I Entanglement swapping, monogamy, and realism

  • #101
kurt101 said:
I am using the general realist position that John Bell and Einstein use when they refer to spooky action at a distance.
I'm not sure either Bell or Einstein made the same claims as you are making. That is why you should give a specific reference.

kurt101 said:
in a realist cause and effect interpretation that I am using it is just the test that reveals the correlation, not what causes the correlation.
If you think either Einstein or Bell made this claim, please give a specific reference. On its face, what you describe here and in the rest of your post looks like a local hidden variable interpretation of the sort that is ruled out by Bell's Theorem.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #102
vanhees71 said:
Any possible causal effect on the outcome of measurements on photons 1 and/or 4 can only be in the future lightcone of the registration of photons 2&3 in this BSM, i.e., if you do the local measurements on photons 1 and 4 spacelike separated from this BSM there cannot be any causal influence of the BSM on photons 1 and 4 before measured, provided you accept microcausality
As I commented earlier (in response to someone else, I believe), this leads to what seems like a highly implausible conclusion: that the BSM has a causal effect on photons 1 & 4 only for the case where the BSM is in the past light cone of the 1 & 4 measurements. But both experimental results and the QM math predict the same outcomes regardless of the spacetime relationship of the measurements--whether the BSM is in the past light cone, spacelike separated, or in the future light cone of the 1 & 4 measurements. The simplest conclusion from all this is that, whatever is going on, it's the same for all three of those cases, so if whatever is going on can't be a "causal effect" by whatever definition of "causal effect" you are using, this would be the case when the BSM is in the past light cone of the 1 & 4 measurements, as well as when it is not.
 
  • #103
[EDIT: This is not well formulated, as pointed out in #104; One should never discuss QT in words, only in formulae. See the clarification in #105]

There is no causal effect of the BSM on photons 2&3 on the outcome of measurments on photons 1&4 when the BSM and these measurements are space-like separated. This is a mathematical fact, if you use microcausal QFT, but that's not an implausible conclusion, if you accept that the observed entanglement of 1&4 in the ensemble selected through the BSM on 2&3 is due to the correlations described by the entanglement of the photon pairs 1&2 and 3&4 in the initial state, and that's indeed all what the QFT formalism tells you. So there's no "causation" but "correlation", and there's no implausibility or contradiction whatsoever.

Indeed, in this measurement it doesn't matter, whether the BSM on 2&3 and the measurements on 1&4 are space-like or time-like separated. The only point is that if you make sure that the measurements are space-like separated that there cannot be a causal effect of the BSM on the measurement outcome on 1&4, and this argument you find regularly in experiments with entangled states, and indeed this argument is consistent with the microcausality condition of QFT.

E.g., it was a big breakthrough when Zeilinger et al realized the "teleportation protocol" where this spacelike separation was ensured to exclude some (hidden) causal influences, i.e., excluding the "locality loophole". I think this was in a paper in 1997 or so. In fact it was also realized in Aspects seminal measurements in the early 1980ies. If needed, I can try to find the references.
 
Last edited:
  • #104
vanhees71 said:
if you accept that the observed entanglement of 1&4 in the ensemble selected through the BSM on 2&3 is due to the correlations described by the entanglement of the photon pairs 1&2 and 3&4 in the initial state, and that's indeed all what the QFT formalism tells you.
I don't understand. In the initial state there is no correlation between the 1&2 and 3&4 pairs. So how can there be any correlations between 2&3 or 1&4 in the initial state?
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question
  • #105
1&2 are in a Bell state as well as 3&4, i.e., each of these pairs is maximally entangled. There are no correlations between 2&3 or 1&4 in the initial state. I haven't claimed anything like that.

Now if you project to a Bell state of 2&3, in the so prepared subensemble 2&3 are fully entangled, because they are prepared to be in a Bell state. Due to the entanglement of 1&2 and 3&4 this implies that for this subensemble also 1&4 are in a Bell state.

It's a easy, although some elaborate calculation, as described by Jennewein et al in

https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0201134

It's more easily seen in the 2nd-quantization notation. The four Bell states of a photon pair with momentum labels ##j## and ##k## are created from the Vakuum by
$$\hat{\Psi}_{jk}^{\dagger \pm} \rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}[\hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,H) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_k,V) \pm \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,V) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_k,H)],$$
$$\hat{\Phi}_{jk}^{\dagger \pm} \rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}[\hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,H) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_k,H) \pm \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_j,V) \hat{a}^{\dagger}(\vec{p}_k,V)].$$
Then the initial four-photon state can then be written in two forms,
$$|\Psi_{1234} \rangle = \hat{\Psi}_{12}^{\dagger -} \hat{\Psi}_{34}^{\dagger-} |\Omega \rangle,$$
but this can as well be written as
$$|\Psi_{1234} \rangle=\frac{1}{2} (\hat{\Psi}_{23}^{\dagger +} \hat{\Psi}_{14}^{\dagger +} - \hat{\Psi}_{23}^{\dagger -} \hat{\Psi}_{14}^{\dagger -}-\hat{\Phi}_{23}^{\dagger +} \hat{\Phi}_{14}^{\dagger +} + \hat{\Phi}_{23}^{\dagger -} \hat{\Phi}_{14}^{\dagger -})|\Omega \rangle.$$
The former notation shows that photon pairs (12) and (34) are each in the polarization-singlet Bell state but (14) and (23), i.e, are uncorrelated.

