evinda said:
Does it hold that the infinitely many elements of $\mathbb{Z}$ are equal to all the infinitely many subgroups of $\mathbb{Z}$ ?
They are not EQUAL (the integer $2$ is not the subgroup of the integers consisting of all MULTIPLES of $2$, for example) but there IS a 1-1 correspondence. In particular, there is the same "number" of subgroups of $\Bbb Z$ as there are *elements* of $\Bbb Z$, namely countably infinitely many.
Could you give me an example of a group where we can see that the above statement holds?
Sure, in the real numbers under addition, any non-zero real number $r$ gives us an example-all of these are of infinite order, as there is no FINITE positive integer $n$ such that:
$r+r+\cdots+r = 0$ ($n$ summands). For if $nr = 0$ (with $n \in N$), then since $\Bbb R$ is a field, $n = 0$, or $r = 0$. SInce $r \neq 0$, we must have $n = 0$, but 0 is not positive.
In $(\Bbb R,+)$ the subgroup generated by $r$ is:
$\langle r\rangle = \{\dots,-3r,-2r,-r,0,r,2r,3r,4r,\dots\} = \Bbb Zr = \{kr: k \in \Bbb Z\}$.
This is the isomorphism with $\Bbb Z$: $kr \leftrightarrow k$.
In general, we have the *homomorphism*:
$\Bbb Z \to \langle a\rangle$, given by $k \mapsto a^k$. In fact, this mapping is surjective, but it is injective if and only if $a$ is not of finite order (if $a$ has finite order, say $n$, then $0$ and $n$ both map to $a^n = a^0 = e$).
Why is any infinite subgroup of $G$ isomorphic to $\Bbb Z$ ?
This is not true. Only infinite CYCLIC subgroups are isomorphic to $\Bbb Z$.
Also always if we have a generator $a$ of a group, all the subgroups are of the form $\langle a^n \rangle, n \in \mathbb{N}$, right?
Yes. In the integers, $a^n$ is typically written $n\cdot a$, since $a\ast b$ is typically written $a+b$ (it's a notational thing).
Normally, the order of an element $g \in G$ is defined as the least positive integer $n$ such that $g^n = e_G$.
If we adopt this convention we see that:
$\langle g\rangle$ contains at most $\{e = g^n,g,g^2,\dots,g^{n-1}\}$ (since higher powers can be reduced to these using $g^n = e$), so the order of $\langle g\rangle$ is at most $n$.
Now suppose two of these were the same, say $g^k = g^m$, for $0 \leq k < m < n$. Then:
$e = g^k(g^k)^{-1} = g^m(g^k)^{-1} = (g^m)(g^{n-k}) = g^{m+n-k} = g^{m-k+n} = g^{m-k}g^n = g^{m-k}$.
But $0 < m - k < n - k < n$, so that $m - k$ would be a positive number less than $n$ with $g^{m-k} = e$. This violates the minimality of $n$ (which is the LEAST such positive integer).
We thus must conclude that this cannot happen, so all the powers:
$\{e,g,g^2,\dots,g^{n-1}\}$ are DISTINCT, that is $\langle g\rangle$ has EXACTLY $n$ elements, that is:
The order of $g$ (as an element) is the order of $\langle g\rangle$ (as a subgroup).
So in our case do we take as known that $G=\bigcup_{g \in G} \{ g \}$ ?
This is true of any set, including those sets which also happen to be groups (every set is the union of its elements).
If so then how do we deduce that if $g \in G$ then $g \in \langle g \rangle$ ?
An alternate definition of $\langle g\rangle$ is the smallest subgroup of $G$ containing $g$. Put another way: every subgroup generated by a set of elements contains the elements that generate it. It would be rather odd to call a subgroup "generated by $g$" if it did not even contain the generator.
So do we known that each group has cyclic subgroups, i.e. is the set of cyclic subgroups of any group always non-empty?
Yes! For ANY group $G$, the subgroup generated by any single element is, by definition, cyclic. Most groups have LOTS of cyclic subgroups.
Aren't the cyclic subgroups a subset of the cyclic subgroups?
If so could you explain me the justification why the cyclic subgroups are finite?
Did you mean "the cyclic subgroups are a subset of all the subgroups"? If so, yes.
The cyclic subgroups are finite, because the elements that generate them are of finite order (see above).