I Are Real Numbers Essential in Scientific Measurements and Models?

AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on the nature of measurements in science, questioning whether measurements are defined by physical interactions or the numerical values assigned to them. It highlights that real numbers and rational numbers have distinct properties, particularly regarding bounded sets, and emphasizes that finite precision limits the applicability of infinite sets in measurements. The conversation also explores the implications of using different number systems, such as hyperreals, and whether physical quantities can be accurately represented as real numbers given the constraints of measurement precision. Ultimately, it suggests that any measurement reflects a finite range of possibilities rather than an arbitrary real number, aligning with the principles of quantum mechanics and the limitations of physical processes.
Messages
36,404
Reaction score
15,117
TL;DR Summary
Discuss the use of different number systems (rationals vs reals) in science
A couple of weeks ago we had an interesting thread where a tangent developed discussing whether real-valued measurements were possible. I would like to generalize that discussion a bit in this one and discuss all scientific purposes, not just measurements.

1) What is a measurement anyway? Is it the physical interaction, or is it the number we assign to the interaction. For example, in a galvanometer, is the measurement the deflection of the needle or is it the number that we assign to the deflection? This is probably a matter of opinion, so it probably is important just to state one's opinion.

2) One thing that I found in my research on the topic is that there is only one axiom that the reals satisfy and the rationals do not. If you have a bounded set of reals then the bound is a real, but there are bounded sets of rationals whose bound is irrational. For example, the set of all rationals such that ##\left(\frac{p}{q}\right)^2<2##. This set is bounded from above, but the bound is ##\sqrt{2}## which is irrational. So, for measurements it is unclear how this applies. There are no infinite sets of measurements, and for any finite set of numbers the bound is an element of that set. So the one axiom that distinguishes reals and rationals doesn't apply to measurements.

3) Because precision is finite, measurements don't have limits in the epsilon-delta sense. Even means of measurements don't have such limits. So speaking of large sets of measurements in the limit as the number of measurements goes to infinity still doesn't give convergence, bounding, or limits even in principle.

4) Suppose that we have two scientific models, one based on real numbers and one based on rational numbers. Suppose further that whenever the real model predicts a value, the rational model predicts the rational value that is closest to that real value. There is no experimental measurement which can provide evidence for one of these models and against the other. Any measurement is compatible with an infinite number of reals and an infinite number of rationals.

5) There are theoretical reasons to prefer the reals over the rationals. For example, you cannot do integration of rational functions, or rather the resulting integrals can be irrational. If we prefer reals over rationals for theoretical reasons, and if our models are compatible with both, can we not declare our measurements to be reals?

6) What about hyperreals? We might make theoretical arguments favoring hyperreals. The same compatibility and preference arguments would apply. Can we declare our measurements to be hyperreals? What about surreals? Is there a line, and if so where do we draw it and why?
 
  • Like
Likes cyboman and DeBangis21
Physics news on Phys.org
Dale said:
5) There are theoretical reasons to prefer the reals over the rationals. For example, you cannot do integration of rational functions, or rather the resulting integrals can be irrational.
@Dale, I'm not sure what you mean here by a rational function. A rational function is the quotient of two polynomials; e.g., ##f(x) = \frac{p(x)}{q(x)}## where both p and q are polynomials. Some rational functions do have integrals that are themselves rational functions. An example is ##\int \frac{dx}{x^2}##, whose integral (or antiderivative) is ##\frac{-1}x + C##. I believe that what you meant by a rational function was one that evaluated to a rational number, but I'm not sure.
 
Mark44 said:
@Dale, I'm not sure what you mean here by a rational function. A rational function is the quotient of two polynomials; e.g., ##f(x) = \frac{p(x)}{q(x)}## where both p and q are polynomials. Some rational functions do have integrals that are themselves rational functions. An example is ##\int \frac{dx}{x^2}##, whose integral (or antiderivative) is ##\frac{-1}x + C##. I believe that what you meant by a rational function was one that evaluated to a rational number, but I'm not sure.
You are correct, I was being unclear. By "rational function" I had intended to mean a function mapping from the rationals to the rationals. The integral $$\int \frac{1}{x} dx = \ln (x) + C$$ is the main culprit I was thinking of. If ##x## is a non-zero rational number then ##1/x## is also rational, but ##\ln (x)## is not.

