bipartite density matrix and the tensor product of partial traces. Entanglement
for arbitrary quantum observables for multipartite systems is discussed. Star-product kernels are used
to map the formulation of the addition rule of density operators onto the addition rule of symbols of the
operators. Entanglement and nonlocalization of the pure state projector and allied operators are dis-
cussed. Tomographic and Weyl symbols (tomograms and Wigner functions) are considered as examples.
The squeezed-states and some spin-states (two qubits) are studied to illustrate the formalism.
 
Last edited:
  • #172
rubi said:
The observables ##X(t)## encode my knowledge of the measurement results. The measurement results themselves are contained in an observable ##A## corresponding the the apparatus. At every point in time, I believe to have obtained a measurement result. Quantum theory doesn't predict, which one. It's just that this knowledge isn't consistent over time unless the observables commute (which is hopefully ensured by decoherence).

---
By the way, I'm not convinced that the domain of applicability of QM extends to such scenarios, but one can pretend it does and see what follows from it. In principle, the matter that consitutes the physicist should be governed by the same laws as the rest of the universe and the knowledge of the physicist should somehow be encoded in the motion of the particles in his brain, so in principle it should be possible to eliminate the cut completely. Of course, this is nowhere near practical. In quantum gravity, such considerations are forced upon us, because we are dealing with a fully constrained Hamiltonian system and all physics is supposed to arise from looking at correlations.

I don't think you have gotten rid of the cut, since you still refer to your "knowledge of the measurement results". So you need the concept of something which can have knowledge, by which you presumably don't include a single electron.
 
  • #173
naima said:
Bhobba did not read the manko paper. Did you?
Manko gives a recipe to get all the ways to "add" the density matrices. the first is to add rhe density matrices. another corresponds to add the vectors. And between them you have other inner composition laws with various fringe visibility.
He uses a trick to manage the phases.
The week end is coming. Take the time to read it!
arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0207033
I understand that he proposes additional ways to add density matrices and it might be useful in some situations, but I don't see how it is relevant to the interpretation of QM. A density matrix contains the information about all probability distributions of the observables, but in order to obtain these distributions, it doesn't matter where this density matrix came from.

atyy said:
I don't think you have gotten rid of the cut, since you still refer to your "knowledge of the measurement results". So you need the concept of something which can have knowledge, by which you presumably don't include a single electron.
Well, I put all matter on the quantum side, so there is nothing left on the "other side of the cut". The "knowledge of the measurement results" is just my way to avoid having to explain how information is encoded in the brain. As a toy model, we could certainly assume that the information about a spin measurement is encoded in the spin of a certain electron within some neuron. Light rays are reflected from the pointer of the measurement apparatus and hit the eye of the physicist. The matter of the eyes interacts with the brain matter and the brain might eventually store the information in the spin of some electron. This is almost certainly not how it works, but I'm not a neuroscientist and modeling the realistic way of how information is stored within the brain just makes the model more complex, but not conceptually different. The point is that if all matter in the universe is described on the quantum side, then nothing remains on the classical side, so there is no Heisenberg cut.
 
  • #174
rubi said:
I understand that he proposes additional ways to add density matrices and it might be useful in some situations, but I don't see how it is relevant to the interpretation of QM. A density matrix contains the information about all probability distributions of the observables, but in order to obtain these distributions, it doesn't matter where this density matrix came from.

When i began to work as a programmer we had languages like cobol, ibm assembly and so on. They used "goto" or 'branch" to a labelled line in the program. Several years later no programmer used them. we replaced them by sub programs. Of course one could find them deep in the internal machine language.

When i began to learn QM the situation was similar. Probalilities or densities of probabilities were associated to transition from one vector in a Hilbert spacesto another vector.
Many years later we began to speak in the language of POVM. the probabilities were associated now to operators. On began to think that a beam splitter receives an operator from a channel and gives two output operators. We can follow these operators along the branches of the devices just like we followed the vectors with amplitude ans phases. At the end a click will tell us which POVM was chosen by Nature.
As i told it in another post I had a doubt: Can we completely avoid addition of vectors (our "goto") to describe the details of the devices? Can we avoid the Kraus operators? When two branches meet can we describe the output only with density matrices?
It seem than Manko gives a yes answer.
The fringes visiblity is a parameter in his formula. It tells if have pure state or decohered state to "add". In the ancient language if we have to add probabilities or amplitudes of probabilities.

I know that we can go on to decompose everything in term of vectors, to add them, to square them, to multiply each case by a probability, to add them again. It works very well. But...
 
