MHB Prove Inequality: Symmetry, Transition & Reflexion

  • Thread starter Thread starter solakis1
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Proof
AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on proving that the properties of symmetry and transitivity do not imply reflexivity in equality. Participants emphasize the need for a counterexample where symmetry and transitivity hold, but reflexivity does not. A specific counterexample is provided, illustrating a relation that is symmetric and transitive but not reflexive. The conversation also touches on the distinction between axioms and theorems in the context of equality, with agreement that reflexivity is often treated as an axiom. Ultimately, the thread highlights the logical independence of these properties in certain contexts.
solakis1
Messages
407
Reaction score
0
How can we prove that the two properties of equality, namely,symmetry and transition do not imply that of reflexion??

needless to say that i do not know ,even how to start
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
Hint: a set of properties {P1, P2, ...} is said to imply a conclusion C if C holds whenever all of {P1, P2, ...} hold. So to show that these properties do not in fact imply C amounts to finding a counterexample, that is, a situation where C holds but not all of P{1, P2, ...} hold. Specifically if you can find examples where {P1, P2, ...} all hold and C holds, and also examples where C holds but not all of {P1, P2, ...} hold, then that logically means that {P1, P2, ...} cannot on their own imply C - that is, the two are logically independent.

In this case {P1, P2, ...} are just symmetry and transition (transitivity?) and C is the property of reflexion (reflexivity?). Can you complete?
 
Bacterius said:
Hint: a set of properties {P1, P2, ...} is said to imply a conclusion C if C holds whenever all of {P1, P2, ...} hold. So to show that these properties do not in fact imply C amounts to finding a counterexample, that is, a situation where C holds but not all of P{1, P2, ...} hold. Specifically if you can find examples where {P1, P2, ...} all hold and C holds, and also examples where C holds but not all of {P1, P2, ...} hold, then that logically means that {P1, P2, ...} cannot on their own imply C - that is, the two are logically independent.

In this case {P1, P2, ...} are just symmetry and transition (transitivity?) and C is the property of reflexion (reflexivity?). Can you complete?

the1st thing i liked for was a counterexample.but I could not find one
 
solakis said:
How can we prove that the two properties of equality, namely,symmetry and transition do not imply that of reflexion??
Equality is reflexive, so the fact that equality is reflexive is implied by anything: If $B$ is true, then $A\to B$ is also true regardless of $B$.

Bacterius said:
Hint: a set of properties {P1, P2, ...} is said to imply a conclusion C if C holds whenever all of {P1, P2, ...} hold. So to show that these properties do not in fact imply C amounts to finding a counterexample, that is, a situation where C holds but not all of P{1, P2, ...} hold.
A counterexample to $P_1\land\dots\land P_n\to C$ would be a situation where all $P_i$ hold, but $C$ does not.

Bacterius said:
Specifically if you can find examples where {P1, P2, ...} all hold and C holds, and also examples where C holds but not all of {P1, P2, ...} hold, then that logically means that {P1, P2, ...} cannot on their own imply C
The second set of examples would show that $C$ does not imply all of $P_i$, but it wouldn't show whether $P_1\land\dots\land P_n$ implies $C$.
 
Evgeny.Makarov said:
Equality is reflexive, so the fact that equality is reflexive is implied by anything: If $B$ is true, then $A\to B$ is also true regardless of $B$.
$.

Sorry I do not get it.You mean that symmetry and transition imply reflexion in equality??
 
Evgeny.Makarov said:
A counterexample to $P_1\land\dots\land P_n\to C$ would be a situation where all $P_i$ hold, but $C$ does not.

The second set of examples would show that $C$ does not imply all of $P_i$, but it wouldn't show whether $P_1\land\dots\land P_n$ implies $C$.

Yes, indeed, my mistake, got a bit mixed up there.. shouldn't be posting too late!
 
solakis said:
You mean that symmetry and transition imply reflexion in equality?
Briefly, yes. If you want to go deeper, we should start by clarifying terminology, in particular, the meaning of transition and reflexion (post #2 has proper terms for what you likely have in mind).
 