So it seems that integration cannot be defined strictly on the rationals. This is actually related to the bounding axiom that distinguishes rationals and reals. I suspect that standard trig functions also cannot be defined between the rationals.
 
Dale said:
I suspect that standard trig functions also cannot be defined between the rationals.
No. They are defined either by a series that needs the topological completion of the reals to guarantee a limit or by the exponential function which is already impossible over the rationals since ##e## isn't rational.

This discussion reminds me of my professor in my ODE class who said: "The real world is discrete!" The rationals are already unphysical because they are dense, and the real world, well, let's stop at the nucleus size or for the idealists at Planck length, is discrete.

On the other hand, physical quantities are always denoted as ##A \pm B.## Doesn't this mean that you cannot even get a rational measurement?
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, DrClaude and Dale
fresh_42 said:
Doesn't this mean that you cannot even get a rational measurement?
I think that is correct. Due to finite precision any measurement is consistent with an infinite number of rationals. How can you claim that any one of those rationals "is" the measurement?
 
Dale said:
I think that is correct. Due to finite precision any measurement is consistent with an infinite number of rationals. How can you claim that any one of those rationals "is" the measurement?
Do we have to say that any physical quantity is only a distribution? And if so, isn't it meaningless whether we consider it over real numbers or a dense subset?
 
  • Like
Likes DaveE and Dale
fresh_42 said:
And if so, isn't it meaningless whether we consider it over real numbers or a dense subset?
I think it is meaningless, indeed. Although I am not sure that is anything even remotely approaching a consensus view.

I think then it is interesting to consider supersets instead of subsets. What about hyperreals? If we are just arbitrarily mapping distributions to dense sets, why not use sets even denser than the reals?
 
Dale said:
I think it is meaningless, indeed. Although I am not sure that is anything even remotely approaching a consensus view.

I think then it is interesting to consider supersets instead of subsets. What about hyperreals? If we are just arbitrarily mapping distributions to dense sets, why not use sets even denser than the reals?
I'm not sure whether the hyperreals are a valid alternative. I think it is a bit like putting the cart before the ox. If we agree that physics is a collection of distributions, then we will need a calculus of random variables. I don't think that we can call what we have, central limit theorem, 1-2-3 theorem, and rules like that already an entire calculus. The approach of analysis by Borel algebras and measure theory (pun not intended) seems more promising. It could create a new perspective.
 
I don't particularly see the relevance of different number systems. If we take a measurement to be a physical process, then (IMO) there is always some finite limit to the precision of any given measurement. It wouldn't make sense, for example, to give a winning time in a 100m race as an arbitrary real number. Any measurement of the time can only be one of a finite number of possible values, depending on the measurement apparatus.

It's a moot point whether the time itself is a real number. Any measurement of that time can only be chosen from a finite number of possibilities for any given event.

One reason this topic arises is that the Internet is littered with web pages saying: if a person chooses a real number uniformly from the interval ##[0,1]##, then ... That, IMO is not a physically realisable process. It can only be done through the mathematics of continuous probability distributions. But, there is no way that someone can choose equally from anything but a finite set of possibilities.
 
  • #10
fresh_42 said:
The approach of analysis by Borel algebras and measure theory
I am vaguely aware of measure theory, but not Borel algebras. I will take a look.
 
  • #11
Dale said:
I am vaguely aware of measure theory, but not Borel algebras. I will take a look.
It's only the set of measurable volumes so that we can integrate. It's what we need for the Lebesgue measure, the integral we use anyway. Hewitt / Stromberg, Real and Abstract Analysis, GTM 25 is written along those lines.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #12
Dale said:
By "rational function" I had intended to mean a function mapping from the rationals to the rationals. The integral $$\int \frac{1}{x} dx = \ln (x) + C$$ is the main culprit I was thinking of. If ##x## is a non-zero rational number then ##1/x## is also rational, but ##\ln (x)## is not.
I thought you might have that one in mind, which is why I chose the integral I showed as a counterexample.
 
