The uncertainty principle and the measurement postulate

In summary, the conversation discusses the relationship between the uncertainty principle and the measurement postulate in quantum mechanics. The uncertainty principle states that as our certainty about the position of a particle increases, our certainty about its momentum decreases, and vice versa. The measurement postulate states that when we make a measurement of the particle's position, the wave function collapses into a delta function, indicating a precise position. However, this seems to contradict the uncertainty principle as it suggests that the particle has both a known position and momentum. The conversation delves into the mathematical and conceptual issues surrounding this paradox and ultimately shows that there is no contradiction between the two principles. In summary, the uncertainty principle and the measurement postulate work together to define the limits of our knowledge
  • #1
la6ki
53
0
Hi everybody.

I have a quick question regarding the relationship between the uncertainty principle and the measurement postulate. According to the former, the higher our certainty is about the position of a particle, the lower our certainty is regarding its momentum, and vice versa. This means that our uncertainty about the momentum would be maximum if we knew the position of the particle exactly. Now, according to the measurement postulate, if we made a measurement and found the particle at a particular position, the wave function will collapse into a delta function, which means that the probability distribution for the position of the particle is now just that delta function. Furthermore, we know that if we were to measure its position again a very short time after the first measurement, we are bound to find the particle at the same position (the wave function remains collapsed for some small amount of time).

But this is where I'm confused. If we know where the particle is now and that we are going to find it at the exact same position after some short Δt, doesn't this mean that the particle just hasn't moved at all and therefore its momentum must be zero? Clearly this can't be true, since that would mean we know both the position and the momentum exactly.

I would really appreciate clarifying comments!
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
if the particle is measured after a time delta t again it can be everywhere since the wavefunction is at that time a gaussian. (if we use schroedinger equ.)
The problem could arise when we take the limit delta t towards 0 but then it means that both measurement happened at the same time hence it is only one measurement.
 
  • #3
In reality, no position measurement has infinite accuracy. So we will just be making approximate position measurements, and every time we do, it leaves the particle not in a delta function state, but in a state represented by a wavefunction that's peaked around the position indicated by the detector, and close to zero elsewhere. If the measurement is very accurate, the peak is very sharp, and the Fourier transform of the wavefunction is spread out over a large region.

An approximate momentum measurement is a series of approximate position measurements, that are inaccurate enough to not spread out the wave function's Fourier transform too much.
 
  • #4
If you use delta you can look under propagator in wikipedia.
 
  • #5
Hi la6ki,

your question is a good one. The paradox is due to [literal application of the] projection postulate.


The first problem is that there is no valid wave function that would correspond to one definite position. "Delta function", which you suggest, is associated with only one point, which is good, but is not really a function. It can be understood as distribution, but then it does not fit into the set of ##\psi## functions which have the Born interpretation, namely that the square of their modulus gives the probability density. This is because the square of ##\delta## is not a valid mathematical object.

Similarly, the function ##e^{i\mathbf p\cdot\mathbf r/\hbar}## is not normalizable wave function.

The proper conclusion from this is that a knowledge that particle has definite position or definite momentum cannot be transcribed into the description based on wave functions. Admissible wave functions have to be somewhere in between, i.e. they have to be not localized too much, but also not spread too much.

So let's assume we work with such "peak" functions instead.


If somehow (not trivial!) we perform what you describe at time ##t_1##, then after the measurement we obtain the position ##x_1##, and we assume that after the measurement the wave function is a peak centered at ##x_1##.

In the interval ##t_1..t_2##, it spreads out.

At time ##t_2##, we do the same thing and obtain ##x_2##.

We can calculate probable momentum as

$$
p_x = m \frac{x_2 - x_1}{\Delta t}
$$

and assign it to the particle and the time interval ##(t_1, t_2)##. If we assume the particle moved uniformly, we can ascribe position and this momentum to it for any time in the interval ##(t_1,t_2)##, although this is rather speculative as we do not know whether the particle moved from ##x_1## to ##x_2## uniformly (consider what happens during the Brownian motion). Heisenberg was aware of this and he did not deny it in his book Principles of Quantum Theory.

What Heisenberg tried to say is that when the position of the particle is measured at time ##t_1##, the value ##p## known from before becomes unreliable, because the measurement of ##x## involves an interaction of the detector with the electron, which changes electron's momentum ##p_x## in an uncontrollable way. He showed that this happens in such a way that the product of statistical spread in ##x_1## and statistical spread in the conjugated momentum ##p_x## just after the measurement at time ##t_1## (calculated for a set of many measurements) is a quantity close to Planck constant.

So there is no direct contradiction with the Heisenberg principle, because our average ##p_x## for time ##t_1..t_2## does not correspond to ##p_x(just~after~ t_1)## which Heisenberg had in mind. In order to break HP, we would have to find somehow the momentum just after the measurement of position at ##t_1##, but our measurement finds only average momentum during time ##t_1..t_2##. We may find the momentum after ##t_2## by calculation, but this is only a posteriori and hypothetical.

(Soon after Heisenberg's lectures, Einstein, Tolman and Podolsky in their paper

"Knowledge of Past and Future in Quantum Mechanics", Physical Review, 1931

came to conclusion that retrodiction of past motion has to have similar uncertainty, so the assumption of uniform motion is dubious.)

It remains to ask: is there a contradiction with the mathematical uncertainty relation?

The answer is again no. In UR, the probable momentum and its uncertainty is not calculated from positions, but directly from the wave function, at one time.

In all instants of time, if we assume we have some admissible wave function, the product of uncertainties is calculated to be greater than ##\hbar / 2##.
 
  • #6
Thanks for the clarifying comments Fredrik & Jano!

Yeah, I think it makes sense now, the idea that what people mean when they talk about uncertainty in the momentum is at the exact moment at which the position is measured, and not after a particular time interval after the measurement.
 

1. What is the uncertainty principle?

The uncertainty principle is a fundamental principle in quantum mechanics that states that it is impossible to simultaneously know the exact position and momentum of a particle. This means that the more precisely we know the position of a particle, the less we know about its momentum, and vice versa.

2. How does the uncertainty principle relate to the measurement postulate?

The uncertainty principle is closely related to the measurement postulate, which states that the act of measuring a particle's position or momentum will affect its state. This means that the more precisely we try to measure one property of a particle, the more uncertain the other property becomes.

3. Can the uncertainty principle be violated?

No, the uncertainty principle is a fundamental principle in quantum mechanics and has been verified through numerous experiments. It is considered a law of nature and cannot be violated.

4. Does the uncertainty principle apply to all particles?

Yes, the uncertainty principle applies to all particles, including subatomic particles like electrons and larger particles like atoms and molecules. It is a fundamental principle of the quantum world and is not limited to specific types of particles.

5. How does the uncertainty principle affect our daily lives?

The uncertainty principle has little to no impact on our daily lives as it only becomes significant at the subatomic level. In our everyday world, the effects of the uncertainty principle are too small to be noticeable. However, it has had a profound impact on our understanding of the quantum world and has led to many technological advancements.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
12
Views
670
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
3
Views
256
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
17
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
48
Views
3K
Replies
10
Views
1K
Replies
1
Views
816
Replies
8
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
32
Views
2K
Back
Top