The latter notation shows that if you project pair (23) to either of the four Bell state the pair (14) must be found in the same Bell state. In Pan et al's work, which we discuss here, (23) has been projected to the polarization-singlet state, and it has been demonstrated that then also the pair (14) is then in the same polarization-singlet state. This happens with probability 1/4.
 
Last edited:
  • #106
vanhees71 said:
There are no correlations between 2&3 or 1&4 in the initial state. I haven't claimed anything like that.
Yes, you did, in what I already quoted from you:

vanhees71 said:
the observed entanglement of 1&4 in the ensemble selected through the BSM on 2&3 is due to the correlations described by the entanglement of the photon pairs 1&2 and 3&4 in the initial state
This can only explain entanglement between 1 & 4 if there are correlations between 1 & 4 in the initial state. But now you say (correctly) that there aren't.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #107
Sigh. What I wanted, of course to say, is that the photons in pair (12) and the photons in pair (34) are entangled. One should never use words. Please see #105 for clarification.
 
  • #108
vanhees71 said:
What I wanted, of course to say, is that the photons in pair (12) and the photons in pair (34) are entangled.
Yes, I agree with that, in the initial state. But what about the final state, after the BSM is done?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #109
PeterDonis said:
Yes, I agree with that, in the initial state. But what about the final state, after the BSM is done?
After you project (23) in one of the four Bell states, (14) must necessarily be in the same Bell state (see #105). I think nobody disagrees with this.

The point, however, is that this is not due to some "spooky interaction at a distance" between the spacelike separated BSM projection measurement on (23) and photons 1 and 4 but simply due to the correlations due to entanglement of pair (12) and the entanglement of (34) in the initial state (of course (14) and (23) are not entangled in the initial state).
 
  • Like
Likes akvadrako
  • #110
vanhees71 said:
After you project (23) in one of the four Bell states, (14) must necessarily be in the same Bell state (see #105). I think nobody disagrees with this.
Nobody disagrees with the math, but I think there is considerable disagreement on how to interpret it.

vanhees71 said:
simply due to the correlations due to entanglement of pair (12) and the entanglement of (34) in the initial state
But how does this work? The math doesn't say. If you are satisfied with just pointing at the math and leaving any question the math doesn't answer unanswered, that's fine. But many people aren't; that's why this thread exists. And it doesn't seem like that's the position you're taking anyway: you're asserting what I quoted above as an explanation; you're not saying that no explanation is required at all.

On its face, it seems like you are describing a local hidden variable model of the kind that is ruled out by Bell's Theorem.
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question and DrChinese
  • #111
Morbert said:
Consider a pair of spacelike separated entangled particles in the state ##|\uparrow_A\uparrow_B\rangle + |\downarrow_A\downarrow_B\rangle##. You have particle ##A## and I have ##B##. You measure ##A## in the ##\{\uparrow, \downarrow\}## basis and obtain the outcome ##\uparrow##, so you know that if I measure ##B##, I will obtain the outcome ##\uparrow##. My questions to you:

i) If, for the same experimental run (i.e. not merely a new/different run) you had instead not performed a measurement, would I still have been guaranteed to obtain the outcome ##\uparrow##?

ii) Is your answer to i) interpretantion-dependent, or enforced by the formalism of QM? Or can QM even concern such questions that are not strictly resolvable by experiment?
I would agree with @vanhees71 :

i) No, because all you know for the full ensemble is that your particle is ideally unpolarized. You simply get in 50% of the cases up and in 50% of the cases down (in the usual statistical sense).

DrC: You must look at the full initial and final contexts. The general rule is not to ascribe a specific value to an unmeasured observable.

ii) It may be interpretation dependent. ...


There are interpretations that answer i. differently. A true realistic interpretation would say there is a specific value independent of the act of measurement, even if it is unknowable in principle.
 
  • #112
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure either Bell or Einstein made the same claims as you are making. That is why you should give a specific reference.
What I meant is that Bell or Einstein, used the phrasing of action at a distance in their papers. For example Bell uses it in his BERTLMANN'S SOCKS AND THE NATURE OF REALITY paper: https://hal.science/jpa-00220688/document
PeterDonis said:
If you think either Einstein or Bell made this claim, please give a specific reference.
I don't.
PeterDonis said:
On its face, what you describe here and in the rest of your post looks like a local hidden variable interpretation of the sort that is ruled out by Bell's Theorem.
I am NOT describing a local hidden variable theory. The action that I am using is the spooky action at a distance like Bell uses in his BERTLMANN'S SOCKS AND THE NATURE OF REALITY paper: https://hal.science/jpa-00220688/document.
 
  • #113
kurt101 said:
What I meant is that Bell or Einstein, used the phrasing of action at a distance in their papers.
That's just a phrasing to describe the issue. It doesn't describe any particular interpretation.

kurt101 said:
I am NOT describing a local hidden variable theory.
Then I have no idea what "realist" interpretation you think you are using or what you think it says. All you are doing is describing the issue under discussion. That is pointless; the discussion is not about describing the issue, it's about what possible resolutions of it might be.
 