  • #13
Mark44 said:
I thought you might have that one in mind, which is why I chose the integral I showed as a counterexample.
Yes, there are many rational to rational functions that do have an integral, but there are some that do not. So I don't think that you can generally say that you can do integration with the rationals.

In other words, my point is that it cannot always be done, not that it can never be done.
 
  • #14
Dale said:
Yes, there are many rational to rational functions that do have an integral, but there are some that do not. So I don't think that you can generally say that you can do integration with the rationals.
No, I wasn't claiming that.
 
  • #15
OK, I think we are in agreement then?
 
  • #16
PeroK said:
I don't particularly see the relevance of different number systems. If we take a measurement to be a physical process, then (IMO) there is always some finite limit to the precision of any given measurement. It wouldn't make sense, for example, to give a winning time in a 100m race as an arbitrary real number. Any measurement of the time can only be one of a finite number of possible values, depending on the measurement apparatus.
If we take a measurement to be a physical process then I don't think that I agree that any measurement can only be one of a finite number of possible values.

I mentioned the galvanometer as an example. If the measurement is the physical process, the deflection of the needle, then I disagree that it can take only one of a finite number of possible values. Position is continuous in both classical and quantum mechanics.
 
  • #17
Another example is the good old analog oscilloscope. The exact frequency and even more the amplitude of a sine wave can be any number close to what the theory says it will be.
 
  • #18
Dale said:
If we take a measurement to be a physical process then I don't think that I agree that any measurement can only be one of a finite number of possible values.

I mentioned the galvanometer as an example. If the measurement is the physical process, the deflection of the needle, then I disagree that it can take only one of a finite number of possible values. Position is continuous in both classical and quantum mechanics.
The needle on a galvonometer - even on a macroscopic scale - is distinctly finite in size. Eventually, at a small enough scale, the point of a needle is no longer point like. And, eventually, even in a classical model the point of the needle is just a vacuum between atoms.

Moreover, QM has the HUP (Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle), which disallows a precise measurement to an arbitrary degree.

So, both practically and theoretically (as far as QM is concerned), the point of a needle cannot be determined to arbitrary precision.
 
  • #19
PeroK said:
Eventually, at a small enough scale, the point of a needle is no longer point like. And, eventually, even in a classical model the point of the needle is just a vacuum between atoms.
I have no objection to that.

PeroK said:
Moreover, QM has the HUP (Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle), which disallows a precise measurement to an arbitrary degree.
I am not disagreeing with that either.

PeroK said:
So, both practically and theoretically (as far as QM is concerned), the point of a needle cannot be determined to arbitrary precision.
I am not talking about precision. I think that we are talking past each other.

If the measurement is the physical process, rather than the number we get from the physical process, then it is a state of some physical system. In both classical mechanics and QM there are not a finite number of states that a galvanometer needle can be in. I am not talking about how precisely we can put it into a state nor how precisely we can determine what state it is in, just how many states our physics models say it can be in.
 
  • #20
Dale said:
I have no objection to that.

I am not disagreeing with that either.

I am not talking about precision. I think that we are talking past each other.

If the measurement is the physical process, rather than the number we get from the physical process, then it is a state of some physical system. In both classical mechanics and QM there are not a finite number of states that a galvanometer needle can be in. I am not talking about how precisely we can put it into a state nor how precisely we can determine what state it is in, just how many states our physics models say it can be in.
In QM, there is a clear distinction between a state and a measurement of that state. There are infinitely many spin states for a spin 1/2 particle, but only two results for a measurement.

No piece of apparatus can establish a measurement of position to arbitrary precision. There is also something strange about a measurement process that does not and cannot yield a result.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and Dale
  • #21
PeroK said:
In QM, there is a clear distinction between a state and a measurement of that state. There are infinitely many spin states for a spin 1/2 particle, but only two results for a measurement.
Good point. My QM is not good, so perhaps I have this wrong. This is known as the spectrum of the eigenvectors, right? Is it the eigenvectors of the state or the operator or both?

