Exploring Non-Locality in dBB Theory: Insights from EPR and Bell's Inequalities

In summary, dBB is a non-local theory that is often used as an alternative to non-realist explanations. The non-locality in dBB arises when trying to make a 2nd order differential equation for the trajectories, while the 1st order equation remains completely local. Some researchers have proposed adding non-realistic elements, such as the Quantum Trajectory Method, to make the theory more useful, but the non-locality in dBB remains a topic of debate and is not fully understood. More research and potential explanations for the non-locality in dBB would be appreciated.
  • #176
ok, thanks for the link, I guess you can always argue that dBB predicts same measurements as standard non-relativistic QM.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #177
Demystifier said:
Here it is:
http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/1010.2082

It reproduces all predictions of QM. However, it is not completely local; it requires initial nonlocal correlations between the particle positions. Yet, it is much more local than standard Bohmian mechanics in the sense that nonlocal forces can be eliminated by appropriate choice of parameterization of the particle trajectories. ALL nonlocality is encoded in the initial conditions.

Hey hey hey! This paper exactly describes what I was talking about on page one of this thread (my third post)! This is just the Quantum Trajectory Method done relativistically. So the integral curves then do interact locally? (except for the initial conditions)

hallelujah
You should know the integral curves are continuous versions of the Consistent Histories studied by Robbert Griffiths (I had him for a class as an undergrad). It might help you to read up on them. I don't recommend his book though it's not very well written. There are only a handful of books written on the subject though.

Basically, what Griffiths concluded is that consistent histories are never unique. There are always other histories that describe the same situation, and the descriptions can never be taken to be simultaneously true. It's a perfect description of quantum complementarity
 
Last edited:
  • #178
Oh, maybe you haven't yet noticed that you can get all of the dynamics just from the initial set of integral curves and the initial [tex]|\Psi|^2[/tex] (at least non-relativistically you can do this. it might break down somewhere in the relativistic case). I noticed that your paper gets all of its dynamics from the wavefunction without any back reaction from the integral curves. I guess you probably cannot tell me if those interactions are purely local. However, you claim that the velocities can be made to come from a local differential equation. I cannot see this myself, but if it is true then I suppose that means that the interaction between [tex]|\Psi^2|[/tex] and the integral curves must be local (since the wavefunction can always be decomposed into those two components)

You've probably noticed though that the integral curves are defined everywhere in configuration space. For a 2-particle system, there is an integral curve going through (x1, x2) and an integral curve going through (x1, x2+[tex]\epsilon[/tex]) so it doesn't make any sense to try to separate the positions of the particles - both of their positions are simultaneously needed to talk about the state in configuration space. So the fact that the velocity of one particle depends strongly on the position of the other particles for an entangled state isn't a problem. Of course it does! That's essentially what entanglement means and there's nothing non-local with it in this picture of integral curves through configuration space.
 
Last edited:
  • #179
in the paper I linked to http://arxiv.org/abs/0903.3878 , the author claims that a Bell-CHSH inequality shows that trajectories fail in the non-relativistic case. Don't you have to introduce a spin component even in this case, ie modify the pilot wave to a C^2 valued function including the spin?
 
  • #180
Demystifier said:
Here it is:
http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/1010.2082

It reproduces all predictions of QM. However, it is not completely local; it requires initial nonlocal correlations between the particle positions. Yet, it is much more local than standard Bohmian mechanics in the sense that nonlocal forces can be eliminated by appropriate choice of parameterization of the particle trajectories. ALL nonlocality is encoded in the initial conditions.

IMHO you are wrong when describing the initial correlations between particle positions as non-local. I think that the source of this misunderstanding comes from a wrong view of what "initial conditions" mean.

The "initial conditions" in an experiment are nothing but the position/momenta of the particles at the beginning of the experiment. They are by no means "initial" for the system itself which has a history going back to the Big-Bang. The situation is analogous with an astronomical observation of the solar system. The position/momenta of the planets are correlated, but is this evidence for non-locality? I think not.

I think that the "initial nonlocal correlations" would necessarily appear in any deterministic theory of motion where particles interact at a distance and they are a direct consequence of the evolution of the system from the Big-Bang till now.
 
  • #181
ueit said:
IMHO you are wrong ...
IMHO, you have not actually read the paper (only the abstract).
 
  • #182
Demystifier said:
IMHO, you have not actually read the paper (only the abstract).

I have read it. In the conclusion you state:

To provide consistency with statistical predictions of QM, one must assume that the a priori probabilities of initial particle positions Xμ a (0) are given by (15). Thus, all nonlocality can be ascribed to initial nonlocal correlations between the particle spacetime positions.