  • #114
vanhees71 said:
1. After you project (23) in one of the four Bell states, (14) must necessarily be in the same Bell state (see #105). I think nobody disagrees with this.

2. The point, however, is that this is ... simply due to the correlations due to entanglement of pair (12) and the entanglement of (34) in the initial state (of course (14) and (23) are not entangled in the initial state).
1. Agreed by me.

2. What does this even mean? What correlations? You agree that (14) are NOT entangled in the initial state (good, we agree). And all of them (in the ideal case) are entangled in one of the 4 Bell states in the final state (even if that particular state is unknown).

I have said this before: Certainly there is nothing that connects the successful swap to any change in the statistical relationship of the (14) pairs in *your* reading of the experiment. But we are talking about perfect correlations and violation of Bell inequalities here. According to your reading, EVERY entangled pair anywhere in the universe at any time could be shown to have the same Bell correlations with (12) or (34) - and each other. Because in your mind, those correlations are present (pre-existing) in any 2 entangled pairs - they are just waiting to be uncovered. (Since of course, nothing actual happens/changes with a BSM - in your worldview).

How do you make any physical sense of that? Any 2 entangled pairs anywhere have these hidden correlations, waiting to be revealed? Are you really saying that?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #115
DrChinese said:
1. Agreed by me.

2. What does this even mean? What correlations? You agree that (14) are NOT entangled in the initial state (good, we agree). And all of them (in the ideal case) are entangled in one of the 4 Bell states in the final state (even if that particular state is unknown).

I have said this before: Certainly there is nothing that connects the successful swap to any change in the statistical relationship of the (14) pairs in *your* reading of the experiment. But we are talking about perfect correlations and violation of Bell inequalities here. According to your reading, EVERY entangled pair anywhere in the universe at any time could be shown to have the same Bell correlations with (12) or (34) - and each other. Because in your mind, those correlations are present (pre-existing) in any 2 entangled pairs - they are just waiting to be uncovered. (Since of course, nothing actual happens/changes with a BSM - in your worldview).

How do you make any physical sense of that? Any 2 entangled pairs anywhere have these hidden correlations, waiting to be revealed? Are you really saying that?

Yes, he will accept that (because the mathematical analysis will be identical for (1,2)×(3,4) than for (1,2)×(5,6) or any other entangled pair ( (7,8) , (9,10), ... ) created independently anywhere, anytime.

There will be maximally entangled subensembles (1,4) ( or (1,6), or (1,8).... depending on what projection to a BSM State we make with what pairs (2,3) (or (2,5), or (2,7)....) respectively.

He just accepts it as a given (because the mathematics of QM says that) and I think he doesn't need any "more profound" explanation.

In my case, I'm still thinking about it...
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #116
PeterDonis said:
Then I have no idea what "realist" interpretation you think you are using or what you think it says. All you are doing is describing the issue under discussion. That is pointless; the discussion is not about describing the issue, it's about what possible resolutions of it might be.
I am trying to get closure on this statement from @DrChinese who said my previous statement "Fundamentally coincidence is the driver factor that allows 1 & 4 to be entangled" doesn't make sense because BSM is the driving factor. I am trying to clarify my statement and I want to know if we understand each other.
DrChinese said:
Yours is not what I would call a realistic interpretation. "Fundamentally coincidence is the driving factor that allows 1 & 4 to be entangled" doesn't make sense, because the BSM is the driving factor. Each and every BSM results in 1 & 4 entanglement, and that does not occur otherwise.
I am using a very vanilla cause and effect realist interpretation and applying it to the case where the BSM test is done after the measurement of 1 and 4. @DrChinese says the BSM test results in 1 & 4 entanglement, but my interpretation is that the actions prior to the BSM test is what leads to the entanglement.

Here is how I describe this case from the realist perspective:
Measuring the polarization of photon 1 makes the polarizations states of 1 & 2 different. Measuring the polarization of photon 4 makes the polarization states of 3 & 4 different. When photons 2 and 3 are identical in almost all properties including polarization, the BSM test will determine they are indistinguishable and this indicates that the measurements of 1 & 4 are maximally entangled.

And here is how I describe this case differently than @DrChinese
The BSM test is what reveals the correlation, not what causes the correlation. All the actions that happen prior to the BSM test being performed is what causes the correlation between 1 & 4. If you choose not to do the BSM test, the correlation between 1 & 4 is still there, you just don't have a BSM test to select it from your measurement data.

So now that I have clarified my perspective. Is my perspective an acceptable one to hold? And if it is not acceptable, what is wrong with it?
 
  • #117
kurt101 said:
Measuring the polarization of photon 1 makes the polarizations states of 1 & 2 different. Measuring the polarization of photon 4 makes the polarization states of 3 & 4 different.
This is "realist", but it isn't local, because 1 & 2 are spatially separated when photon 1 is measured, and 3 & 4 are spatially separated when photon 4 is measured. So this is a nonlocal "action at a distance" model. You might be satisfied with that, but the others that have been objecting to the interpretation @DrChinese has been using won't be; they have been trying to defend a local interpretation, where there is no "action at a distance" even when particles are entangled, so measuring photon 1 can't change anything about photon 2, and measuring photon 4 can't change anything about photon 3.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and DrChinese
  • #118
kurt101 said:
I am using a very vanilla cause and effect realist interpretation and applying it to the case where the BSM test is done after the measurement of 1 and 4. @DrChinese says the BSM test results in 1 & 4 entanglement, but my interpretation is that the actions prior to the BSM test is what leads to the entanglement.

