Is the wavefunction subjective? How?

  • A
  • Thread starter fluidistic
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Wavefunction
In summary: But it is not 50% because you can't flip a coin twice and have it come out the same. So it is not 50% because it is not a real number. It is purely a representation of something that can only be determined by observation.This is similar to the wavefunction. There is a corresponding measurement that is guaranteed to give a particular result, if that's the correct wave function. If it gives anything else, that wave function was objectively wrong.
  • #1
fluidistic
Gold Member
3,923
261
I have read Lubos Motl blogposts (https://motls.blogspot.com/2012/11/why-subjective-quantum-mechanics-allows.html and https://motls.blogspot.com/2019/03/occams-razor-and-unreality-of-wave.html) stating that the wavefunction is subjective. This means that it is perfectly valid that two different observers use two different wavefunctions to describe the same system. I do not understand how it makes any sense.

Consider the example of the probability for a UK male of 25 years of age to die within the next year. Clearly, this probability is well defined and exists regardless of whether person A and person B agree about it. We can get a rather good estimate thanks to statistics, for example. But it seems that this logic does not apply anymore in QM. It seems like according to QM logic, that probability is subjective and only depends on who you ask. It is not a well defined number that exists regardless of the observer(s).

I am trying to convince myself that such a thing is possible, but I am unfruitful thus far. What would be the point then to write down the Schrödinger's equation for a system and solve for ##|psi \rangle## if I can come up with any other wavefunction and claim that it solves the same problem as described by another observer?

Does the subjectivity of the wavefunction in fact imply that the Schrödinger's equation is subjective? Because once the Schrödinger's equation is properly settled, then its solution follows.

I feel like I'm missing something in order to understand Lubos Motl and I feel like he's right. I have also glanced Wigner's friend Wikipedia's article and the QBism viewpoint. I do not want to deal with interpretations unless it is absolutely required.
From what I have read, extracting information out of a system is a subjective thing (though I do not understand how). Arnold Neumaier claims that this is done via an irreversible interaction though Lubos Motl claims that this isn't necessarily true and that irreversibility is also subjective (because even in QM everything is reversible though the probability to go one-way might be extremely small and the threshold is subjective), but I think this is besides the point.

So I am entirely confused about ##|\psi \rangle##. Can someone shed some light?
 
  • Like
Likes YaGurlAnimalWorkzz
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
fluidistic said:
Consider the example of the probability for a UK male of 25 years of age to die within the next year. Clearly, this probability is well defined and exists regardless of whether person A and person B agree about it.
This probability is ill-defined and changes with time. It was different in 1850 from what it is this year, and will again be different in 2050.
fluidistic said:
We can get a rather good estimate thanks to statistics, for example.
Different samples collected by A (data from 1950 to 2015) or B (data from 2000 to 2018) will give possibly quite different estimates. Even the same data give different estimates when evaluated with different statistical methodologies (frequentist or Bayesian, time-independent or time-dependent, linear or nonlinear models, etc.).
 
Last edited:
  • #3
fluidistic said:
Consider the example of the probability for a UK male of 25 years of age to die within the next year. Clearly, this probability is well defined and exists regardless of whether person A and person B agree about it. We can get a rather good estimate thanks to statistics, for example. But it seems that this logic does not apply anymore in QM. It seems like according to QM logic, that probability is subjective and only depends on who you ask. It is not a well defined number that exists regardless of the observer(s).

I guess I have the opposite opinion about the subjectivity/objectivity of probability. I think that classical probability is always subjective. A particular male will either die this year or not. Perhaps if we had enough information about his situation, what's going on in his cells, we could say definitely whether he will die. But the statistics saying that x% of the population will die this year, averages over those details. For a specific male, we can come up with different probabilities depending on how much information we have about him. So it's subjective.

In contrast, it seems to me that wave functions are not subjective. Certainly, people can have different opinions about what the wave function is, but it seems that it can be objectively right or wrong. For a given wave function, there is a corresponding measurement that is guaranteed to give a particular result, if that's the correct wave function. If it gives anything else, that wave function was objectively wrong.
 
  • #4
stevendaryl said:
A particular male will either die this year or not.
But the example was not about a particular male but about an arbitrary male from the population considered:
fluidistic said:
Consider the example of the probability for a UK male of 25 years of age to die within the next year.
 
  • Like
Likes Gregory Alan, dextercioby and fluidistic
  • #5
I see that the male example was a bad one. Consider a 2 faced coin. The probability that is lands on either of its face is well defined, even though we do not know it a priori (it may be biased, etc.). In QM, it seems we cannot assert this. I.e. in QM the coin doesn't have a well defined probability to land on either face, and in fact this probability varies across observers.
 