  • #175
rubi said:
Well, I put all matter on the quantum side, so there is nothing left on the "other side of the cut". The "knowledge of the measurement results" is just my way to avoid having to explain how information is encoded in the brain. As a toy model, we could certainly assume that the information about a spin measurement is encoded in the spin of a certain electron within some neuron. Light rays are reflected from the pointer of the measurement apparatus and hit the eye of the physicist. The matter of the eyes interacts with the brain matter and the brain might eventually store the information in the spin of some electron. This is almost certainly not how it works, but I'm not a neuroscientist and modeling the realistic way of how information is stored within the brain just makes the model more complex, but not conceptually different. The point is that if all matter in the universe is described on the quantum side, then nothing remains on the classical side, so there is no Heisenberg cut.

But you still need "brain" or "information" as something special. If there is no brain in the universe, then does the theory predict that anything happens?
 
  • #176
naima said:
I know that we can go on to decompose everything in term of vectors, to add them, to square them, to multiply each case by a probability, to add them again. It works very well. But...
All the things like POVM's, open quantum systems, and so on, aren't really a generalization of standard QM. They have an equivalent description in standard QM with a larger Hilbert space. So in order to discuss foundational issues, we can just discuss standard QM and then later take partial traces and so on if we want to restrict to subsystems. If we can clarify the interpretational issues in standard QM, we automatically clarify them for open quantum systems as well.

atyy said:
But you still need "brain" or "information" as something special. If there is no brain in the universe, then does the theory predict that anything happens?
No, a brain is just matter like everything else. And information isn't a primitive concept at all. These concepts don't have a special status. If there is no brain, then all the processes still happen. There is just nobody who think about them. For instance, there might be a Hamiltonian that describes the whole universe and it just doesn't make matter accumulate into things like brains. A brain is just a certain constellation of matter, just like a chair or a molecule, although a quite complex one. (Note that this has nothing to do with consciousness or so. I just describe all the matter in the universe within the same quantum theory, including the matter that makes up physicists. If this matter is governed by the laws of quantum mechanics as well, then this should certainly be possible.)
 
  • #177
rubi said:
No, a brain is just matter like everything else. And information isn't a primitive concept at all. These concepts don't have a special status. If there is no brain, then all the processes still happen. There is just nobody who think about them. For instance, there might be a Hamiltonian that describes the whole universe and it just doesn't make matter accumulate into things like brains. A brain is just a certain constellation of matter, just like a chair or a molecule, although a quite complex one. (Note that this has nothing to do with consciousness or so. I just describe all the matter in the universe within the same quantum theory, including the matter that makes up physicists. If this matter is governed by the laws of quantum mechanics as well, then this should certainly be possible.)

But how does this work? Let's say we have only a wave function of the universe, with deterministic unitary time evolution. What happens? Either nothing is happening since we only have a wave function, or we have many worlds since the wave function is a superposition and all branches happen.
 
  • #178
Gleason an Gleason/Busch theorems were a major step forward in QM.
They are talking about "events" that sum to Id. They have a scalar product and a norm (the trace norm).
Decoherence is not about vectors in the Hilbert space. Decoherence is about events.
 
  • #179
atyy said:
But how does this work? Let's say we have only a wave function of the universe, with deterministic unitary time evolution. What happens? Either nothing is happening since we only have a wave function, or we have many worlds since the wave function is a superposition and all branches happen.
You don't only have a wave function ##\Psi##, you also have observables ##\hat X\phi^{\hat X}_a = \lambda^{\hat X}_a\phi^{\hat X}_a## for all possible physical questions and you have the Born rule ##P(X\in A)=\int_A |\left<\phi^{\hat X}_a,\Psi\right>|^2\mathrm d a##. The wave function ##\Psi## contains all the data you need in order to obtain the answer to any (probabilistic) question you might ask. If you have a question to the system, you just choose the appropriate observable ##\hat X## and then the Born rule allows you to compute the probability for something happening. In order for something to happen, there need not be a human who observes it. I'm not using the MWI interpretation, there is only one world in my interpretation. I'm just saying that the state ##\Psi## allows me to calculate probabilities for all possible physical events. Of course only one of these events will ever happen, but if we accept that nature is intrinsically random, then we can't do better than to have a theory that calculates only probabilities and there is no underlying mechanism that selects one of them.

