straycat said:
This is a good analogy. To calculate the orbital of a planet (say Mars), we take as input the masses, intial positions, and initial velocities of the sun, planets, and other objects in the solar system, and plug these into Newton's equation, which spits out the solution x_mars(t). (We could then talk about the "Isaac rule" which states that "x(t) is interpreted as the trajectory.")
Worse! The number of planets will even CHANGE THE FORM of Newton's equation: the number of 1/r^2 terms in the force law for each planet will be different to whether there are 2, 3, 5, 12, 2356 planets. In other words, the DIMENSION OF THE PHASE SPACE defines (partly) the form of Newton's equation.
Likewise, to calculate the probability associated with a given observation, we take the initial state of the system, which includes stuff like the particle's spin, which includes the total number of possible spin states, and plug this into the Schrodinger equation, which spits out the amplitudes a_n.
In the same way, the FORM of the Schroedinger equation (or better, of the Hamiltonian) will depend upon the spins of the particles ; and this time not only the number of terms, but even the STRUCTURE of the Hamiltonian: a Hamiltonian for a spin-1/2 particle CANNOT ACT upon the Hilbert space of a spin-1 particle: it is not the right operator on the right space.
So you are saying that the probability of, say, spin up is independent of the total number of eigenstates (two in this case), because it depends only upon a_up. But isn't this like saying that the trajectory of Mars is independent of the trajectories of the other planets, because it depends only on x_mars(t)? Obviously this statement is false, because you cannot change (say) x_jupiter(t) without inducing a change in x_mars(t) as well.
I was referring to the number of eigenspaces of the hermitean measurement operator, NOT about the unitary dynamics (which is of course sensitive to the number of dimensions of HILBERTSPACE, which is nothing else but the number of physical degrees of freedom). The eigenspaces of the hermitean measurement operator, however, depend entirely on the measurement to be performed (the different, distinguishable, results). When the measurement is complete, then all eigenspaces are one-dimensional. But clearly that's not possible, because that means an almost infinite amount of information.
The hermitean measurement operator is in fact just a mathematically convenient TRICK to say which different eigenspaces of states correspond to distinguishable measurement results (and to include a name = real number for these results). What actually counts is the slicing up of the hilbert space in slices of subspaces which "give the same results".
The extraction of probabilities in quantum theory, comes from the confrontation of two quantities:
1) the wavefunction |psi> and 2) the measurement operator (or better, the entire set of eigenspaces) {E_1,E_2...E_n},
and the result of this confrontation has to result in assigning a probability to each distinct outcome.
I tried to argue in my paper that every real measurement always has only a finite number of eigenspaces {E_1...E_n} ; that is to say, the result of a measurement can always be stored in a von Neumann computer with large, but finite, memory. You can try to fight this, and I'm sure you'll soon run into thermodynamical problems (and you'll even turn into a black hole

).
As such, when I do a specific measurement, so when I have a doublet: {|psi>,{E_1...E_n}}, then I need to calculate n numbers, p_1,... p_n, which are the predicted probabilities of outcomes associated, respectively, to E_1 ... E_n.
This means that p_i ({|psi>,{E_1...E_n}}) in general.
This means that p_i can change completely if we change ANY of the E_j. On the other hand, FOR A GIVEN SET OF {E_1...E_n}, they have to span a Kolmogorov probability measure. But FOR A DIFFERENT SET, we can have ANOTHER probability measure.
The Born rule says that p_i is given by <psi|P_i|psi> (if psi is normalized), where P_i is the projector on E_i. The APP says that p_1 = 1/k, with k the number of projectors which do not annihilate |psi>.
Non-contextuality is the claim that p_i can only depend upon |psi> and E_i. Gleason's theorem says then, that IF WE REQUIRE that p_i is ONLY a function of |psi> and E_i (no matter what the other E_k are, and how many there are), then the ONLY solution is the Born rule. If the probability for a measurement to say that the state is in E_i can only depend upon E_i itself, and the quantum state |psi>, then the only solution is the Born rule.
This rules out the APP, for the APP needs to know the number k of eigenspaces which contain a component of |psi>. The APP is hence a non-non-contextual rule. It needs to know 'the context' of the measurement in WHICH we are trying to calculate the probability of |psi> to be in E_i.
To sum up: if we assume non-contextuality, this means (correct me if I am wrong) that we are assuming that the probability of the n^th outcome depends only on a_n and not on anything else, such as the total number N of eigenspaces. My difficulty is that I do not see how this assumption is tenable, given that you cannot calculate a_n without knowing (among other things) the total number of eigenspaces. It would be analogous to the assumption that the trajectory of Mars is independent of the trajectory of Jupiter.
No, that's because you're confusing two different sets of dimensions. The physical situation determines the number of dimensions in Hilbert space, and the dynamics (the unitary evolution) is dependent upon that only. But there's no discussion about the number of dimensions of Hilbert space (the number of physical degrees of freedom).
The number of EIGENSPACES is related to the resolution and kind of the measurement, in that many physical degrees of freedom will give identical measurement results, which are then lumped into ONE eigenspace. It is more about HOW WE DISTRIBUTE the physical degrees of freedom over the DIFFERENT measurement outcomes, and how this relates to the probability of outcome.
Non-contextuality says that if we perform TWO DIFFERENT measurements, but which happen to have a potential outcome in common (thus, have one of their E_i in common), that we should find the same probability for that outcome, for the two different cases. It is a very reasonable requirement at first sight.