Ergodocity and unitary evolution

In summary: There are several reasons why this might be a problem. First of all, as I mentioned, energy conservation is a fundamental property of quantum mechanics. If ergodicity is not valid in all cases, then this might not be the most reliable way to describe the behavior of systems.Second, if ergodicity is not valid, then it is not clear what criteria we should use to choose between different possible outcomes of a quantum system. This can be a problem if we want to make predictions about the behavior of a quantum system.Finally, if ergodicity is not valid, then it is not clear what can be said about the relationship between different quantum systems. This is a problem because it can be difficult to
  • #1
A. Neumaier
Science Advisor
Insights Author
8,595
4,620
[This thread split from https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/is-collapse-indispensable.854384/] [Broken]
A. Neumaier said:
ergodicity is incompatible with unitary evolution.
akhmeteli said:
Could you please give a reference to this statement?
I don't know a reference but I can indicate a proof. Ergodicity of unitary evolution of the wave function says that for given ##\psi_0## of norm 1, ##\psi(t)=e^{-itH}\psi_0## comes for some ##t## arbitrarily close to any ##\psi## of norm 1. This is equivalent to asserting that the inner product ##\langle\psi_0|e^{itH}|\psi\rangle## gets arbitrarily close to 1. Now represent ##\psi_0## and ##\psi## in a basis where ##H## is diagonal, to verify that when ##H## is unbounded, this is for given ##\psi_0## the case only for a small minority of states ##\psi##.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
A. Neumaier said:
I don't know a reference but I can indicate a proof. Ergodicity of unitary evolution of the wave function says that for given ##\psi_0## of norm 1, ##\psi(t)=e^{-itH}\psi_0## comes for some ##t## arbitrarily close to any ##\psi## of norm 1. This is equivalent to asserting that the inner product ##\langle\psi_0|e^{itH}|\psi\rangle## gets arbitrarily close to 1. Now represent ##\psi_0## and ##\psi## in a basis where $H$ is diagonal, to verify that when ##H## is unbounded, this is for given ##\psi_0## the case only for a small minority of states $##\psi##.
I have some doubts about your definition of ergodicity. For example, it does not seem to take into account energy conservation. A similar definition for a classical system would also forbid any ergodicity, as standard evolution of a classical system conserves energy.
 
  • #3
akhmeteli said:
your definition of ergodicity. For example, it does not seem to take into account energy conservation.
According to most interpretations, energy doesn't have sharp values in QM. Almost no system is in an energy eigenstate - hence how can energy be conserved in quantum mechanics? Only ##\langle H\rangle## is conserved.

On the other hand, even if your require ##\psi_0## and ##\psi## to be restricted by having the same expectation for every conserved quantity, the same argument still applies - the closure of the trajectory ##\psi(t)## is far too small to cover any reasonable domain of state vectors.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
A. Neumaier said:
According to most interpretations, energy doesn't have sharp values in QM. Almost no system is in an energy eigenstate - hence how can energy be conserved in quantum mechanics? Only ##\langle H\rangle## is conserved.
In my book, energy is conserved in quantum mechanics as Hamiltonian commutes with itself:-) But even if you deny energy conservation in quantum mechanics, your definition of ergodicity is still unreasonable, as it requires that evolution of an eigenstate of energy bring it arbitrarily close to another eigenstate with a different eigenvalue. A similar definition in classical mechanics would require that evolution of a state with a certain energy bring it arbitrarily close to a state with a different energy, so there would be no ergodicity in classical mechanics, not even for Sinai's billiards:-)
A. Neumaier said:
On the other hand, even if your require ##\psi_0## and ##\psi## to be restricted by having the same expectation for every conserved quantity, the same argument still applies - the closure of the trajectory ##\psi(t)## is far too small to cover any reasonable domain of state vectors.
Sorry, this does not look obvious to me, and you don't have any reference.

If you give a proof here, that would be interesting, and I would appreciate such a proof, but such a proof should start with a generally accepted definition of ergodicity, not some definition introduced by you here for the first time.

Let me note that I had no intention to ask a "gotcha" question. Your statement seemed 1) interesting; 2) not obvious; 3) not obviously wrong, so I wanted to know its status. Right now it looks like this is your personal opinion.

I should also note that I have my doubts about this statement, as, for example, there is a quantum recurrence theorem (Phys. Rev. 107, 337, 1957). This is certainly not the same as ergodicity, but it makes me wonder if quantum mechanics is that much different from classical mechanics in this respect.
 