Here is how I describe this case from the realist perspective:
Measuring the polarization of photon 1 makes the polarizations states of 1 & 2 different. Measuring the polarization of photon 4 makes the polarization states of 3 & 4 different. When photons 2 and 3 are identical in almost all properties including polarization, the BSM test will determine they are indistinguishable and this indicates that the measurements of 1 & 4 are maximally entangled.

And here is how I describe this case differently than @DrChinese
The BSM test is what reveals the correlation, not what causes the correlation. All the actions that happen prior to the BSM test being performed is what causes the correlation between 1 & 4. If you choose not to do the BSM test, the correlation between 1 & 4 is still there, you just don't have a BSM test to select it from your measurement data.

If you assume Causality (as @vanhees71 does, for example), then naturally your explanation will center on what happens first. It does lead to awkward explanations (as the before/after scenarios will not be consistent).

Also, as @PeterDonis points out in post #117, your explanation is nonlocal - which is fine. QM is "quantum nonlocal." However, the usual point is to maintain Einsteinian causality in which no effect can occur outside of a light cone. So there is that.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #119
PeterDonis said:
It can't reveal any correlation between 1 & 4 that existed before, because there is no correlation between 1 & 4 that existed before. That's obvious from the initial state that was prepared.
The initial state that 1 & 2 were prepared in and 3 & 4 were prepared in are changed prior to when the BSM test is performed. So it is not obvious to me that 1 & 4 were not changed to a maximally entangled state prior to the BSM test.
PeterDonis said:
This is "realist", but it isn't local, because 1 & 2 are spatially separated when photon 1 is measured, and 3 & 4 are spatially separated when photon 4 is measured. So this is a nonlocal "action at a distance" model. You might be satisfied with that,
Yes, I am satisfied with this nonlocal "action" at a distance model.
PeterDonis said:
but the others that have been objecting to the interpretation @DrChinese has been using won't be; they have been trying to defend a local interpretation, where there is no "action at a distance" even when particles are entangled, so measuring photon 1 can't change anything about photon 2, and measuring photon 4 can't change anything about photon 3.
So you are saying @DrChinese and I are not really in any disagreement? I mean we probably have some disagreements in our preferred interpretation (assuming he has one), but that set aside, are you saying he is not saying my interpretation and perspective are not allowed?
 
  • #120
kurt101 said:
The initial state that 1 & 2 were prepared in and 3 & 4 were prepared in are changed prior to when the BSM test is performed.
I deleted the post you are quoting here.

kurt101 said:
I am satisfied with this nonlocal "action" at a distance model.
Ok.

kurt101 said:
So you are saying @DrChinese and I are not really in any disagreement?
Not if you're OK with nonlocal action at a distance. See his post #118.
 
  • #121
DrChinese said:
If you assume Causality (as @vanhees71 does, for example), then naturally your explanation will center on what happens first. It does lead to awkward explanations (as the before/after scenarios will not be consistent).
When you refer to awkward explanations you are referring to how to describe relativistically versus absolutely?
 
  • #122
kurt101 said:
When you refer to awkward explanations you are referring to how to describe relativistically versus absolutely?
He's referring to the fact that the actual math is the same regardless of the time ordering of the measurements--as has already been repeatedly pointed out. That means that any purported "explanation" in words that changes depending on the time ordering of the measurements has a problem in explaining how it can be consistent with the math, which doesn't depend on the time ordering of the measurements.
 
  • #123
kurt101 said:
When you refer to awkward explanations you are referring to how to describe relativistically versus absolutely?
What @PeterDonis said, which as usual he states better and more succinctly than I can. :smile:
 
  • #124
PeterDonis said:
He's referring to the fact that the actual math is the same regardless of the time ordering of the measurements--as has already been repeatedly pointed out. That means that any purported "explanation" in words that changes depending on the time ordering of the measurements has a problem in explaining how it can be consistent with the math, which doesn't depend on the time ordering of the measurements.
Ok, I don't really think that is a blocker to my perspective, but I can at least understand the push back on my perspective.

My argument to support how can it be consistent is this:

The entanglement swapping experiment where BSM test is done last, run in reverse is essentially an EPR experiment. Photons 2 & 3 start out in the same state. The reverse non-local action happens between 1 & 2. The reverse non-local action happens between 3 & 4. And the 4 ends up in a state that is entangled with 1. So intuitively this explanation should not be surprising at all.
 
  • #125
PeterDonis said:
Nobody disagrees with the math, but I think there is considerable disagreement on how to interpret it.But how does this work? The math doesn't say. If you are satisfied with just pointing at the math and leaving any question the math doesn't answer unanswered, that's fine. But many people aren't; that's why this thread exists. And it doesn't seem like that's the position you're taking anyway: you're asserting what I quoted above as an explanation; you're not saying that no explanation is required at all.

On its face, it seems like you are describing a local hidden variable model of the kind that is ruled out by Bell's Theorem.
But what else do you need as "explanation"? Of course, the quantum formalism is pretty abstract, but we don't have anything more intuitive to express this quantum behavior. Nature doesn't care about what we find intuitive!