PeroK said:
No piece of apparatus can establish a measurement of position to arbitrary precision. There is also something strange about a measurement process that does not and cannot yield a result.
Again, I am not talking about precision.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
I am reminded that Eddington defined physics as comparing pointer readings. In this context isn't this argument simply academic?
All experimental measurement is ratiometric. It is why and how we calibrate our experimental equipment.
Is there a "measurement" that is somehow divorced from actual experiment?
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and PeroK
  • #23
hutchphd said:
Is there a "measurement" that is somehow divorced from actual experiment?
I.e. the rough analogy of non constructive mathematics. In a previous thread I suggested something like realising the fixed point mapping theorem as a real valued measurement of sorts.
 
  • #24
This seems an exercise in omphalloskepsis to me. I understand this tobe a minority view! (Perhaps occasioned by my seeming incapacity to do rigorous mathematics)
 
  • #25
It's clear to me that in digital data, we only have integer values actually, with multiplication altered to have a subdivision of 1 in as many parts as the precision goes and rounding results. For measurements this is often with an error bar or assumed to be a normal distribution and a standard deviation is provided.

Regardless, there are many required theoretical aspects of modern science that were inspired by continuity (trigonometry, probability density, topology, Lie groups), algebraicity (complex numbers, galois theory and its isomorphisms), infinity (projective spaces, renormalization) and probably much more. IMO science should not be limited to describe only what is measurable, there should be space to expand theoretically and perhaps sometime also experimentally.
 
  • #26
Structure seeker said:
IMO science should not be limited to describe only what is measurable, there should be space to expand theoretically and perhaps sometime also experimentally.
It's not. We use mathematics, which is not physically constrained. The simplest example is instantaneous velocity, which cannot be measured. It's a mathematical construction.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and hutchphd
  • #27
This thread drifted into strange parts. Measurements, precision, and even HUP has been mentioned. This has little to do with ...
Discuss the use of different number systems (rationals vs reals) in science
... and this thread is quickly on its way to vacuity, faster than usual. We already know that the measurement discussion leads nowhere. Heck, we even have a separate forum for it. We felt the need to lock such discussions away in the padded cell. It is a bottomless barrel.

I, too, think that the question ...
Discuss the use of different number systems (rationals vs reals) in science
... reverses the natural order. Which number system we use is an a posteriori question, after the decision has been made to use ordinary calculus. The question shouldn't be whether we assume the existence of limits that can neither be measured nor be written down, or restrict ourselves to finite decimals, i.e. a dense subset. Both, completeness and density are unphysical terms. The choice between reals and rationals is without substance in my mind, and hyperreals even more. These are all a posteriori considerations and only affect convenience and techniques. It is a similar discussion as to whether we believe in AC or not.

In my mind, we should take a step backward and ask what we want to deal with. If we take the perspective of measurements as the fundamental object of physics, then in my opinion, we should replace our variables which don't always represent numbers anyway, by probability distribution functions. This would be a new perspective with the potential to unify the physical calculus. And it sets the measurement in the center of consideration. Whether the related random variables are real, rational, or even complex, waves or operators is more or less not important.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreasC, Dale and hutchphd
  • #28
fresh_42 said:
and this thread is quickly on its way to vacuity
My comment was meant to imply that the all measurement (at least in the present structure of our science) is ratiometric. I do not consider that unimportant. Vacuity is in the eye of the beholder, but the slope is indeed slippery.
 
  • #29
Dale said:
4) ... Any measurement is compatible with an infinite number of reals and an infinite number of rationals.
This, and IMHO there is nothing more to consider.
 
  • Like
Likes Vanadium 50, hutchphd and Dale
  • #30
fresh_42 said:
These are all a posteriori considerations and only affect convenience and techniques. ... If we take the perspective of measurements as the fundamental object of physics, then in my opinion, we should replace our variables which don't always represent numbers anyway, by probability distribution functions
I like that as it would handle precision “natively” and the same framework would suffice for qualitative measurements, discrete valued measurements, and continuous valued measurements.

I think we are not too far from that already.
 
  • #31
@PeroK you keep mentioning precision, both in this thread and in the previous thread. Precision is not the issue in my mind.

Precision describes the spread of a probability density function. I am talking about the sample space. You could have two random variables with equal variance but one is over the rationals and another is over the reals.