  • #5
A. Neumaier said:
I don't know a reference but I can indicate a proof. Ergodicity of unitary evolution of the wave function says that for given ##\psi_0## of norm 1, ##\psi(t)=e^{-itH}\psi_0## comes for some ##t## arbitrarily close to any ##\psi## of norm 1. This is equivalent to asserting that the inner product ##\langle\psi_0|e^{itH}|\psi\rangle## gets arbitrarily close to 1. Now represent ##\psi_0## and ##\psi## in a basis where $H$ is diagonal, to verify that when ##H## is unbounded, this is for given ##\psi_0## the case only for a small minority of states $##\psi##.

So the ergodic theorem isn't generally valid then. (Or, more reasonably, you would have to carefully qualify what situations it is meant to apply to before claiming it should hold.) Why should this be a problem for MWI?
 
  • #6
wle said:
So the ergodic theorem isn't generally valid then. [...] Why should this be a problem for MWI?
Because the observable probabilities agree only in a tiny fraction of the possible worlds (namely in those where ergodicity holds - if there is one at all) with the ensemble probabilities. Now MWI is made such the ensemble probabilities agree with the quantum mechanical predictions, while in our particular world we can measure only observable probabilities (that come from repeating experiments in this particular world). Thus MWI fails to explain why our world is so special that it belongs to the ergodic minority.
 
  • #7
A. Neumaier said:
Because the observable probabilities agree only in a tiny fraction of the possible worlds (namely in those where ergodicity holds - if there is one at all) with the ensemble probabilities.

I don't see how you've done anything to justify that (at least, not for any version of the ergodic theorem that we actually believe is true). Like akhmeteli pointed out, essentially all you're saying is that if you write ##\lvert \psi(t) \rangle = \sum_{n} a_{n}(t) \lvert n \rangle## for a (pure) quantum state in a basis ##\{\lvert n \rangle\}## that diagonalises the Hamiltonian, then the absolute values ##\lvert a_{n}(t) \rvert## of the coefficients must be independent of time for all ##n##. This is just QM's version of conservation of energy. There's nothing remarkable about this. Most serious theories and even toy models in physics obey conservation laws that imply constraints on the future evolution of an initial state. This is not something unique to QM.
 
  • #8
wle said:
I don't see how you've done anything to justify that
I had argued this under the assumption (temporarily granted by you) that the ergodic theorem doesn't hold.
Now you retracted this temporary assumption to make a different point. I'll make my argument more precise once I have more time to do so.
 
  • #9
A. Neumaier said:
I had argued this under the assumption (temporarily granted by you) that the ergodic theorem doesn't hold.
Now you retracted this temporary assumption to make a different point.

I don't see where you get that idea. There are two ideas called "ergodic theorem" in physics. One of them, the one you contradict in post #63, roughly says that a physical system will eventually visit all of the available state/configuration space (generally after some astronomically long time). The way you stated your argument was as if you assumed the ergodic theorem had unrestricted validity, i.e., it applies to any or all degrees of freedom for any physical system. You then showed an example from quantum physics showing that isn't true and concluded this was somehow a problem for MWI, rather than a more mundane example showing that, in general, not all physical systems are ergodic. I don't know any a priori reason to believe that the entire universe as a whole must be an ergodic system for instance, so I don't see any reason it should be a problem if MWI implies it is not.
 
  • #10
akhmeteli said:
I have some doubts about your definition of ergodicity. For example, it does not seem to take into account energy conservation.
Ok, let me take energy conservation into account. The argument becomes even simpler. Suppose we consider only (improper) states with a fixed energy ##E## in the continuous spectrum of a multiparticle system (and, in case you want, with all other conserved quantities required by system symmetries fixed, too) . Then ##H\psi_0=E\psi_0##. Thus ##\psi(t)=e^{-itH}\psi_0=e^{-itE}\psi_0## is parallel to ##\psi_0##, hence the subspace accessible to the trajectory is only a 1-dimensional subspace of the (for a system that can separate into more than two asymptotic parts) infinite-dimensional space of possible eigenfunctions for the eigenvalue ##E##. This is as nonergodic as one can have it!
 
  • #11
Classical evolution of states is unitary as evidenced in the Koopman-Von Neumann version of classical mechanics. If my memory serves well, it was this version of CM (with its unitary evolution of vectors in a Hilbert space) the one Von Neumann used to proves his ergodicity theorem in CM.
 