Evgeny.Makarov said:
Briefly, yes. If you want to go deeper, we should start by clarifying terminology, in particular, the meaning of transition and reflexion (post #2 has proper terms for what you likely have in mind).
Then the following is provable:
{$$(\forall A \forall B[A=B \Longrightarrow B=A])\wedge (\forall A \forall B \forall C [(A=B \wedge B=C)\Longrightarrow A=C])$$} $$\Longrightarrow \forall A[A=A]$$

I don't understand what you mean by clarifying terms... etc etc
 
solakis said:
Then the following is provable:
{$$(\forall A \forall B[A=B \Longrightarrow B=A])\wedge (\forall A \forall B \forall C [(A=B \wedge B=C)\Longrightarrow A=C])$$} $$\Longrightarrow \forall A[A=A]$$
Yes.

solakis said:
I don't understand what you mean by clarifying terms... etc etc
Clarifying terms means making their meaning clear. The meaning of the terms "transition" and "reflexion", when they are used in the context of relations, is unclear to me. Please reread what others have said about these terms in this thread.
 
  • #10
Evgeny.Makarov said:
Yes.

.

Please show me a syntactical proof
 
  • #11
For this I need the logical calculus (Hilbert style, natural deduction, natural deduction in Fitch style, sequent calculus, etc.) and axioms.

I expect that there is an axiom $\forall x.\,x=x$. It is a part of all so-called theories with equality. Then your formula is obtained by simply adding vacuous assumptions.
 
  • #12
Evgeny.Makarov said:
For this I need the logical calculus (Hilbert style, natural deduction, natural deduction in Fitch style, sequent calculus, etc.) and axioms.

I expect that there is an axiom $\forall x.\,x=x$. It is a part of all so-called theories with equality. Then your formula is obtained by simply adding vacuous assumptions.

In that case you allow me to say that the said formula is not provable
 
  • #13
I don't agree, and you have not provided any reasons for your opinion.
 
  • #14
Evgeny.Makarov said:
I don't agree, and you have not provided any reasons for your opinion.

Well, in the previous formula if we put A=B=C=a we have the following formula:

{(a=a=> a=a)&[ (a=a)&(a=a)=>a]} =>a=a

Is this formula an indentity ? NO
Because if you take a=a to be false then you have : T=>F which is false.

Hence a=a for all a , is not a theorem implied by the other two properties of equality ,thus it may be considered as an axiom
 
  • #15
solakis said:
Hence a=a for all a , is not a theorem implied by the other two properties of equality ,thus it may be considered as an axiom
I agree that it is an axiom, and that's what I said back in post #4 and repeated in post #11. If you are talking about equality, then it comes with axioms ensuring at least that it is an equivalence relation and in particular reflexive. If you are talking about some arbitrary relation, then, indeed, symmetry and transitivity do not imply reflexivity. A counterexample is the relation $\{(2,2),(3,3),(2,3),(3,2)\}$ on the set $\{1,2,3\}$. However, if a relation $R$ on $X$ is left-total in addition to being symmetric and transitive, then it is reflexive. The fact that $R$ is left-total means $\forall x\in X\,\exists y\in Y\;xRy$. In the counterexample above, 1 is not related to any number, so the relation is not left-total.

When I talked about clarifying terminology in post #7, I was hoping that along with correcting your terms for reflexivity and transitivity, you would explain what you mean by equality: the identity (also called the diagonal) relation or some arbitrary relation. However, you have done neither.

solakis said:
Well, in the previous formula if we put A=B=C=a we have the following formula:

{(a=a=> a=a)&[ (a=a)&(a=a)=>a]} =>a=a
The relationship between
\[
(\forall x,y.\;x=y\to y=x)\land (\forall x,y,z.\,x=y\land y=z\to x=z)\to\forall x.\,x=x\quad(*)
\]
and
\[
(a=a\to a=a)\land (a=a\land a=a\to a=a)\to a=a\quad(**)
\]
is not clear to me. If you have a universal formula $\forall x.\,P(x)$ and a term (say, a constant) $a$, then $P(a)$ is called an instance of $\forall x.\,P(x)$ and is implied by it. However, (*) has nested universal quantifiers, so it is not immediately clear whether truth or falsity of (**) implies that of (*).

solakis said:
Is this formula an indentity ? NO
You probably mean a tautology, not an identity.
 
  • #16
solakis said:
Well, in the previous formula if we put A=B=C=a we have the following formula:

{(a=a=> a=a)&[ (a=a)&(a=a)=>a]} =>a=a

Is this formula an indentity ? NO
Because if you take a=a to be false then you have : T=>F which is false.

Hence a=a for all a , is not a theorem implied by the other two properties of equality ,thus it may be considered as an axiom
Yes you are right, i agree.
And surely I meant tautology, not identidy.
 
Back
Top