Real valued measurement is not a synonym for infinite precision, in my mind. Hopefully that helps us not talk past each other.
 
  • #32
The question about the number system does remind me of the problem with AC. If we say that ##(0,1)## has a maximal element then most people wouldn't understand it. If we say "let ##\displaystyle{a\in \times_{\iota\in I}A_\iota}##" then most people would continue reading without noticing that they have just used the axiom of choice.

I do not see how the number system is relevant to physics. If we measure a length as the ##192 703 382 559 127 383 007 402 699## th atom from left on the edge of our ruler, or as ##1.41 \pm 0.005## inches or as ##\sqrt{2}## inches as the theory tells us - where is the difference? The choice of the number system only says: there is definitely a length (if we use ##\mathbb{R}##) or there is a length close enough to the number of atoms (if we use ##\mathbb{Q}##). I prefer the existence of that length over "close enough" although I know that we will never be able to measure ##\sqrt{2}## inches.
$$
\ddot x = G_0\, , \,x(0)=0\, , \,\dot x(0)=1
$$
spits out when exactly I will hit the ground due to the completeness of the real numbers, regardless of the fact that my input variable can only be measured up to eight digits or so. The result shouldn't depend on the number system. I wouldn't really like to read: I hit the ground after ##0.45152364098573090445081112433814## seconds but only if ##G_0=9.81.## Such a result would not make sense, and if I write ##0.45 \pm 0.002## seconds, then it is not what the theory says. The truth is that I have measured a real random variable
$$
T_0=\sqrt{\dfrac{2X(0)}{G_0}}
$$
consisting of the outcome of a random variable height ##X(0)## and the outcome of a random variable called local acceleration ##G_0.## This would be what I actually have done in reality. Whether ##G_0,X(0),T_0## are real or rational is irrelevant, they are neither. However, only ##\mathbb{R}## guarantees me that there is definitely a solution to my equation which makes sense since it hurts after half a second.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #33
fresh_42 said:
I do not see how the number system is relevant to physics.
Well, you cannot do calculus with the rationals. That seems important on the theory side.
 
  • #34
Dale said:
Well, you cannot do calculus with the rationals. That seems important on the theory side.
I'm not so sure. If we put the measurements in the center of consideration, then arbitrary close is close enough. It helps that we have names for ##\mathrm{e}## and ##\pi ## but where do we need all their digits? Rational Cauchy sequences will no longer converge, nevertheless, they are still Cauchy sequences.

It's a matter of convenience, in my mind, not a matter of physics.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #35
fresh_42 said:
It's a matter of convenience, in my mind, not a matter of physics.
The question is whether we could ever confirm by measurement that the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter is ##\pi##.

IMO, there are a number of problems with mapping the mathematics to a physical circle.
 
  • #36
PeroK said:
The question is whether we could ever confirm by measurement that the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter is ##\pi##.
I came across the Leibniz series for ##\pi/4## lately. I think this contains every aspect of our discussion here.
$$
\sum_{n=1}^{\infty }{\dfrac {(-1)^{n-1}}{2n-1}}= 1-{\dfrac{1}{3}}+{\dfrac{1}{5}}-{\dfrac{1}{7}}+{\dfrac{1}{9}}-\dotsb ={\dfrac{\pi }{4}}
$$
Should we give up assigning a value because it is no longer rational? If we hand over the left-hand side to physicists in order to perform a measurement and they say that they cannot add infinitely often, then is it a problem of our theory, or reality in general?

Surely, we can never confirm by measurement that the assigned value is what the theory says. However, that doesn't stop us from assigning its value or from using the formula. That's why I said it is a matter of convenience. We deduced this formula logically and the physicists cannot measure a significant violation. Therefore, we conveniently accept it.

From a purely logical point of view, physics has already a significant problem with that apple. Just because it always fell down does not guarantee it always will! We accept that it will without further thought, but we cannot be sure. It's a convenience, a commitment, a theoretical assumption, but not a truth chiseled in stone. You can always say that a single measurement will not be sufficient. That was the origin of my idea to treat physical quantities as random variables by default.