  • #12
andresB said:
Classical evolution of states is unitary as evidenced in the Koopman-Von Neumann version of classical mechanics. If my memory serves well, it was this version of CM (with its unitary evolution of vectors in a Hilbert space) the one Von Neumann used to proves his ergodicity theorem in CM.
Yes, one can use an operator formalism (using diagonal operators on a Hilbert space of phase space functions) to prove ergodic theorems in classical mechanics. But the wave function dynamics considered as a deterministic dynamical system is definitely nonergodic.
 
  • #13
A. Neumaier said:
Ok, let me take energy conservation into account. The argument becomes even simpler. Suppose we consider only (improper) states with a fixed energy ##E## in the continuous spectrum of a multiparticle system (and, in case you want, with all other conserved quantities required by system symmetries fixed, too) . Then ##H\psi_0=E\psi_0##. Thus ##\psi(t)=e^{-itH}\psi_0=e^{-itE}\psi_0## is parallel to ##\psi_0##, hence the subspace accessible to the trajectory is only a 1-dimensional subspace of the (for a system that can separate into more than two asymptotic parts) infinite-dimensional space of possible eigenfunctions for the eigenvalue ##E##. This is as nonergodic as one can have it!
Thank you. However, if the volume is finite, I would not expect a continuous spectrum? Or am I wrong? And one should not expect ergodicity for an infinite volume, be it classical mechanics or quantum mechanics. Or am I wrong again?

I still have two other questions.

1. So what is your definition of ergodicity for quantum theory?
2. Is it a generally accepted definition?

For example, my understanding is that, say, in classical mechanics, ergodicity means something like "the average over time equals the average over the ensemble". It does not look like whatever definition you use has much to do with that. However, if you use some generally accepted definition, that should be fine.
 
  • #14
akhmeteli said:
ergodicity means something like "the average over time equals the average over the ensemble".
Yes, that's the generally accepted meaning, and that's what I use. If a mixed quantum mechanical state is considered as an ensemble of pure states, the same definition makes sense in the quantum case.
akhmeteli said:
if the volume is finite, I would not expect a continuous spectrum?
The electrons in a finite piece of metal form conduction bands, which are continuous spectra. In general, it is the ability to move rather than only vibrate or rotate that makes a spectrum continuous.

The context of the original question was that MWI considers our universe [a system presumably of infinite volume; in any case it has clearly moving parts and hence a continuous energy spectrum] as a particular realization of an ensemble of universes, each of them described by a wave function. My complaint was that unless one can interpret the ensemble average as a time average (and hence is ergodic), one can infer nothing about observable probabilities (which typically come from temporal repetitions in one particular realization - the only one we have) from the ensemble probabilities postulated in MWI. Since quantum mechanics is indeed not ergodic, it means that MWI is mute about observable probabilities. It explains nothing.
 
  • #15
A. Neumaier said:
Yes, that's the generally accepted meaning, and that's what I use. If a mixed quantum mechanical state is considered as an ensemble of pure states, the same definition makes sense in the quantum case.
But what ensemble do you consider (one cannot reasonably consider an arbitrary ensemble) and what observables do you average?
A. Neumaier said:
The electrons in a finite piece of metal form conduction bands, which are continuous spectra.
I am not sure the spectrum is continuous for a finite number of electrons in a finite volume. And an infinite number of electrons in a finite volume does not make much sense.
A. Neumaier said:
In general, it is the ability to move rather than only vibrate or rotate that makes a spectrum continuous.
Again, not sure the spectrum can be continuous for a finite volume anyway.
A. Neumaier said:
The context of the original question was that MWI considers our universe [a system presumably of infinite volume; in any case it has clearly moving parts and hence a continuous energy spectrum] as a particular realization of an ensemble of universes, each of them described by a wave function. My complaint was that unless one can interpret the ensemble average as a time average (and hence is ergodic), one can infer nothing about observable probabilities (which typically come from temporal repetitions in one particular realization - the only one we have) from the ensemble probabilities postulated in MWI. Since quantum mechanics is indeed not ergodic, it means that MWI is mute about observable probabilities. It explains nothing.
Again, I doubt about a continuous spectrum for a finite volume. However, I don't mind the presumption that the Universe is infinite, so I don't mind your argument against MWI. On the other hand, I doubt there is ergodicity for an infinite volume in the classical case either.
 
  • #16
akhmeteli said:
I am not sure the spectrum is continuous for a finite number of electrons in a finite volume.
Indeed, you are probably right. But every metal reflects light, which makes the system consisting of metal and light unbounded (unless one assumes that evrey photon is absorbed somewhere in the universe...)