Why do you think that the particles having a certain distribution is a sign of non-locality? It can be a result of the Big-Bang itself, or it can be a consequence of the past interactions, prior to the beginning of the experiment.
 
  • #183
ueit said:
Why do you think that the particles having a certain distribution is a sign of non-locality? It can be a result of the Big-Bang itself, or it can be a consequence of the past interactions, prior to the beginning of the experiment.
First, you should note that "initial" in this paper refers to s=0, not to t=0. Thus, "initial" does not necessarily mean "at the big bang", or "at a spacelike hypersurface". In fact, a part of the "initial conditions" may even be in the future. See the picture on page 8 of the attachment in
https://www.physicsforums.com/blog.php?b=2240

Second, what initial conditions have to do with nonlocality? Well, if initial conditions involve nonlocal correlations (which they do, according to the paper), then there is something nonlocal about that. It is not much more than a purely linguistic tautology: if something is nonlocal (whatever that means), then it is nonlocal.

But what causes this nonlocality? Well, the paper does not attempt to answer this question. Just like most physical theories do not attempt to answer why the initial conditions are such as they are.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #184
ueit said:
The position/momenta of the planets are correlated, but is this evidence for non-locality? I think not.
Good analogy. If you think that way, you may think of the theory (in the paper) as being completely local.

ueit said:
I think that the "initial nonlocal correlations" would necessarily appear in any deterministic theory of motion where particles interact at a distance and they are a direct consequence of the evolution of the system from the Big-Bang till now.
Perhaps it is true that you will get SOME initial nonlocal correlations. But can you get initial nonlocal correlations EXACTLY EQUAL TO THOSE PREDICTED BY QM? I don't think so.
 
  • #185
Demystifier: Could you respond to my post at the top of this page (page 12)? Maybe I'm mistaken, but it really seems to me like your paper is describing exactly what I was asking about on page 1.
 
  • #186
LukeD said:
Hey hey hey! This paper exactly describes what I was talking about on page one of this thread (my third post)! This is just the Quantum Trajectory Method done relativistically. So the integral curves then do interact locally? (except for the initial conditions)

hallelujah
You should know the integral curves are continuous versions of the Consistent Histories studied by Robbert Griffiths (I had him for a class as an undergrad). It might help you to read up on them. I don't recommend his book though it's not very well written. There are only a handful of books written on the subject though.

Basically, what Griffiths concluded is that consistent histories are never unique. There are always other histories that describe the same situation, and the descriptions can never be taken to be simultaneously true. It's a perfect description of quantum complementarity
I don't know what exactly do you mean by "quantum trajectory method", but my approach does not have much in common with consistent histories of Griffiths.

Yet, the answer to your question is - yes. More precisely, different particles do not have a direct mutual interaction at all. Instead, each particle is guided by another local current. Yet, each of these currents is calculated from the common non-separable wave function.

EDIT: If by quantum trajectory method you mean the method by Lopreore and Wyatt, then my approach does not have much to do with it either.
 
Last edited:
  • #187
Demystifier said:
Yet, the answer to your question is - yes. More precisely, different particles do not have a direct mutual interaction at all. Instead, each particle is guided by another local current. Yet, each of these currents is calculated from the common non-separable wave function.

Ok, I see what you're saying. But I think your idea has much more in common with both Consistent Histories and the Quantum Trajectory Method than you think. The complete set of trajectories IS a Consistent History. It matches the mathematical definition. There is really no way around that.

As far as the Quantum Trajectory Method - it works in non-relativistic QM, but I don't know about relativistic QM. You haven't taken advantage of the method, but I'm dying to know if you can do it relativistically. In the non-relativistic theory, you can separate the N-particle wavefunction [tex]\Psi(q1,...qN,t)[/tex] into 2 parts, [tex]\rho = |\Psi(q1,...,qN,t)|^2[/tex] and N velocity fields, one for each particle, v_i(q1,...,qN,t). You can then solve for 2 local, coupled differential equations that describe the evolutions of [tex]\rho[/tex] and the velocity fields as functions of time.
You already have the velocity fields, but you're still using the full wave function to describe their evolution. The velocity fields exist as a "component" of the wavefunction. You can pull them out.
 
  • #188
LukeD said:
As far as the Quantum Trajectory Method - it works in non-relativistic QM, but I don't know about relativistic QM.
I far as I understand it, the quantum trajectory method works only for wave equations which are first-order equations in time derivatives, and only for wave functions without spin. The relativistic Klein-Gordon equation does not satisfy the first condition, while the relativistic Dirac equation does not satisfy the second condition.
 