PeroK said:
IMO, there are a number of problems with mapping the mathematics to a physical circle.
That was the reason why I quoted my ODE professor: the real world is discrete.
 
  • #37
I think I should link two papers that might make sense in this discussion. I haven't read them in detail - mainly because I still can't evaluate the seriousness of the discussion here or where it is supposed to got to - one is a classical paper from a mathematician, and the newer one is at least interesting and from a physicist.

Eugene Wigner, The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in Natural Sciences, New York, 1960
(the original reference is on the first page, the link to the university server in Edinburgh, so hopefully no copyright issues)
https://www.maths.ed.ac.uk/~v1ranick/papers/wigner.pdf

A.N. Mitra, Mathematics: The Language of Science, Delhi, 2018
https://arxiv.org/pdf/1111.6560v3.pdf
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #38
I have a slightly different take on this. Suppose that we have a theory which uses real numbers and predicts that some value is exactly ##\pi##. All measurements have some finite precision. If we make any measurement that includes ##\pi## in its uncertainty interval, then we have evidence supporting the theory and it is reasonable to say that you have measured the value to be the real number ##\pi## to within the experimental precision.

To me, that is how science should work. Measurements and experiments are indeed important, but so is theory. If the theory claims a real number value and the experiment is consistent with the theory then there is no reason to not claim that the measurement is a real number.
 
  • Like
Likes russ_watters, pbuk, nasu and 1 other person
  • #39
Dale said:
I have a slightly different take on this. Suppose that we have a theory which uses real numbers and predicts that some value is exactly ##\pi##. All measurements have some finite precision. If we make any measurement that includes ##\pi## in its uncertainty interval, then we have evidence supporting the theory and it is reasonable to say that you have measured the value to be the real number ##\pi## to within the experimental precision.

To me, that is how science should work. Measurements and experiments are indeed important, but so is theory. If the theory claims a real number value and the experiment is consistent with the theory then there is no reason to not claim that the measurement is a real number.
I don't totally disagree with this. It has a potential flaw in that the measurement outcome depends on the theory. The measurement, IMO, would be something like ##3.14159 \pm 0.00005##, say. That's the result of the measurement. If the theory says that the precise value is ##3.141592##, then you say that is the result of the measurement. And, if the theory says that the precise value is ##\pi##, then you say that is the result the measurement. I'm not totally convinced by this. IMO, the result of the measurement is ##3.14159 \pm 0.00005## and let the theorists make of that what they will.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and russ_watters
  • #40
Dale said:
I have a slightly different take on this. Suppose that we have a theory which uses real numbers and predicts that some value is exactly ##\pi##. All measurements have some finite precision. If we make any measurement that includes ##\pi## in its uncertainty interval, then we have evidence supporting the theory and it is reasonable to say that you have measured the value to be the real number ##\pi## to within the experimental precision.

To me, that is how science should work. Measurements and experiments are indeed important, but so is theory. If the theory claims a real number value and the experiment is consistent with the theory then there is no reason to not claim that the measurement is a real number.
Actually, I have a more significant disagreement with this. If we replace the numbers on a clock with ##2\pi, \frac {\pi} {6}, \frac {\pi} {3}, \frac{\pi}{4}, \frac{2\pi}{3} \dots##, then we get one of only twelve possible measurements for the position of a clock hand. They are all irrational. That's not the point. The point is there are only twelve possible outcomes.

In your experiment, there are only two possible outcomes: an interval containing ##\pi## and an interval not containing ##\pi##.

There can never be an uncountable number of possible measurement outcomes.
 
  • #41
PeroK said:
There can never be an uncountable number of possible measurement outcomes.
This is tautological in my opinion. You can always only perform a finite number of measurements at all, hence getting a finite number of outcomes in finite time. The possible outcomes are also finite per the construction of our measurements based on counting. We simply cannot distinguish ##\pi## from a rational number, but this handicap does not mean we haven't measured ##\pi##. Who is it to tell us the difference?
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #42
fresh_42 said:
We simply cannot distinguish ##\pi## from a rational number, but this handicap does not mean we haven't measured ##\pi##. Who is it to tell us the difference?
The curved spacetime of GR? If space is not static and Euclidean, then the ratio may not be ##\pi##. This is another aspect of confusing the mathematical model with the physical objects and phenomena themselves.
 