There is no hidden variable in what I've written above. It's just QFT, and indeed there's not the slightest hint to any hidden variables from any experiment. The important point is that QFT is "local" due to the microcausality constraint, but is not "realistic", i.e., observables don't need to take determined values
 
  • #126
kurt101 said:
The reverse non-local action happens between 1 & 2. The reverse non-local action happens between 3 & 4.
But 1 & 4 don't even exist when the BSM is done in this scenario. In the "forward" version they were measured and destroyed before the BSM was done. In the "reverse" version they would have to be created somehow (and I don't know how you would do that).
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #127
DrChinese said:
1. Agreed by me.

2. What does this even mean? What correlations? You agree that (14) are NOT entangled in the initial state (good, we agree). And all of them (in the ideal case) are entangled in one of the 4 Bell states in the final state (even if that particular state is unknown).

I have said this before: Certainly there is nothing that connects the successful swap to any change in the statistical relationship of the (14) pairs in *your* reading of the experiment. But we are talking about perfect correlations and violation of Bell inequalities here. According to your reading, EVERY entangled pair anywhere in the universe at any time could be shown to have the same Bell correlations with (12) or (34) - and each other. Because in your mind, those correlations are present (pre-existing) in any 2 entangled pairs - they are just waiting to be uncovered. (Since of course, nothing actual happens/changes with a BSM - in your worldview).
I guess the problem is that it's hard to say what I want to say, and English is not my mother tong. The point is that (12) is max. entangled as well as (34). Now you take 2 from one of these entangled pairs and 3 from the other and entangle them by project them to a Bell state, which necessarily also implies entanglement of (14). The entanglement swapping is possible, because of the entanglement (i.e. the stronger-than-classical correlations described by them) of (12) and of (34). In the so selected subensemble neither (12) nor (34) are entangled (that's why it's called "swapping").
DrChinese said:
How do you make any physical sense of that? Any 2 entangled pairs anywhere have these hidden correlations, waiting to be revealed? Are you really saying that?
In a sense yes. Of course for each single system it's random, whether I'm succesful or not in swapping. It's as in the somewhat simpler case of teleportation.
 
  • #128
PeterDonis said:
This is "realist", but it isn't local, because 1 & 2 are spatially separated when photon 1 is measured, and 3 & 4 are spatially separated when photon 4 is measured. So this is a nonlocal "action at a distance" model. You might be satisfied with that, but the others that have been objecting to the interpretation @DrChinese has been using won't be; they have been trying to defend a local interpretation, where there is no "action at a distance" even when particles are entangled, so measuring photon 1 can't change anything about photon 2, and measuring photon 4 can't change anything about photon 3.
The projection of pair (23) to a Bell state is a local measurement, i.e., the involved photons interact locally with the PBS.
 
  • #129
vanhees71 said:
The projection of pair (23) to a Bell state is a local measurement, i.e., the involved photons interact locally with the PBS.
Yes. But @kurt101 is saying that this measurement also changes photons 1 and 4. That is not local. (I'm not saying you claim this, only that @kurt101 does.)
 
  • #130
vanhees71 said:
1. I guess the problem is that it's hard to say what I want to say, and English is not my mother tong.

2. The point is that (12) is max. entangled as well as (34). Now you take 2 from one of these entangled pairs and 3 from the other and entangle them by project them to a Bell state, which necessarily also implies entanglement of (14). The entanglement swapping is possible, because of the entanglement (i.e. the stronger-than-classical correlations described by them) of (12) and of (34). In the so selected subensemble neither (12) nor (34) are entangled (that's why it's called "swapping").

3. In a sense yes. Of course for each single system it's random, whether I'm successful or not in swapping. It's as in the somewhat simpler case of teleportation.

1. I have always thought your English is excellent, and in fact superior to most native English speakers. I have always assumed your mother tongue is German, but I guess I should ask.

2. It not that it "implies entanglement of (14)"... it is the cause of it.

3. This is the point I keep making: in the ideal case they are ALL successful swaps. If there are matched 1 & 4 clicks, a swap occurs (assuming the BSM setup is operating). You don't know the resulting state, but they are entangled. So there really is no subensemble in the sense you imagine. Once you realize that ALL of the matched 1 & 4 pairs are entangled and that there are no rejects, you realize that the "out" you are relying upon doesn't work. You could send the (23) pair into outer space (after the BS where they are made indistinguishable, never detecting them) and 1 & 4 would still be entangled - again you wouldn't know which Bell state they are in.

All of the (14) matched pairs are... entangled. So since they didn't start that way, as we agree, something changed. There is only one candidate cause: the BSM. Without that, none of the (14) matched pairs are entangled. None.
 
  • #131
PeterDonis said:
But 1 & 4 don't even exist when the BSM is done in this scenario. In the "forward" version they were measured and destroyed before the BSM was done. In the "reverse" version they would have to be created somehow (and I don't know how you would do that).
I don't really think that you can run the entanglement swapping experiment backwards, but if you could it looks like an EPR experiment. I mean the case where the BSM test is done after the measurement of 1 & 4. Anyways this is what made me think that my explanation might actually work.
PeterDonis said:
Yes. But @kurt101 is saying that this measurement also changes photons 1 and 4. That is not local. (I'm not saying you claim this, only that @kurt101 does.)
And just to be clear I am only saying that the 2 & 3 measurement changes photons 1 & 4 in the case where the BSM test on 2 & 3 is done before measuring 1 & 4. I thought this was @DrChinese position as well.