  • #6
fluidistic said:
in QM the coin doesn't have a well defined probability to land on either face, and in fact this probability varies across observers.
Not really if the coin has the usual macroscopic size.

fluidistic said:
What would be the point then to write down the Schrödinger's equation for a system and solve for
##|\psi\rangle## if I can come up with any other wavefunction and claim that it solves the same problem as described by another observer?
The subjective interpretations take the wave function at time 0 as subjective but the Hamiltonian and its dynamics as objective (though making here a difference is questionable). This allows them to obtain their subjective probabilities as computed by a scattering calculation with this Hamiltonian and the Schrödinger equation.
 
  • #7
fluidistic said:
I see that the male example was a bad one. Consider a 2 faced coin. The probability that is lands on either of its face is well defined, even though we do not know it a priori (it may be biased, etc.). In QM, it seems we cannot assert this. I.e. in QM the coin doesn't have a well defined probability to land on either face, and in fact this probability varies across observers.

As I said, I think that's backwards. Classical probabilities are subjective, but quantum wave functions are not.

Classical probabilities are consistent with the assumption that EVERYTHING is pre-determined, and that the appearance of probability simply reflects our ignorance about the state of the world. If you knew everything there is to know about the structure of the coin, and the way that the person flips coins, and the air currents, etc, you could predict with certainty what the result would be. The 50/50 probability comes from not knowing all those details.

And, as I said, quantum wave functions have an associated certainty to them. For each wave function there is a measurement that is guaranteed to give a specific result if that wave function is the true wave function, but may give a different result if that wave function is wrong.
 
  • Like
Likes jordi
  • #8
A. Neumaier said:
But the example was not about a particular male but about an arbitrary male from the population considered:

But what does that mean? If some males are definitely going to die, and some males are definitely going to live, then what does the probability of an arbitrary male dying mean?
 
  • #9
stevendaryl said:
But what does that mean? If some males are definitely going to die, and some males are definitely going to live, then what does the probability of an arbitrary male dying mean?
Well, in a finite sample space (here: UK males today 25 years of age) with uniform measure (as usually assumed in democratic statistics), this probability is precisely the relative frequency.
It is well-defined and deterministically known if you know the state of the universe (assumed classical) today and its precise dynamics.

Those who take a subjective view of classical probability mistake (in my opinion) probabilities estimated for a population from incomplete information (about the current state and/or the full dynamics) for the true probabilities. Only the estimated probabilities, not the true ones, are subjective since they depend on the way the estimation is done, which always depends on matters of choice that may differ between different scientists.
 
  • #10
A. Neumaier said:
Those who take a subjective view of classical probability mistake (in my opinion) probabilities estimated for a population from incomplete information (about the current state and/or the full dynamics) for the true probabilities. Only the estimated probabilities, not the true ones, are subjective since they depend on the way the estimation is done, which always depends on matters of choice that may differ between different scientists.

There is no reason to believe that there is such a thing as "true probabilities". It's certainly consistent to deny the existence of such a thing. In classical physics, anyway, there is no inherent nondeterminism, so probabilities are always due to lack of information about the details.

I would not say that relative frequency is the same thing as probability. One out of every 7 days is Sunday, but that doesn't mean that there is a 1/7 chance that today is Sunday.
 
  • #11
stevendaryl said:
There is no reason to believe that there is such a thing as "true probabilities". It's certainly consistent to deny the existence of such a thing.
It is also consistent to deny everything. But this does not warrant the conclusion that there is no reason to believe in something.
stevendaryl said:
In classical physics, anyway, there is no inherent nondeterminism, so probabilities are always due to lack of information about the details.
This does not follow. The probability that an arbitrary throw of perfect dice gives a 4 is still 1/6, objectively, and deterministically.
stevendaryl said:
I would not say that relative frequency is the same thing as probability.
Not in general. But I had qualified my statement.
 
  • #12
A. Neumaier said:
It is also consistent to deny everything. But this does not warrant the conclusion that there is no reason to believe in something.

But there is no advantage in assuming (classically, anyway) that probabilities are objective.
 
  • #13
stevendaryl said:
But there is no advantage in assuming (classically, anyway) that probabilities are objective.
There is. People working in insurance companies live from it.

To survive you need to have good approximations to the objective probabilities. This is not different in the classical and in the quantum case.
 
  • #14
stevendaryl said:
But there is no advantage in assuming (classically, anyway) that probabilities are objective.