  • #43
PeroK said:
I don't totally disagree with this. It has a potential flaw in that the measurement outcome depends on the theory. The measurement, IMO, would be something like ##3.14159 \pm 0.00005##, say. That's the result of the measurement. If the theory says that the precise value is ##3.141592##, then you say that is the result of the measurement. And, if the theory says that the precise value is ##\pi##, then you say that is the result the measurement.
Yes. I don't think that this is so much a flaw as an acknowledgement that some measurements will not be able to distinguish between two theories. That is a scientific fact. Such a measurement would indeed support both theories without providing evidence for one theory over the other.

However, if you do not allow measurements to represent real numbers then the theory that predicts ##\pi## is inherently contradicted by any measurement, no matter how precisely it agrees with the theory. If you simply assert that all measurements must be inherently rational or natural, then one thing you automatically know is that your theory saying it is ##\pi## is disproven by a measurement of ##3.14159 \pm 0.00005##.

PeroK said:
IMO, the result of the measurement is 3.14159±0.00005 and let the theorists make of that what they will.
I guess I have a more holistic view of science. I view both theory and experiment as co-essential to science.

PeroK said:
They are all irrational. That's not the point.
Why not? Seems like a good point to me. We are trying to determine what number system to use, so it does seem important that when you change from ##\mathrm{Hz}## to ##\mathrm{s^{-1}}## at least one must be irrational.

PeroK said:
The point is there are only twelve possible outcomes.
Counterexample: Rolex. Also, the phase of any frequency standard that produces a phase.

PeroK said:
There can never be an uncountable number of possible measurement outcomes.
I disagree. I don't know the correct wording for quantum stuff, but my understanding is that there do exist quantum measurements that have a continuous spectrum. And clearly classically there can be an uncountable number of possible measurement outcomes. So on what theory do you base this theoretical claim?
 
  • #44
Dale said:
If you simply assert that all measurements must be inherently rational or natural, then one thing you automatically know is that your theory saying it is ##\pi## is disproven by a measurement of ##3.14159 \pm 0.00005##.
You continue to confuse a finite set with a countable set with an uncountable set. You can have a finite subset of real numbers: ##\{ \pi, e, \sqrt 2 \}## is a finite set. You can choose from that set.

Dale said:
I view both theory and experiment as co-essential to science.
Who doesn't?
Dale said:
And clearly classically there can be an uncountable number of possible measurement outcomes. So on what theory do you base this theoretical claim?
No measuring device can produce an uncountably infinite number of possible outputs. Most real numbers would require an infinite amount of information to describe them, so cannot be the outcome of a measurement. These real numbers have only a mathematical existence.

Dale said:
Counterexample: Rolex.
Even a Rolex watch cannot have an uncountably infinite number of markings.
Dale said:
I disagree. I don't know the correct wording for quantum stuff, but my understanding is that there do exist quantum measurements that have a continuous spectrum. And clearly classically there can be an uncountable number of possible measurement outcomes. So on what theory do you base this theoretical claim?
We are never going to agree about this. You say you can produce any real number and I say you can only produce a number from a pre-defined finite set. You see measurement as a theoretical, mathemetical process; I see it as a practical, physical process.

A good test case would be to consider a clock that could stop at any instant and record any time interval. You say it's possible. I say that, ultimately, any clock can only have a (pre-defined) finite number of possible outputs. This is explicit in the most accurate clocks we have. So, although theoretically time is a continuous variable, in practice any measurement of time with any clock is a discrete variable. And how do you measure time without a clock?
 
  • #45
PeroK said:
You continue to confuse a finite set with a countable set with an uncountable set. You can have a finite subset of real numbers: {π,e,2} is a finite set. You can choose from that set.
I am not confusing them. A finite set of irrational numbers are still irrational numbers. To me that is an indication that measurements cannot be a priori restricted to rational numbers.