naima said:
Gleason an Gleason/Busch theorems were a major step forward in QM.
They are talking about "events" that sum to Id. They have a scalar product and a norm (the trace norm).
Decoherence is not about vectors in the Hilbert space. Decoherence is about events.
I don't deny that Gleason's theorem is a great theorem, but it has nothing to do with decoherence. Decoherence is the mechanism that ensures that the probability distributions of QM don't show oscillatory behaviour, so we don't usually get interference patterns, unless we face a situation, where decoherence doesn't play a role. Decoherence is just standard QM of very large, unisolated systems.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim and Mentz114
  • #180
rubi said:
You don't only have a wave function ##\Psi##, you also have observables ##\hat X\phi^{\hat X}_a = \lambda^{\hat X}_a\phi^{\hat X}_a## for all possible physical questions and you have the Born rule ##P(X\in A)=\int_A |\left<\phi^{\hat X}_a,\Psi\right>|^2\mathrm d a##. The wave function ##\Psi## contains all the data you need in order to obtain the answer to any (probabilistic) question you might ask.

That's not really true. There are probabilistic questions that don't have answers: "What is the probability that this electron has spin-up in the x-direction and the y-direction?" There are specific questions that you're allowed to ask in QM, and it answers all of those, but that's sort of tautological: It answers the questions that it can answer.
 
  • #181
stevendaryl said:
That's not really true. There are probabilistic questions that don't have answers: "What is the probability that this electron has spin-up in the x-direction and the y-direction?" There are specific questions that you're allowed to ask in QM, and it answers all of those, but that's sort of tautological: It answers the questions that it can answer.
That's right, but it's not a problem of QM. The violation of Bell's inequality shows that it is in principle impossible to improve this situation (unless you want to exploit loopholes). It's not QM that hinders us to ask that question, but nature itself. So in some sense, QM is a theory that already achieves everything that a physical theory can possibly achieve. (Of course it's not the only theory that can achieve everything, but it's one of them.) QM just accepts it as a fact that nature forces these questions to be meaningless.

--
By the way, I understand that this doesn't seem satisfactory and I'm also interested in how to interpret this situation. All I'm saying is that it's not QM's fault that it gives unsatisfactory answers. It has to.
 
Last edited:
  • #182
rubi said:
You don't only have a wave function ##\Psi##, you also have observables ##\hat X\phi^{\hat X}_a = \lambda^{\hat X}_a\phi^{\hat X}_a## for all possible physical questions and you have the Born rule ##P(X\in A)=\int_A |\left<\phi^{\hat X}_a,\Psi\right>|^2\mathrm d a##. The wave function ##\Psi## contains all the data you need in order to obtain the answer to any (probabilistic) question you might ask. If you have a question to the system, you just choose the appropriate observable ##\hat X## and then the Born rule allows you to compute the probability for something happening. In order for something to happen, there need not be a human who observes it. I'm not using the MWI interpretation, there is only one world in my interpretation. I'm just saying that the state ##\Psi## allows me to calculate probabilities for all possible physical events. Of course only one of these events will ever happen, but if we accept that nature is intrinsically random, then we can't do better than to have a theory that calculates only probabilities and there is no underlying mechanism that selects one of them.

But if you have the observables too, and you use words like "questions you might ask", then the "you" is still postulated as something that you need to know that is not defined by the wave function alone.
 
  • #183
rubi said:
That's right, but it's not a problem of QM. The violation of Bell's inequality shows that it is in principle impossible to improve this situation (unless you want to exploit loopholes). It's not QM that hinders us to ask that question, but nature itself. So in some sense, QM is a theory that already achieves everything that a physical theory can possibly achieve. (Of course it's not the only theory that can achieve everything, but it's one of them.) QM just accepts it as a fact that nature forces these questions to be meaningless.

It's not at all clear to me how much of the QM formalism is about the way nature is. The Born rule that says that "if you measure observable O you'll an eigenvalue with such-and-such a probability" is not really about nature. In nature, we don't have observables. Not directly, anyway. You set up an experiment and the result of the experiment is this or that macroscopically distinguishable state of a detector. So what you're observing is not (directly) any property at all of the system under investigation (an electron, for example). You're observing a property of a macroscopic object, the position of a pointer, or the location of a dark spot on a photographic film, etc. So, to me, the whole mathematical apparatus of Hermitian operators and their expectation values seems removed from what's really going on in nature. I'm not exactly sure what I would like in a quantum theory, but I think that there should be a way to formulate it that doesn't mention measurements or observables or a macroscopic/microscopic distinction. Those should be derived concepts, not primitives.
 