  • #189
LukeD said:
The complete set of trajectories IS a Consistent History. It matches the mathematical definition. There is really no way around that.
OK, but in the consistent history approach no set of consistent histories takes a preferred role. So if my trajectories are one such set, there is still a plenty of other such sets, so my set does not play any particularly important role in the CH approach.
 
  • #190
Demystifier said:
OK, but in the consistent history approach no set of consistent histories takes a preferred role. So if my trajectories are one such set, there is still a plenty of other such sets, so my set does not play any particularly important role in the CH approach.

Correct. In particular, when you have spin, the set of trajectories in position space is non-unique. This means that there are multiple sets of trajectories that will answer all your position questions. You said that the Quantum Trajectory Method does not work when you have spin. I don't understand why it doesn't. Could you point me towards a paper?

If you want to answer questions in a different basis (say momentum), you can do it with the dBB paths, but it's not very straight forward (as you know, momentum is not just mv). It's much easier to just construct trajectories in momentum space. Of course you cannot combine your conclusions between the position and momentum space representations because the operators don't commute. Inserting a position measurement into your momentum space trajectories would cause an interaction that changes the dynamics.

So I think you already know this, but the point I'm trying to make is that your trajectories don't have a special role aside from the fact that they answer all your position questions. (The position trajectories also satisfy a simple differential equation. It's not so nice for trajectories in other bases)
 
  • #191
LukeD said:
You said that the Quantum Trajectory Method does not work when you have spin. I don't understand why it doesn't. Could you point me towards a paper?
I don't know any paper claiming this, that is only my own conclusion based on my superficial understanding of QT method. It seems to me that you cannot reconstruct the 2-COMPONENT wave function from trajectories and density (involving a summation over 2 components). Do you know a paper claiming the opposite?
 
  • #192
Ah ok, I see the problem. Well, I will think about this and see if I can come up with a solution. I suspect that the answer might be that you need to enlarge your configuration space to include both position and spin (though the treatment of spin is certainly not trivial. a naive approach seems unlikely to work. the solution needs to be firmly grounded in Consistent Histories)

I've barely found a single paper on the Quantum Trajectory method. I've never seen a treatment of spin.
 
  • #193
Demystifier said:
Perhaps there is nothing wrong with it, but looks ugly. Too many possibilities are allowed, so how to know which foliation is the right one? In the absence of direct experimental evidence for a theory, simplicity and mathematical elegance should be the main guiding principles.
Much before there is Ockham's razor, which suggests, in my opinion, not to introduce entities like whole four-dimensional spacetime into existence without necessity, if a three-dimensional space does the same job equally well, and without any fatalistic implications.

Then, there are not too many possibilities. If you are really looking for a preferred foliation, the harmonic condition gives a very nice candidate, which gives all the properties necessary for preferred frames, namely an essential simplification for the equations of GR.
 
  • #194
Ilja, your arguments certainly make sense. Yet, such a view is not without difficulties. For example, consider a spacetime with a horizon, e.g., a black hole. Is there a coordinate singularity at the horizon in harmonic coordinates? I am afraid there is, which constitutes a problem.
 
  • #195
Demystifier said:
... consider a spacetime with a horizon, e.g., a black hole. Is there a coordinate singularity at the horizon in harmonic coordinates? I am afraid there is, which constitutes a problem.

Let's distinguish here two cases: First, my own theory of gravity (http://ilja-schmelzer.de/gravity), which is slightly different from GR. In fact, the only reason to modify the GR equations was to obtain the harmonic condition as an Euler-Lagrange equation. But the Lagrange formalism has an inherent "action equals reaction" symmetry, so the influence of the metric on the harmonic coordinates leads to a backward influence of the harmonic coordinates on the metric. As a consequence, if the coordinates become infinite, this influence would also become infinite - and, as a consequence, it does not happen. So, in this theory the collapse stops shortly before horizon formation and the theories allows for stable gravastars slightly greater than their horizon size. So, no problem here.

But the problem is also not really a problem in GR + harmonic condition. Here, indeed, during the collapse the harmonic time becomes infinite. But now we have to interpret this. In the Lorentz interpretation, the preferred coordinate defines the true time, all what really exists is what exists now in terms of true time. Instead, GR proper time is a particular, philosophically unimportant showing of particular devices named clocks.

Now, clock time dilation can become infinite, so that the integral defining proper time τ along a path from now to infinite true time may be finite. But this is of no philosophical importance, because τ has no such importance. Simply the numbers shown by clocks never (in true time t) become greater than a given number τ. Big deal.
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
7
Views
1K
Replies
50
Views
3K
Replies
80
Views
7K
Replies
4
Views
992
Replies
93
Views
4K
Replies
44
Views
3K
Replies
17
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
3
Replies
87
Views
5K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
23
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
Back
Top