In the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4, I am saying that the measurement of 1 & 4 changes the photons prior to the BSM test of 2 & 3.
 
  • #132
kurt101 said:
I don't really think that you can run the entanglement swapping experiment backwards
It's not even a matter of not being able to do it in practice: you can't even build a working theoretical model of it in principle.

kurt101 said:
but if you could it looks like an EPR experiment.
No, it doesn't, because in the reversed version, photons 2 & 3 would not be entangled when they "emerge" from the "BSM" (since in the forward version they are not entangled going into the BSM). This is not even considering the fact that it is impossible to create photons 1 & 4 (which do not even exist at the time 2 & 3 "emerge" from the "BSM" in the backward versions) in just the right states to match up wtih 2 & 3.

kurt101 said:
I am only saying that the 2 & 3 measurement changes photons 1 & 4 in the case where the BSM test on 2 & 3 is done before measuring 1 & 4. I thought this was @DrChinese position as well.
@DrChinese is taking the position that the 2 & 3 BSM has the same effect (it swaps entanglements) regardless of the time ordering of the 2 & 3 vs. 1 & 4 measurement. You are not taking that position; you are saying that the BSM only has this effect if it happens first.

kurt101 said:
In the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4, I am saying that the measurement of 1 & 4 changes the photons prior to the BSM test of 2 & 3.
Yes, and that is not the position @DrChinese is taking. See above.
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question and DrChinese
  • #133
PeterDonis said:
It's not even a matter of not being able to do it in practice: you can't even build a working theoretical model of it in principle.No, it doesn't, because in the reversed version, photons 2 & 3 would not be entangled when they "emerge" from the "BSM" (since in the forward version they are not entangled going into the BSM). This is not even considering the fact that it is impossible to create photons 1 & 4 (which do not even exist at the time 2 & 3 "emerge" from the "BSM" in the backward versions) in just the right states to match up wtih 2 & 3.
Yes, you are strictly correct, but I still think there is symmetry in running the experiment backwards that looks a lot like the EPR experiment which guides intuition on why my explanation works. If you run one side in reverse, photon 2 would leave the BSM. Then when photon 1 reaches the detector (also going backwards) the spooky action in reverse would happen. Then eventually 1 & 2 would meet having the same state. So the last part if is out of order for the EPR experiment and that is a flaw in my analogy. And to make the analogy work you have to think as 1 & 2 acting together as a single photon. It is far from perfect, but it is what made me think it should work.

PeterDonis said:
@DrChinese is taking the position that the 2 & 3 BSM has the same effect (it swaps entanglements) regardless of the time ordering of the 2 & 3 vs. 1 & 4 measurement. You are not taking that position; you are saying that the BSM only has this effect if it happens first.Yes, and that is not the position @DrChinese is taking. See above.
Agreed.
 
  • #134
kurt101 said:
I still think there is symmetry in running the experiment backwards that looks a lot like the EPR experiment
Unless you can justify this claim with math (which you can't), it's personal speculation and is off limits here.
 
  • #135
PeterDonis said:
Unless you can justify this claim with math (which you can't), it's personal speculation and is off limits here.
I can write a program which I tend to think of the program as being the math, but it is not the language of math that you are looking for. Correct?

And even if I was able to translate the program to math that was acceptable, I imagine it would still fall under the grounds of speculative theory.

So unless I get something published and peer reviewed, I think I have gone as far as I can here.

I feel as if I have gotten my question answered and understand @DrChinese position.
 
  • #136
kurt101 said:
I can write a program
That's not the math of QM, that's just some program you wrote. I am talking about the standard math of QM.

kurt101 said:
even if I was able to translate the program to math that was acceptable
Or you could just use the standard math of QM. That's what it's for.
 
  • Like
Likes kurt101
  • #137
Regarding precisely "when" (14) pairs become entanglemed in the BSM experiment according to the minimalist* interpretation: The point where the minimalist interpretation makes contact with reality is in macroscopic preparations and macroscopic outcomes. Quantum states, Hermitian operators etc do not characterise the microscopic system. They instead characterise macroscopic interventions on the microscopic system. In statistical language, projectors mentioned previously in this thread like ##\{\mathbb 1_1 \otimes P_{23,i} \otimes \mathbb 1_4\}## that project to the BSM basis, select for subensembles according to BSM outcome. No other element of reality beyond the macroscopic BSM events is considered by the theory. If the experiment is modified to include a BSM on (14) as well, then projectors like ##\{\mathbb 1_2 \otimes P_{14,i} \otimes \mathbb 1_3\}## will select for subensebles according to this BSM outcome. Reality is not characterised by some time-evolution process whereby (14) entanglement is induced at some moment at or after preparation. Reality is instead *only* characterised by a collection of experimental outcomes that followed from identical preparations, with computable frequencies and correlations. Locality is readily preserved.