Saying that probabilities are relative frequencies doesn't really make sense. For one thing, relative frequencies are always rationals, with the denominator dependent on the number of trials performed. You can say that probabilities are the limit of relative frequencies as the number of trials goes to infinity, but there is no guarantee of that. All that you can say is that the probability that the relative frequency departs significantly from the probability goes to zero as the number of trials goes to infinity. But that's a circular definition of probabilities in terms of probabilities.
 
  • #15
A. Neumaier said:
There is. People working in insurance companies live from it.

No, decision-making is not affected by what your attitude is toward probabilities. If a bet has only a 1% chance of winning, then you won't take it unless the payoff is at least 100 to 1. Whether that 1% is subjective or objective doesn't make any difference.
 
  • #16
stevendaryl said:
Saying that probabilities are relative frequencies doesn't really make sense.
You are arguing against a straw man. I wasn't saying that. I was saying:
A. Neumaier said:
in a finite sample space (here: UK males today 25 years of age) with uniform measure (as usually assumed in democratic statistics), this probability is precisely the relative frequency.
stevendaryl said:
If a bet has only a 1% chance of winning, then you won't take it unless the payoff is at least 100 to 1. Whether that 1% is subjective or objective doesn't make any difference.
It does, because to survive you need to make bets that live up to their expectation - at least if the bets are about things that make a real difference. The other betters will soon be out of the game.
 
  • #17
A. Neumaier said:
It does, because to survive you need to make bets that live up to their expectation - at least if the bets are about things that make a real difference. The other betters will soon be out of the game.

You're saying that a gambler will be more successful if he believes in objective probabilities, than if he believes in subjective probabilities? That doesn't make any sense to me. They make the same bets.
 
  • #18
stevendaryl said:
You're saying that a gambler will be more successful if he believes in objective probabilities, than if he believes in subjective probabilities? That doesn't make any sense to me. They make the same bets.
No. I am saying that a gambler will be more successful if his subjective probabilities closely match the objective probabilities than if his subjective probabilities are far off. The latter leads to very different bets.
 
  • Like
Likes julcab12, PeroK and fluidistic
  • #19
The quantum state has a DeFinetti's theorem and other associated subjective Bayesian results, so it's perfectly fine to think of it as subjective. You can then interpret the convergence of different density matrices under observational data of an ensemble in an Objective or Subjective Bayesian manner. That leads one into the interpretation of probability theory.

Regardless the quantum case doesn't seem that different from the classical case in this regard.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen, bhobba and dextercioby
  • #20
In the blog post, Lubos is pointing out (in different words) that the wavefunction along a lightcone originating from Alice at time t1 will be different from a wavefunction along the lightcone originating from Bob at time t2. They will use different numbers in a different order. That is correct. But there is an information preserving transformation between the two perspectives; they are just different representations of the same underlying objective thing.

In the same way that two observers in different reference frames may have different descriptions of the state of the same world, two observers may be storing two different wavefunctions that describe the same world. Assuming the observers don't discard necessary information (e.g. by forgetting the wavefunction they were storing before a measurement), there will be a transformation between their respective stored wavefunctions that shows they are equivalent (in the same way that Lorentz boosts show that different reference frames are equivalent). If this was not the case, they would be able to compare notes and find contradictions where e.g. one of them predicted A with 100% certainty and the other predicted not A with 100% certainty.
 
  • #21
Ok, I think I start to understand. Thanks to the inherent randomness in QM, there is no "general psi" that everyone must agree on. Instead psi is subjective in that it can (but need not) represent what the observer knows about a system. As an example, the QSHM as seen by 2 observers that observed the system since different times. In order to get psi, they have to solve Schrodinger's equation, but their initial conditions might differ, and hence its solution too, thus psi. And they are both correct, despite psi differing.

Things can be made much more complicated when the 2 observers are dealing with different Hilbert spaces, etc.

In the end it is indeed quite different from the classical mechanics case where every one has to agree about the state of the system.

That was a shotgun to the mind!
 
  • #22
fluidistic said:
In the end it is indeed quite different from the classical mechanics case where every one has to agree about the state of the system
Just to be clear, when I said classical case, I meant classical (Kolmogorov) probability theory rather than classical mechanics. The arguments for and against quantum states being subjective are basically exactly the same as those for regular old probability distributions.
 
