Quantum Mechanics without Measurement

In summary: The problem with this is that it reintroduces the EPR paradox. If two particles are in different histories, then they can't share a common reality.I recommend the following paper by Robert B. Griffiths on developing the theory of quantum mechanics without giving a special role to measurements:http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0612065v1.pdf
  • #36
martinbn said:
Yes, if it is a logical necessity it is a good explanation.
Yes, but CH is not a logical necessity. For instance, nonlocal hidden variables are logically not excluded.

martinbn said:
But what is your point? If it is something is meaningless it is meaningless, saying the opposite cannot be a part of a good explanation.
Generaly, something can be meaningless only within a certain predefined rules of language. The CH interpretation proposes one such set of rules, and within this language some statements are meaningless. But they still have meaning outside of this language, i.e., in some other interpretation of quantum mechanics. So the real question is: Should we accept the rules of language proposed by CH? My point is that we shouldn't.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
atyy said:
Would you accept CH as a solution to the question of what local nonrealism might be in a way that solves the measurement problem
No I wouldn't.

atyy said:
(eg. solipsism is local nonrealism, but it has a measurement problem)?
In an attempt to understand local nonrealism as a kind of solipsism WITHOUT a measurement problem, I have constructed my own model of solipsistic local hidden variables:
http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/1112.2034 [Int. J. Quantum Inf. 10 (2012) 1241016]
 
  • #38
stevendaryl said:
Some people think that such an emphasis on measurement is appropriate, since physics is an empirical science, and empirical science is founded on measurements, experiments, observations, etc. However, I find it very unsatisfactory for measurement to play a key role in the formulation a of fundamental theory because measurements are not fundamental.

I absolutely agree, and so do J. S. Bell in his last article – Against ‘Measurement’ (1990).

[PLAIN said:
http://www.tau.ac.il/~quantum/Vaidman/IQM/BellAM.pdf]Here[/PLAIN] [Broken] are some words which, however legitimate and necessary in application, have no place in a formulation with any pretension to physical precision: system, apparatus, environment, microscopic, macroscopic, reversible, irreversible, observable, information, measurement.

The concepts 'system', 'apparatus', 'environment', immediately imply an artificial division of the world, and an intention to neglect, or take only schematic account of, the interaction across the split. The notions of 'microscopic' and 'macroscopic' defy precise definition. So also do the notions of 'reversible' and 'irreversible'. Einstein said that it is theory which decides what is 'observable'. I think he was right – 'observation' is a complicated and theory-laden business. Then that notion should not appear in the formulation of fundamental theory. Information? Whose information? Information about what?

On this list of bad words from good books, the worst of all is 'measurement'. It must have a section to itself.

stevendaryl said:
A measuring device is, after all, a physical object, presumably governed by the same physical laws that govern atoms and molecules and light and gravity. What makes a particular physical object suitable to be considered a "measuring device" is pretty complicated:

  • There must be an interaction between the system being measured and states of the measuring device.
  • The measuring device must act as an "amplifier", so that microscopic properties of the system being measured can trigger macroscopic changes in the state of the device.
  • The measuring device must have states that are sufficiently "orderly" to interpret easily. Either, there must be a number of discrete states in the measuring device that are observably different, or else there must be a continuous sets of states that can readily be interpreted as a linear scale.
  • The act of measurement should result in a "record", an irreversible change that can be reliably checked later.

Yes, and to be picky (and maybe make things worse), there are also quantum "measuring devices", for example a beamsplitter; where we do have an interaction and measurement of states, but no microscopic amplification or irreversibility (i.e. quantum measurements could easily be undone).

It seems that the root of the 'confusion' is the Schrödinger wavefunction vs. the Born rule |ψ|2, which afaik is just a 'hack', without any rigorous mathematical 'explanation'. Bell seems to agree even on this point.