On the other hand, the question whether a classical unbounded system is ergodic is not relevant for the application to MWI.
 
  • #17
A. Neumaier said:
Indeed, you are probably right. But every metal reflects light, which makes the system consisting of metal and light unbounded (unless one assumes that evrey photon is absorbed somewhere in the universe...)
I am not sure I understand that: if the Universe (or any other system) has a finite volume, it has a finite volume for photons as well, and the spectrum is not continuous. If, however, you consider photons as part of an external thermostat (or is it called bath?), there is no unitary evolution anyway.
A. Neumaier said:
On the other hand, the question whether a classical unbounded system is ergodic is not relevant for the application to MWI.
MWI's problems are not my problems, but maybe an MWI's fan would say that, as classical mechanics is (arguably) a limit case of quantum mechanics, classical ergodicity can serve as an approximate justification of the Born rule in MWI. But again, this is not my problem, and again, I am not sure there is classical ergodicity in an infinite volume.
 
  • #18
akhmeteli said:
I am not sure I understand that: if the Universe (or any other system) has a finite volume, it has a finite volume for photons as well, and the spectrum is not continuous.
Yes, but my intention was to talk about an ordinary finite piece of metal in our actual universe, which seems to have infinite volume.
 
  • #19
But then, it seems like the important point is if the spectrum is continuum or not, and not unitary evolution in general.
 
  • #20
andresB said:
But then, it seems like the important point is if the spectrum is continuum or not, and not unitary evolution in general.
If the spectrum is highly degenerate then my argument still applies. If the spectrum is nondegenerate then the assumption of fixed energy makes the eigenspaces 1-dimensional, and fixed energy orbits are of course ergodic in these 1D spaces. However, quantum mechanics is trivial in 1-dimensional spaces.

Then the question is what one means by ergodicity when one evolves a state where energy is not constant. In this case one cannot argue that energy is constant, and restricting to constant expected energy yields a huge space (infinite-dimensional already for an anharmonic oscillator) that cannot be filled densely.
 
  • #21
Well, I got lost because I thought you guys were talking about discrete vs continuum spectrum and not about degenerate eigenvalues.
 
  • #22
andresB said:
Well, I got lost because I thought you guys were talking about discrete vs continuum spectrum and not about degenerate eigenvalues.
It was just that in case a system can disintegrate into more than two parts it is easy to see that part of the continuous spectrum must be infinitely degenerate, hence the simplr argument proves nonergodicity in a very direct way.
 
  • #23
A. Neumaier said:
Because the observable probabilities agree only in a tiny fraction of the possible worlds (namely in those where ergodicity holds - if there is one at all) with the ensemble probabilities. Now MWI is made such the ensemble probabilities agree with the quantum mechanical predictions, while in our particular world we can measure only observable probabilities (that come from repeating experiments in this particular world). Thus MWI fails to explain why our world is so special that it belongs to the ergodic minority.

I think I understand how ergodicity is relevant in thermodynamics: We specify the macroscopic state variables: Pressure, volume, number of particles of each type, etc. Then we use the usual statistical mechanics derivation to compute the probability of the system being somewhere in a region of phase space, given those macroscopic variables. We have two ways of understanding that probability:
  1. We form (either actually, or as a thought-experiment) an ensemble of systems that all have the same macroscopic variables, but differ in microscopic details. Then we understand the probabilistic statement as the claim that a certain fraction (or measure) of those systems are in the region of phase space of interest.
  2. We take a single system, and let it evolve in time. If the system is ergodic, then it will come arbitrarily close (in phase space) to every system in the above ensemble. Then we can interpret probabilistic statements as statements about the relative amount of time that the one system will spend in the region of phase space.
So ergodicity allows us to interpret probability measure-theoretically, on an ensemble, and also as a fraction of time, on a single system.

But I'm not sure that the same considerations are relevant to MWI. Let's look at a simpler example than MWI: rolling dice.

There are two different ways to make sense of the claim "Each outcome has a probability of 1/6":
  1. Get a large ensemble of dice-rollers to each roll one die, count the fraction (or the measure, if it's an infinite ensemble) that obtain each result.
  2. Have a single dice-roller roll one die many, many times, and compute the relative frequency of each outcome.
The usual assumption is that the relative frequency for a single die is equal (in some kind of limit) to the measure for the ensemble.

How is ergodicity relevant here?
 
  • #24
A. Neumaier said:
It was just that in case a system can disintegrate into more than two parts it is easy to see that part of the continuous spectrum must be infinitely degenerate, hence the simplr argument proves nonergodicity in a very direct way.