  • #23
Quantum mechanics requires a designation of something that is the quantum system and something else which is the measurement apparatus. This is of course subjective. The quantum system is included in the wave function, and the measurement apparatus is not included in the wave function. In this sense, the wave function is subjective.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM and odietrich
  • #24
atyy said:
Quantum mechanics requires a designation of something that is the quantum system and something else which is the measurement apparatus. This is of course subjective. The quantum system is included in the wave function, and the measurement apparatus is not included in the wave function. In this sense, the wave function is subjective.
This is not the standard usage of the term 'subjective'. In this sense, the state in classical mechanics is also subjective, unless you always work with the state of the whole universe, which is unknown.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #25
atyy said:
Quantum mechanics requires a designation of something that is the quantum system and something else which is the measurement apparatus. This is of course subjective. The quantum system is included in the wave function, and the measurement apparatus is not included in the wave function. In this sense, the wave function is subjective.
If we're speaking very roughly (ignoring position eigenstate problems), let's say ##x## is a position on a detector screen and ##\psi(x)## is just the wavefunction giving the probability to be detected at a point on the screen.

Would it be a valid way to phrase Bohr's idea of the cut to say that by necessity ##x## has to be classical in order to have the notion of an outcome?

Obviously in classical mechanics we might measure a system with a form of "cut" in that we don't explicitly model our thermometers, meter sticks, etc and simply take them to produce values by interacting with the system under study. So we might be studying a meteorite which is modeled with variables ##q_i## moving under some equations of motion. Our telescopes then record values ##A_i## that we then use to construct ##q_i## etc

However the point of the cut in Quantum Mechanics is that by doing this you're actually treating the system and your devices very differently unlike in classical mechanics. For in QM the modeled systems don't have values like ##q_i##, quantum states are very different things. However you have to still consider your devices as producing an ##A_i## in order to still have the notion of an experiment with outcomes.

Would this be accurate do you think?
 
  • #26
fluidistic said:
I have read Lubos Motl blogposts (https://motls.blogspot.com/2012/11/why-subjective-quantum-mechanics-allows.html and https://motls.blogspot.com/2019/03/occams-razor-and-unreality-of-wave.html) stating that the wavefunction is subjective. This means that it is perfectly valid that two different observers use two different wavefunctions to describe the same system. I do not understand how it makes any sense.
..
I feel like I'm missing something in order to understand Lubos Motl and I feel like he's right
...
So I am entirely confused about ##|\psi \rangle##. Can someone shed some light?

I didnt read all the links but as I understand Lubos take on the nature of symmetries, I associate this to basically mean that the choice of observer (in as I envision Lubos thinking here) is thought of a "gauge choice"; and to have a specific information state you need to fix the gauge (observer). The objectivity rather lies in the equivalence class of observers. And psi is not an equivalence class, its gauge dependent.

One can make other comments on this view, ie. objection to reducing the observer to a gauge choice, but this has been discussed elsewhere in the BTSM section so i will not pull that up here. But if you ignore these objections the logic above is i think clear enough and makes perfect sense. Cases where it does not make sense are i think also edges of things where we are forced to BTSM discussions.

/Fredrik
 
  • #27
DarMM said:
If we're speaking very roughly (ignoring position eigenstate problems), let's say ##x## is a position on a detector screen and ##\psi(x)## is just the wavefunction giving the probability to be detected at a point on the screen.

Would it be a valid way to phrase Bohr's idea of the cut to say that by necessity ##x## has to be classical in order to have the notion of an outcome?

Obviously in classical mechanics we might measure a system with a form of "cut" in that we don't explicitly model our thermometers, meter sticks, etc and simply take them to produce values by interacting with the system under study. So we might be studying a meteorite which is modeled with variables ##q_i## moving under some equations of motion. Our telescopes then record values ##A_i## that we then use to construct ##q_i## etc

However the point of the cut in Quantum Mechanics is that by doing this you're actually treating the system and your devices very differently unlike in classical mechanics. For in QM the modeled systems don't have values like ##q_i##, quantum states are very different things. However you have to still consider your devices as producing an ##A_i## in order to still have the notion of an experiment with outcomes.

Would this be accurate do you think?

I'm not sure about Bohr in the strict historical sense (only Bohr in the broad sense that the orthodox interpretation is Copenhagen in the broad sense), but yes, the cut means the measurement apparatus and the quantum system are modeled quite differently. It doesn't seem like we can the extend descriptor of the quantum system to include the measurement apparatus, unless we have yet another measurement apparatus to measure the measurement apparatus.

In classical physics, we can imagine the system as being in a pure state, and that it is only our ignorance that makes things uncertain. In quantum physics, even if the system is assigned a pure state, we can't imagine that the system is "really" in a pure state, unless we attempt something like many worlds or hidden variables.
 