PeroK said:
You see measurement as a theoretical, mathemetical process; I see it as a practical, physical process.
Instead of telling me that I am confusing things I am not confusing and instead of telling me how I see things that I don't see that way, why don't you stick to justifying your own view. I also see measurement as a practical physical process, I just disagree about some of your assertions about that physical process. I also think that it is important to consider both the practical physical things as well as the theoretical considerations. Both are needed for science.

PeroK said:
I say you can only produce a number from a pre-defined finite set.
On what do you base that claim?

PeroK said:
No measuring device can produce an uncountably infinite number of possible outputs.
I am not convinced that is true. On what basis do you make that claim? Both classically and in QM there are measurements with an uncountably infinite number of possible outputs.

However, consider also that not only do we want to make measurements with one device on one measurand, we also want to compare measurement results on the same consistent scale across devices and across measurands.

Are you sure that there are a finite number of possible outputs across all possible measuring devices measuring all possible measurands? And furthermore are you sure that those different devices and measurands are all rationally related?

If I have two clocks and one measures in a fixed fraction of ##\mathrm{Hz}##, and the other measures in a fixed fraction of ##\mathrm{rad/s}## then even though each individually gives a pre-defined finite set of outcomes, you cannot express them both on the same consistent scale using only rational numbers.

So even if it were true that no single measuring device can produce an uncountably infinite number of possible outputs, that still does not imply that the rationals are sufficient for representing measurements in general.
 
  • #46
Dale said:
I am not convinced that is true. On what basis do you make that claim? Both classically and in QM there are measurements with an uncountably infinite number of possible outputs.
If I were an experimental physicist, I would not say that an experiment could produce any one of an uncountable infinity of outcomes. If I were using modern digital, computerized equipment that claim would be patently false.

Similarly, if I were asked to produce a number, then whatever process I devise would ultimately choose from a predefined finite set - with the specific set dependent on the process. I'm not convinced that, for example, "throwing a dart at a dart board" is an uncountable random number generator.

That doesn't stop you believing you can generate any real number at random or from an experiment. Since we know that most real numbers are not describable, you would at least have to admit that generating a number or measurement outcome excludes actually providing the number explicitly or reporting the result of that measurement. I'm not convinced by an argument that says "I've generated a real number, but I can't say what it is". Or, "I've made a measurement, but I can't say what the outcome actually is."

Perhaps we just have a difference of opinion on what constitutes (the outcome of) a measurement.
 
  • #47
fresh_42 said:
I think this contains every aspect of our discussion here.
You mean it converges incredibly slowly? :smile:
 
  • Haha
  • Like
Likes mathwonk, Haborix, fresh_42 and 2 others
  • #48
Vanadium 50 said:
You mean it converges incredibly slowly? :smile:
I didn't know the metaphor was that good!
 
  • #49
PeroK said:
Perhaps we just have a difference of opinion on what constitutes (the outcome of) a measurement
Perhaps. Because I do see a measurement as a physical process, I tend to think that the connection between measurements and numbers is artificial. Something that we choose as a convention, not something forced on us by nature.

PeroK said:
If I were using modern digital, computerized equipment that claim would be patently false.
Measurements existed long before computers.

There is a dial or a gauge or a display, but is that the measurement or is the measurement the physical process that occurs on the other side of the instrument? Maybe calling the physical process a measurement is impractical.

PeroK said:
if I were asked to produce a number, then whatever process I devise would ultimately choose from a predefined finite set - with the specific set dependent on the process
This brings me back to the consistent scale. Suppose we have two processes, each with their respective predefined finite sets, that are to be measured on the same consistent scale. Can you guarantee that they are always rationally related? If not, then wouldn’t you find it more convenient to use real numbers?

PeroK said:
Since we know that most real numbers are not describable, you would at least have to admit that generating a number or measurement outcome excludes actually providing the number explicitly or reporting the result of that measurement
Yes, I do admit that. And I don’t have a counter argument for it.
 
Last edited:
  • #50
Dale said:
I am not confusing them. A finite set of irrational numbers are still irrational numbers. To me that is an indication that measurements cannot be a priori restricted to rational numbers.
If I get a measurement of ##3.14159 \pm 0.0001## that doesn't contradict the theory that contains transcedental numbers in reality, right? Still the measurement returns rational numbers.
 

Similar threads

Back
Top