[PLAIN said:
http://www.tau.ac.il/~quantum/Vaidman/IQM/BellAM.pdf]In[/PLAIN] [Broken] the beginning, Schrodinger tried to interpret his wave- function as giving somehow the density of the stuff of which the world is made. He tried to think of an electron as represented by a wavepacket – a wavefunction appreciably different from zero only over a small region in space. The extension of that region he thought of as the actual size of the electron - his electron was a bit fuzzy. At first he thought that small wavepackets, evolving according to the Schrodinger equation, would remain small. But that was wrong. Wavepackets diffuse, and with the passage of time become indefinitely extended, according to the Schrodinger equation. But however far the wavefunction has extended, the reaction of a detector to an electron remains spotty. So Schrodinger's 'realistic' interpretation of his wavefunction did not survive.

Then came the Born interpretation. The wavefunction gives not the density of stuff, but gives rather (on squaring its modulus) the density of probability. Probability of what, exactly? Not of the electron being there, but of the electron being found there, if its position is 'measured'.

Why this aversion to 'being' and insistence on 'finding'? The founding fathers were unable to form a clear picture of things on the remote atomic scale. They became very aware of the intervening apparatus, and of the need for a 'classical' base from which to intervene on the quantum system. And so the shifty split.

And the "shifty split" is still there; 24 years later, as Steven Weinberg explains.

[my bolding]
[PLAIN said:
http://scitation.aip.org/content/aip/magazine/physicstoday/article/58/11/10.1063/1.2155755]Bohr’s[/PLAIN] [Broken] version of quantum mechanics was deeply flawed, but not for the reason Einstein thought. The Copenhagen interpretation describes what happens when an observer makes a measurement, but the observer and the act of measurement are themselves treated classically. This is surely wrong: Physicists and their apparatus must be governed by the same quantum mechanical rules that govern everything else in the universe. But these rules are expressed in terms of a wavefunction (or, more precisely, a state vector) that evolves in a perfectly deterministic way. So where do the probabilistic rules of the Copenhagen interpretation come from?

Considerable progress has been made in recent years toward the resolution of the problem, which I cannot go into here. It is enough to say that neither Bohr nor Einstein had focused on the real problem with quantum mechanics. The Copenhagen rules clearly work, so they have to be accepted. But this leaves the task of explaining them by applying the deterministic equation for the evolution of the wavefunction, the Schrödinger equation, to observers and their apparatus. The difficulty is not that quantum mechanics is probabilistic — that is something we apparently just have to live with. The real difficulty is that it is also deterministic, or more precisely, that it combines a probabilistic interpretation with deterministic dynamics.

Regarding Griffiths; the urge to 'eradicate' measurements altogether, I think has more to do with the problem that we do have empirical evidence (i.e. EPR-Bell experiments) that do not fit his consistent worldview – and the easiest thing to do is just to get rid of the whole enchilada, by some preposterous word-salad, that no one can take seriously.

And yet it moves -- Galileo Galilei

Griffiths makes two disastrous mistakes:

1)
Bell's theorem is a no-go theorem, which put restrictions on the classical world, not quantum mechanics, and to try to solve this dilemma by 'modifications' on Hilbert space, quantum logic, etc, is just ridiculous. QM works – classical local realism don't!

We can forget everything about Bell's theorem and QM, and instead put "Barnum & Bailey Circus – The Greatest Show on Earth", in its place:

Code:
 Classical      |     Barnum & Bailey              |     Classical
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
 Source  -->    |     Entanglement Circus   -->    |     Measurement data 
----------------------------------------------------------------------------

Now, if we empirically have tested the Barnum & Bailey Circus for almost a hundred years, without finding one single error, we have to assume that this circus is not cheating, right?

And since the outcome is classical, we can inspect the results without any 'influences' from Barnum & Bailey, right?

Then, the only rational way is to check if we can replicate the 'trick' without Barnum & Bailey, and if we can't do this, then the only option left is modifications in our view on the classical part, even if it hurts, right?

Thus, it doesn't really matter what 'trick' Barnum & Bailey performs, because we have checked their business model for almost a hundred years, and Barnum & Bailey are true/compatible to all tests performed this far (which also means that this reputation can never be taken away from them, no matter what happens in the future), right?