  • #184
stevendaryl said:
It's not at all clear to me how much of the QM formalism is about the way nature is. The Born rule that says that "if you measure observable O you'll an eigenvalue with such-and-such a probability" is not really about nature. In nature, we don't have observables. Not directly, anyway. You set up an experiment and the result of the experiment is this or that macroscopically distinguishable state of a detector. So what you're observing is not (directly) any property at all of the system under investigation (an electron, for example). You're observing a property of a macroscopic object, the position of a pointer, or the location of a dark spot on a photographic film, etc. So, to me, the whole mathematical apparatus of Hermitian operators and their expectation values seems removed from what's really going on in nature. I'm not exactly sure what I would like in a quantum theory, but I think that there should be a way to formulate it that doesn't mention measurements or observables or a macroscopic/microscopic distinction. Those should be derived concepts, not primitives.

Both Many-Worlds and Bohmian interpretations DO formulate QM without observables being primitives. I'm not completely satisfied with either of those, but they are more along the lines of what I would want, I think.
 
  • #185
atyy said:
But if you have the observables too, and you use words like "questions you might ask", then the "you" is still postulated as something that you need to know that is not defined by the wave function alone.
Well, if you like it better, I could have written "questions that the universe might have to decide upon". It's not necessary for some being to ask the questions in order to have the universe decide upon them. But if you are a being, made of matter, governed by the laws of QM, then the evolution of the universe (containing yourself) might make you become aware of the answer that the universe has assigned to these questions. The word "observable" is also not to be taken literally. It's just a name for the mathematical objects that refer to parts of the universe, whether they are observed or not.
 
  • #186
stevendaryl said:
It's not at all clear to me how much of the QM formalism is about the way nature is. The Born rule that says that "if you measure observable O you'll an eigenvalue with such-and-such a probability" is not really about nature.
That's one way to phrase the Born rule, but you can also phrase it in a way that doesn't use the word measurement: "With such-and-such a probability, the eigenvalue ##\lambda## will be physically realized by nature."

In nature, we don't have observables. Not directly, anyway. You set up an experiment and the result of the experiment is this or that macroscopically distinguishable state of a detector. So what you're observing is not (directly) any property at all of the system under investigation (an electron, for example). You're observing a property of a macroscopic object, the position of a pointer, or the location of a dark spot on a photographic film, etc.
Observables refer to some parts of the universe. Of course, not all of these parts are accessible to humans, so humans can usually only learn about observables corresponding to macroscopic objects. But in the physical theory, observables are just how the correspondence between the theory and the real world is made, independent of whether humans can access them. The word "observable" is probably not very good.

So, to me, the whole mathematical apparatus of Hermitian operators and their expectation values seems removed from what's really going on in nature. I'm not exactly sure what I would like in a quantum theory, but I think that there should be a way to formulate it that doesn't mention measurements or observables or a macroscopic/microscopic distinction. Those should be derived concepts, not primitives.
Well, I think one can formulate the theory without mentioning words like measurement. We just have to choose our words more carefully. We just usually don't do this, because we are used to the physics slang. When I use these words, I don't really have their literal meaning in mind.

stevendaryl said:
Both Many-Worlds and Bohmian interpretations DO formulate QM without observables being primitives. I'm not completely satisfied with either of those, but they are more along the lines of what I would want, I think.
Well, in BM, at least position is a primitive observable, although it can't be accessed directly. In many worlds, observables are avoided by just specifying a basis directly, which essentially corresponds to specifying a preferred set of observables. There always needs to be some correspondence between the physical theory and some parts of the universe, otherwise the theory can't make predictions about those parts. I use the word "observable" for this correspondence.
 
  • #187
rubi said:
That's one way to phrase the Born rule, but you can also phrase it in a way that doesn't use the word measurement: "With such-and-such a probability, the eigenvalue ##\lambda## will be physically realized by nature."

I don't think it makes any sense to phrase it that way. Suppose I put an electron into a state state that is spin-up in the z-direction. We can compute a probability of \frac{1}{2} associated with the statement "The electron has spin-up in the x-direction". How long do I have to wait for that statement to be "physically realized by nature"? It's never going to be physically realized. If I don't act on the electron, it'll continue to be spin-up in the z-direction forever.
 
  • #188
rubi said:
Well, if you like it better, I could have written "questions that the universe might have to decide upon". It's not necessary for some being to ask the questions in order to have the universe decide upon them. But if you are a being, made of matter, governed by the laws of QM, then the evolution of the universe (containing yourself) might make you become aware of the answer that the universe has assigned to these questions. The word "observable" is also not to be taken literally. It's just a name for the mathematical objects that refer to parts of the universe, whether they are observed or not.