BUt eve if that is correct (I admit that I'm somewhat lost at this point), would that proves that unitary evolution is, in general, incompatible with ergodicity?
 
  • #25
A. Neumaier said:
Yes, but my intention was to talk about an ordinary finite piece of metal in our actual universe, which seems to have infinite volume.
Thank you for answering my questions.
 
  • #26
stevendaryl said:
How is ergodicity relevant here?
This is not what MWI does. In MWI it is the worlds that form an ensemble. Thus we have at least one world in which all throws show sixes - in fact many more since throwing dice is not the only measurable thing that happens in the world. Similarly, for any other sequence of throws that we may think of, there are plenty of worlds realizing just this. But we are actually in just one of these worlds - all others are (from our point of view) imagined, like in your case 1.

MWI ''works'' by saying that the ensemble probabilities are such that Born's rule holds. This means that if we look at enough worlds we find that most (in the sense of ensemble probaility) of the worlds [the ordinary ones] have random throw sequences, whereas an infinite minority of worlds [the exceptional ones] has throw sequences with a nontrivial pattern or correlations. Moreover, there are an even larger minority of mixed worlds where at times the dice behave random, and at other times the dice behave systematic.

Obviously we are in one of the ordinary worlds since we experience random throw sequences. But if the other worlds are as real as ours, the inhabitants of the infinitely many exceptional worlds or mixed worlds observe very different laws, and the same MWI ''explains'' their laws. Thus MWI explains every possible set of laws or unlawfulness or intermittent lawfulness. For me, this implies that MWI explains nothing.

The situation were different if MWI were ergodic. in this case, the ensemble statistics would be aritrarily closely replicated in time in each individual world, i.e., the observations of the inhabitants in each world would satisfy the same statistics, and there would be only ordinary worlds.

Without ergodicity, positing that we are in an ordinary world is equivalent to positing that the Born rule holds in our world - i.e., we assume what we would want to derive. Since we experience only one world, it is no good to argue with typicality - since this typicality is precisely what we want to infer!
 
  • #27
stevendaryl said:
ergodicity allows us to interpret probability measure-theoretically, on an ensemble, and also as a fraction of time, on a single system.
Yes, and this is important, since each single cup of tea has the properties derived from the ensemble.

Already Gibbs (who invented towards the end of the 19th century the notion of a thermodynamic ensemble) noticed (and stated explicitly) that the ensembles are fictitious repetitions, used just to be able to apply statistical intuition - although he gets deterministic results applicable to each instance.

Note that the formal developments in equilibrium thermodynamics never use the notion of repetition, so it doesn't matter in this case whether the ensemble is real or fictitious. Gibbs was well aware of that.

But if the ensemble is used to describe stochastic experiments that extend over times significant at human scales, the repetitions count. In this case it makes a big difference whether these repetitions are actual and hence affect the statistics computed from the experiments, or if they are imagined, and hence have no impact at all.
 

What is ergodicity?

Ergodicity is a property of a system in which the time average of a physical quantity is equal to its ensemble average. This means that, over time, the system will explore all possible states and the average behavior of the system is representative of the behavior of individual particles within the system.

What is unitary evolution?

Unitary evolution is a concept in quantum mechanics where the state of a system changes over time in a reversible and deterministic manner. This means that the state of a system at any given time can be calculated from its initial state and the evolution operator, which describes how the system changes over time.

How are ergodicity and unitary evolution related?

Ergodicity and unitary evolution are closely related in that both describe the behavior of a system over time. While ergodicity is a property of classical systems, unitary evolution is a concept in quantum mechanics. However, both describe how a system evolves over time in a deterministic and reversible manner.

What are some real-world examples of ergodic systems?

Some examples of ergodic systems in the natural world include the behavior of gas particles in a closed container and the movement of molecules in a liquid. These systems are considered ergodic because, over time, the particles will explore all possible states and the behavior of the system as a whole is representative of the behavior of individual particles.

How is ergodicity important in scientific research?

Ergodicity is an important concept in scientific research, particularly in fields such as statistical mechanics and thermodynamics. It allows scientists to make predictions about the behavior of a system based on its average behavior, rather than having to study each individual particle. This simplifies the study of complex systems and makes it possible to make generalizations and predictions about their behavior.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
13
Views
938
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
12
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
8
Views
695
Replies
2
Views
539
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
597
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
644
  • Advanced Physics Homework Help
Replies
3
Views
842
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
783
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
15
Views
2K
Back
Top