  • Informative
Likes DarMM
  • #28
If the wave function is subjective so that two different observers use two different wave functions to describe a system, then any predictions they make must be different - otherwise they're just equivalent wave functions. Two different predictions about the same event cannot both be correct (unless the observers fly off into two alternative realities where one is right and one is wrong - in which case prediction is futile anyway).
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim and Lord Jestocost
  • #29
Jehannum said:
If the wave function is subjective so that two different observers use two different wave functions to describe a system, then any predictions they make must be different - otherwise they're just equivalent wave functions. Two different predictions about the same event cannot both be correct (unless the observers fly off into two alternative realities where one is right and one is wrong - in which case prediction is futile anyway).

I made that point earlier. If I believe that the wave function is ##\psi##, then that implies an objective fact. I can come with an observable ##\Pi_\psi## that is guaranteed to give the result +1 if the measurement is performed on a system in state ##\psi##. If the result is anything other than +1, that objectively proves that I was wrong to say that the wave function was ##\psi##. So to me, that shows that there is something objective about the wave function, if you can be proved wrong about it.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #30
As remarked by Nick Herbert in “Quantum Reality: Beyond the New Physics”:

The separate images that we form of the quantum world (wave, particle, for example) from different experimental viewpoints do not combine into one comprehensive whole. There is no single image that corresponds to an electron. The quantum world is not made up of objects. As Heisenberg puts it, ‘Atoms are not things.’

This does not mean that the quantum world is subjective. The quantum world is as objective as our own: different people taking the same viewpoint see the same thing, but the quantum world is not made of objects (different viewpoints do not add up). The quantum world is objective but objectless.
” [Emphasis added by LJ]
 
  • #31
stevendaryl said:
I made that point earlier. If I believe that the wave function is ##\psi##, then that implies an objective fact. I can come with an observable ##\Pi_\psi## that is guaranteed to give the result +1 if the measurement is performed on a system in state ##\psi##. If the result is anything other than +1, that objectively proves that I was wrong to say that the wave function was ##\psi##. So to me, that shows that there is something objective about the wave function, if you can be proved wrong about it.
Just to be clear, what's the difference between this and a Bayesian prior ##\rho## with support on a set ##A \subset \Omega## with ##\Omega## the sample space? I could test the random variable ##\chi_{A}##, the characteristic function of ##A##, and ##\rho## is guaranteed to give ##1## as the response.

i.e. is this anything but Subjective vs Objective Bayesianism without any additional quantum nuances?
 
  • #32
DarMM said:
The quantum state has a DeFinetti's theorem and other associated subjective Bayesian results, so it's perfectly fine to think of it as subjective.

Exactly - either view - objective or subjective is valid. Have a look at Gleason's Theorem:
http://kiko.fysik.su.se/en/thesis/helena-master.pdf

It shows it exits (providing non-contextuality is assumed) but says nothing about if its just subjective or real.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #33
bhobba said:
Exactly - either view - objective or subjective is valid. Have a look at Gleason's Theorem:
http://kiko.fysik.su.se/en/thesis/helena-master.pdf

It shows it exits (providing non-contextuality is assumed) but says nothing about if its just subjective or real.

Thanks
Bill
I think you might like Cabello's work. It's a sort of weakening of the assumptions of Gleason's theorem. Although be warned heavy duty graph theory is involved.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #34
I should say, if you want the "Bird's eye view" of the theorem, a quick run down is as follows.

Gleason assumes two things. That observable quantities are related to each other in a specific form, i.e. the algebra of observables is a C*-algebra and also that the world is such that your probability assignments need not take note of the context within which you make measurements. As you known ##P\left(\Pi\right)##, where ##\Pi## is a projector, is the same regardless what observable ##A## you measure to examine ##\Pi##.

Cabello however only assumes that the algebra of observables has the weaker property that joint measurability of ##A## and ##B## implies there exists an experiment to measure ##A## that doesn't disturb ##B##. This isn't quite as strong as assuming the whole C*-algebra structure, but can be shown to imply it if you want a noncontextual probability assignment.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #35
DarMM said:
Just to be clear, what's the difference between this and a Bayesian prior ##\rho## with support on a set ##A \subset \Omega## with ##\Omega## the sample space? I could test the random variable ##\chi_{A}##, the characteristic function of ##A##, and ##\rho## is guaranteed to give ##1## as the response.

i.e. is this anything but Subjective vs Objective Bayesianism without any additional quantum nuances?

Yes, in Bayesian probability, you can be proved objectively wrong if you give an assignment of 0 or 1 to some possibility. So in that sense, Bayesian probability has an objective element to it, which is what is possible and what is not. The exact numbers are subjective.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM and bhobba

Similar threads

Replies
5
Views
925
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
8
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
21
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
419
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
13
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
3
Replies
82
Views
8K
Back
Top