But if you do that, then you the universe will simultaneously decide upon a particle's position and momentum, since the wave function allows you to calculate the distribution of both observables.
 
  • #189
stevendaryl said:
I don't think it makes any sense to phrase it that way. Suppose I put an electron into a state state that is spin-up in the z-direction. We can compute a probability of \frac{1}{2} associated with the statement "The electron has spin-up in the x-direction". How long do I have to wait for that statement to be "physically realized by nature"? It's never going to be physically realized. If I don't act on the electron, it'll continue to be spin-up in the z-direction forever.

atyy said:
But if you do that, then you the universe will simultaneously decide upon a particle's position and momentum, since the wave function allows you to calculate the distribution of both observables.

The following answer applies to both of you:
This is where the consistency requirement comes in. The universe doesn't decide on all these facts individually, but it chooses one history among a set of consistent histories. So if the universe has decided for a history that has a definite spin-z value at ##t=t_1##, then it didn't decide for a history, in which spin-x had a value at ##t=t_1##. If the universe has decided for a history that had a well-defined position at ##t=t_1##, then it didn't decide for a history with a well-defined momentum at ##t=t_1##.
 
  • #190
rubi said:
The following answer applies to both of you:
This is where the consistency requirement comes in. The universe doesn't decide on all these facts individually, but it chooses one history among a set of consistent histories. So if the universe has decided for a history that has a definite spin-z value at ##t=t_1##, then it didn't decide for a history, in which spin-x had a value at ##t=t_1##. If the universe has decided for a history that had a well-defined position at ##t=t_1##, then it didn't decide for a history with a well-defined momentum at ##t=t_1##.

Okay, I do not know enough about consistent histories to make an intelligent argument, but just for confirmation about what you're saying:

I put an electron into a state of being spin-up in the z-direction. So I have a probability of \frac{1}{2} of it being spin-up in the x-direction. The meaning of that is that for all histories in which the electron has a spin in the x-direction (which might be none), half of them have spin-up and half have spin-down.
 
  • #191
stevendaryl said:
Okay, I do not know enough about consistent histories to make an intelligent argument
If you're interested, there is a very nice book called "Consistent Quantum Theory" by Robert Griffiths.

I put an electron into a state of being spin-up in the z-direction. So I have a probability of \frac{1}{2} of it being spin-up in the x-direction. The meaning of that is that for all histories in which the electron has a spin in the x-direction (which might be none), half of them have spin-up and half have spin-down.
That depends on the time. The electron has spin-z up at ##t=t_1##. Then there are several histories in which the electron has spin-x up at later time ##t=t_2##, but during the time evolution, the probabilities might have changed. If the time evolution doesn't touch the electron anymore, then you are right.
 
  • #192
rubi said:
The following answer applies to both of you:
This is where the consistency requirement comes in. The universe doesn't decide on all these facts individually, but it chooses one history among a set of consistent histories. So if the universe has decided for a history that has a definite spin-z value at ##t=t_1##, then it didn't decide for a history, in which spin-x had a value at ##t=t_1##. If the universe has decided for a history that had a well-defined position at ##t=t_1##, then it didn't decide for a history with a well-defined momentum at ##t=t_1##.

If you are using consistent histories, that is probably fine. But the view of reality there is much weaker, and whether the observer is really removed is debatable. Also, in a sense, consistent histories has collapse built into it. In any case, I don't intend to debate consistent histories here - mainly, if you are using consistent histories, I don't have a huge disagreement. I thought your point was that we could retain common sense reality, and remove the observer without introducing hidden variables or MWI - I certainly recognize a weaker sense of reality as a reasonable approach to solving the measurement problem.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #193
rubi said:
If you're interested, there is a very nice book called "Consistent Quantum Theory" by Robert Griffiths.

Ok, now I understand - you are using consistent histories. I do acknowledge that as a reasonable apporach to the measurement problem. But it would be clearer if you just stated that upfront, eg. if one is not using the orthodox interpretation, one should say I am taking an approach which attempts to solve the measurement problem of Copenhagen by doing at least one of the following (1) hidden variables (2) many worlds (3) retrocausation (4) weaker reality, etc ...
 
  • #194
atyy said:
I certainly recognize a weaker sense of reality as a reasonable approach to solving the measurement problem.
I'm not sure if I understand what you mean by "weaker sense of reality" here. Could you expand on that?
 