*By minimalist I am referring to the account of QM presented by Fuchs and Peres in articles like this one https://physicstoday.scitation.org/doi/pdf/10.1063/1.883004
 
Last edited:
  • #138
PS re/ realism and locality - For posterity I will repost the obligatory video by Gell-Mann that talks about the recovery of a local realist interpretation of measurement as revealing pre-existing properties, without recourse to hidden variables. https://www.webofstories.com/play/murray.gell-mann/165
 
  • #139
Morbert said:
the minimalist* interpretation
This seems to be more or less the interpretation that @vanhees71 is using.
 
  • #140
PeterDonis said:
This seems to be more or less the interpretation that @vanhees71 is using.
I think so too. The only possible difference is that Fuchs and Peres are also willing to talk about the likelihood of single events as well as frequencies of events in ensembles, which I am not sure vanhees is willing to do.

"When we are told that the probability of precipitation tomorrow is 35%, there is only one tomorrow." -- Fuchs and Peres
 
  • #141
Morbert said:
The only possible difference is that Fuchs and Peres are also willing to talk about the likelihood of single events
I believe their approach to probabilities is Bayesian, which treats probabilities as states of epistemic belief and so has no problem assigning probabilities to single events.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #142
Morbert said:
*By minimalist I am referring to the account of QM presented by Fuchs and Peres in articles like this one https://physicstoday.scitation.org/doi/pdf/10.1063/1.883004
PeterDonis said:
This seems to be more or less the interpretation that @vanhees71 is using.
Morbert said:
I think so too. The only possible difference is ...
No, just no. This is NOT the minimal statistical interpretation. And this is not close to vanhees71's usage of the minimal statistical interpretation either.
 
  • #143
Morbert said:
... Locality is readily preserved.

*By minimalist I am referring to the account of QM presented by Fuchs and Peres in articles like this one https://physicstoday.scitation.org/doi/pdf/10.1063/1.883004

Quantum theory is inherently nonlocal, although signal locality is respected. You - as many - have formulated requirements for some definition of nonlocality that cannot be met. Specifically, you basically reject experimental nonlocality proofs which some central observer does not experience until all of the information arrives - which is limited by signal. Circular reasoning - you have proved what you assume.

What is clearly nonlocal, as we have discussed here: An experimentalist here can create - or not - a distant biphoton from components that have never existed in a common light cone. There really is no disputing this experimental fact as I have characterized it. If you choose to reject this because it does not demonstrate signal nonlocality, that's... circular.

Logically, if there is something called "quantum nonlocality" (as I say there is) and it can be demonstrated (as it can be), but it does not feature FTL signaling: then it cannot be judged by a "macroscopic" experiment where component results must be brought together before you accept the nonlocality. Macroscopic Alice can write her results down and compare them with the measurement results of Macroscopic Bob and Victor anytime. Obviously, their combined story indicates that there is quantum nonlocality. You can't wave your hands and ignore the obvious.

Well, I guess you can... :smile:
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question
  • #144
gentzen said:
No, just no. This is NOT the minimal statistical interpretation. And this is not close to vanhees71's usage of the minimal statistical interpretation either.
Dreischner calls the account of Peres + Fuchs a minimal instrumentalist interpretation and cites Friebe (though I do not have access to the cited text). By minimal statistical interpretation, do you mean a minimal ensemble interpretation? I don't know if they are as different as you imply, but the minimal interpretation as described in this thread and others has an instrumentalist character (for example, the association of a quantum state with a preparation procedure). If there is some important distinction or misrepresentation then please be explicit.
 
Last edited:
  • #145
DrChinese said:
Quantum theory is inherently nonlocal, although signal locality is respected.
Here you are making a stronger claim that can't be categorised as a difference in interpretation. And it's one I disagree with. E.g. According to decoherent histories interpretations and minimal instrumentalist interpretations, quantum theory is no more nonlocal than classical theory.
 
  • #146
DrChinese said:
What is clearly nonlocal, as we have discussed here: An experimentalist here can create - or not - a distant biphoton from components that have never existed in a common light cone.
Sure, but we can also agree the experimenter can not "create this" without information about measurements on other entangled parts of both the components. Ie. The experimebter cant create this without this information. Do we agree?
DrChinese said:
There really is no disputing this experimental fact as I have characterized it. If you choose to reject this because it does not demonstrate signal nonlocality, that's... circular.
As we use different notions of locality, I'm fine with agreeing with you with that disclaimer.

But that form of nonlocality you refer to is not a problem per see (At least not for me). The notion of locality that is part of the often constructing principles of physics isnt the kind of locality that you speak of. The only problem is that its almost the same word for different things.