  • Like
Likes AlexCaledin
  • #195
Feeble Wonk said:
I'm not sure if I understand what you mean by "weaker sense of reality" here. Could you expand on that?

I first heard about it from bhobba:
https://www.physicsforums.com/threa...gen-interpretation.735465/page-6#post-4654211

From my more naive point of view - consistent histories does not admit a single fine grained reality. As we know in regular Copenhagen, collapse changes the evolution of the wave function. In consistent histories, we can get one set of "coarse grained" consistent histories by choosing a certain set of times at which to collapse the wave function. If we collapse the wave function more often, then we have a "fine grained" set of consistent histories. However, the coarse grained set is not obtainable by coarse graining the fine grained set. A way to escape this is to allow probabilities that are negative or greater than one: http://arxiv.org/abs/1106.0767 (I'm not advocating this solution, but this paper has a good explanation of the problem).
 
  • #196
atyy said:
consistent histories does not admit a single fine grained reality

Steven Weinberg says it this way,

"There is nothing absurd or inconsistent about the decoherent histories approach in particular, or about the general idea that the state vector serves only as a predictor of probabilities, not as a complete description of a physical system. Nevertheless, it would be disappointing if we had to give up the “realist” goal of finding complete descriptions of physical systems... it is hard to live with no description of physical states at all, only an algorithm for calculating probabilities."

Steven Weinberg, Lectures on Quantum Mechanics
https://en.wikiquote.org/wiki/Consistent_histories
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim, atyy and vanhees71
  • #197
atyy said:
However, the coarse grained set is not obtainable by coarse graining the fine grained set. A way to escape this is to allow probabilities that are negative or greater than one: http://arxiv.org/abs/1106.0767 (I'm not advocating this solution, but this paper has a good explanation of the problem).
So, if I'm understanding this properly, this theory would suggest that Nature is fundamentally deterministic, but not fully predictable even in principle. Correct?
 
  • #198
Feeble Wonk said:
So, if I'm understanding this properly, this theory would suggest that Nature is fundamentally deterministic, but not fully predictable even in principle. Correct?

I very much appreciate the detailed working out of consistent histories and decoherent histories and their variations by Omnes, Griffiths, Hartle, Gell-Mann etc. Their solid work goes far beyond the empty handwaving of Ballentine or Peres (I should point out that consistent histories does not support Ballentine or Peres, because consistent histories does not have deterministic unitary evolution of the wave function as fundamental). However, I cannot say that I am convinced that it represents a viable solution of the measurement problem - in particular, whether it can really be said to remove the observer from quantum mechanics. So I can't really answer your question.

It might be better for me to point to Griffiths own work http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-consistent-histories/ and criticism in the general article by Laloe http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0209123.
 
  • #199
I don't know if this paper has been mentioned already in this thread, but Weinberg wrote a paper about quantum mechanical measurement:
http://arxiv.org/pdf/1603.06008v1.pdf

He speculates that the evolution of large-scale systems might not be unitary, but that speculation is not assumed in his paper. As mentioned (either here, or in a different, related thread), the treatment of non-isolated systems interacting with an environment is nonunitary, although it's not clear with unitarity might be restored if you consider the complete system (including the environment).
 
  • #200
bhobba said:
'However, classicality is implicitly contained in 2 and 3 through the partitioning of the universal degrees of freedom into separable, localized substructures interacting via Hamiltonians that do not re-entangle them, so (given U-O) one has to put in classicality to get classicality out'

That's the factorisation issue. Its a legit issue but as I have said many times far too much is made of it IMHO. We do the same thing in classical mechanics for example but no one jumps up an down about that.

That said I have read Wallaces book and he uses an approach based on histories that seems to bypass it.

Thanks
Bill
No, Wallace doesn't bypass the problem. He just helps himself to already disjoint Hilbert space descriptions as ostensibly part of the 'bare theory'. This fails to account for the emergence of classical distinguishability--i.e, 'system' as distinct from its 'environment'. And it wrongly describes contingent information (the empirical situation at hand) as part of the pure theory.
This is not an issue in classical physics because classical physics does not have entanglement and indisguishability and the measurement problem. One can't get rid of these QM problems by saying that they aren't problems in classical physics. There is a solution to these problems in a non-unitary direct action approach, so it's not necessary for people to cling to these circular arguments, where the only way to get distinguishability in the unitary-only theory is to assume it from the beginning and then claim that one has demonstrated that it naturally emerges. We can do better than this.
 
Back
Top