/Fredrik
 
  • #147
PeterDonis said:
This is wrong. The "event ready" signal is generated by a combination of things: the 2 & 3 photons arriving at the BSM device within the same narrow time window, and the output of the BSM indicating the particular Bell state that the BSM is set up to distinguish. This happens at the BSM, not at the initial preparation. @DrChinese is more familiar than I am with the specific papers describing the experiments, and I'm sure can give specific references to the descriptions in those papers that match the above.
I don't think the specific details are relevant. The point of the event ready signal is to select those events which can safely be assumed to be successful measurements. This doesn't add anything conceptually new to the analysis of the idealized experiment. You still have a full ensemble of events which constitue successful measurements and you decompose this full ensemble into subensembles according to the measurement result of the BSM.
DrChinese said:
For our purposes, let's assume that the 1 & 4 measurement systems (PBS plus 2 detectors for each) are positioned such that when we have a successful BSM, the 1 & 4 detectors go off at the same time (within our designated time window). We add fiber cable to make that work out, and we place them at the same spot. Additionally, we do the same with the BSM detector array. We use fiber to adjust the travel time, and route them to the same location as the 1 & 4 detectors. All 4 photons will arrive at location where all of the detectors are, and the photons will all arrive within the same time window. I am adding this little twist so you can see exactly what should be discussed when we talk about an ensemble or subset or subensemble. So what we expect, with a successful BSM, is that 4 detectors will click at almost precisely the same time. For the 1 & 4 photons, each will generate one click indicating their polarization relative to their respective PBS. The BSM detector array will register 2 clicks, one for the 2 photon and one for the 3 photon - but we won't know which is which. So 4 "simultaneous" clicks means we have a successful BSM in this setup.
These events taken together, i.e. prior to post-selection, constitute the full ensemble.
DrChinese said:
In theory: for every single case where the 1 & 4 photons are detected within the time window: they are entangled.
This sentence makes no sense without saying with respect to which data set you make it. If you consider a dataset consisting of only a single data point, it makes no sense, because the unbiased estimator of covariance is not well defined for a single data point. If you consider the full ensemble, then the statement is false. The photons 1&4 will be uncorrelated in the full ensemble. The statement is true for the post-selected subensembles only.
DrChinese said:
We may not know which of the 4 Bell states they are in - and therefore we can't perform a Bell test on them - but they ARE entangled. [...] But assuming we are good scientists, there is no subensemble yet.
No. If you don't look at a subensemble, there will not be entanglement in the data. The correlation will be zero. This follows strictly from the math.
 
  • Like
Likes akvadrako
  • #148
DrChinese said:
Quantum theory is inherently nonlocal, although signal locality is respected.
You are being imprecise on purpose here. Quantum non-locality means nothing more than the fact that Bell's inequality is violated. What you want to imply is that there are non-local cause and effect relationships. The broad consensus among physicists is that no non-local cause and effect relationship can be inferred from the data. QM can be interpreted either way.
 
  • Like
Likes lodbrok, akvadrako and Fra
  • #149
Nullstein said:
I don't think the specific details are relevant.
They most certainly are. Basing the signal on what happens at the BSM is very different from basing it on something from the initial preparation, which is what you said before.

Nullstein said:
The point of the event ready signal is to select those events which can safely be assumed to be successful measurements.
Not quite. The point of the event ready signal in these experiments is to select those events in which photons 2 & 3 are projected into the particular Bell state that the BSM is set up to uniquely detect. That doesn't mean the other events aren't successful measurements; they're just measurements whose results can't be distinguished by the humans reading the output of the apparatus. But they still involve projecting photons 2 & 3 into a Bell state and everything associated with that (for example, that photons 1 & 4 are also projected into a Bell state).

Nullstein said:
You still have a full ensemble of events which constitue successful measurements and you decompose this full ensemble into subensembles according to the measurement result of the BSM.
That's not correct for these particular experiments. The "event ready" signal runs are the only runs for which the measurement result of the BSM can be determined. The other runs involve BSM results that the humans reading the apparatus can't distinguish from each other. So the other subensembles can't be picked out. Only the "event ready" subensemble can.

It would be possible in principle to design a more sophisticated BSM that could distinguish all 4 Bell states, so that 4 subensembles could be picked out; but my understanding is that the technical difficulties in doing that in practice have not yet been figured out. In such an experiment, the "event ready" signal would be the arrival of photons 2 & 3 at the BSM within a narrow enough time window for the BSM to act on them at all (if they don't arrive within a narrow enough time window, the BSM does nothing).
 
  • #150
Let me try once more to explain the relationship between correlation and causation and how it applies to entanglement swapping:

Experimentally, we find that certain sets of data show correlation between spacelike separated variables ##A## and ##B##. In general though, correlation does not imply a cause and effect relationship between those variables, i.e. we may not conclude that ##A## caused ##B## or the other way around. Why is that?
  1. The correlation may be mediated by a third variable ##C##, i.e. ##C## caused ##A## and ##C## caused ##B##. In that case, the correlation will go away if we condition on the variable ##C##. This is called a common cause explanation. Bell's theorem proves that a common cause explanation for the EPR correlations is excluded.
  2. The correlation may arise, because we are only looking at a specific subset of the data. In particular, if we look at data which was obtained by conditioning on a common effect, then inferring causality is forbidden if the correlation goes away after summing over the common effect variable. This is the case in entanglement swapping. Here, the correlation in the subensembles will go away if we sum over the possible measurement outcomes of the BSM, i.e. if we pass to the full ensemble.
If there was still correlation between ##A## and ##B## after we have taken care of these issues, we may indeed infer causality from the fact that ##A## and ##B## are correlated. But in the case of entanglement swapping, it is just a fact that the correlation goes away after taking care of these issues, so we may not infer causality.

All of this is well understood applied statistics. It's not something I made up. This is how causal inference is taught and done in every empirical field of science. The paper https://arxiv.org/abs/1606.04523 shows that this is also well understood in the case of entanglement swapping. Robert Spekkens, one of the authors, is one of the leading researchers in quantum foundation and the application of causal inference to quantum mechanics, so this should certainly be taken seriously.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn and lodbrok
Back
Top