Conclusion: We must modify our view* on the classical part in this show; this is the only way out, Griffiths is on the wrong path, leading to a dead end.

*I.e. "Barnum & Bailey" has the capability to perform a 'trick' that is empirical true, but impossible to replicate with only the tools available in the classical part.

2)
Griffiths tries to put science on The Platonic Pedestal of Eternal, Ultimate and Consistent Truth – but he has already lost the game (obviously without even knowing it). Gödel's incompleteness theorem proves that any system that is sufficiently powerful cannot be both consistent and complete.

Thus, Griffiths is using logic – proven to be either inconsistent or incomplete – to prove physics consistent and complete.​

Result = Inconsistent Fairy Tales
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #39
Demystifier said:
No I wouldn't.

Why don't you consider CH to be a version of local nonrealism without a measurement problem?

Demystifier said:
In an attempt to understand local nonrealism as a kind of solipsism WITHOUT a measurement problem, I have constructed my own model of solipsistic local hidden variables:
http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/1112.2034 [Int. J. Quantum Inf. 10 (2012) 1241016]

Yes, I think that works.
 
  • #40
Demystifier said:
This, indeed, is the main problem with the Griffiths interpretation. To avoid EPR "paradox" and consequences of the Bell theorem, Griffiths proposes to abandon the rules of classical LOGIC, replacing them with a kind of quantum logic:
http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/1105.3932
http://lanl.arxiv.org/abs/1110.0974
Most physicists, mathematicians, and even logicians, find it very unattractive.

In particular, let me quote from http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Bell's_theorem
"[...] By forbidding the reasoning used to prove inequality (1), the aforementioned rule of CH prevents us from arriving at the contradiction. But a physical theory is not simply a game for which one can impose arbitrary rules about what reasonings are permitted for the propositions of the theory;"

Demystifier said:
The problem is that Griffiths wants to avoid the Bell theorem, according to which hidden variables (not necessarily deterministic) must necessarily be nonlocal. He avoids Bell theorem not by rejecting assumptions of the Bell theorem, but by rejecting classical LOGIC leading from the assumptions to the theorem.

Indeed, any logical conclusion may be avoided by rejecting the rules of logic. This technique, for instance, is often used by politicians. But should we allow it in science? I don't think so.

Thank you very much for this Demystifier. In an earlier thread, I did find it necessary to defend Griffiths as not being a crackpot. After all, he is a Professor of Physics at Carnegie Mellon University.

But now, I'm not so sure about this...
 
  • #41
Demystifier said:
Except being an excellent physicists, Feynman is also known for being a good lover. (That can also be said for Schrodinger, but let us stick with Feynman.)

So, we can say that Feynman is a good physicist, and we can also say that Feynman is a good lover.
But can we say that Feynman is a good scientist and a good lover?

This could be hard to prove, however with Schrödinger the case is a little bit ambiguous... Schrödinger discovered quantum theory while hunkered down with a lover in a Swiss chalet... and when pressed to write about his creative life... he protested, saying that he felt the part his lovers played in it was crucial, but discretion would require him to leave that out.

This opens a possibility for Schrödinger actually 'multitasking' in the Swiss chalet... :smile:

Seriously, everything that does not happen simultaneously cannot be proven true?? :bugeye: What a joke...
 
  • #42
Quantum Mechanics without Measurement


also known as 'superposition'
 
  • #43
martinbn said:
So! There is not claim that all conjunctions are meaningless. But you have completely changed the experimental set up. This is a different scenario.

I don't think so. The Feynman is precisely understood in terms of "hidden variables". Even though you have to make a choice whether to test his lover ability or his physics ability, we an assume that both abilities exist in him at the same time, although we can't demonstrate this.

So there is no contradiction that arises from assuming "hidden variables" in the Feynman case, while in the quantum mechanics it leads to a contradiction (or to a violation of something else important, such as locality).
 
  • #44
DevilsAvocado said:
Thank you very much for this Demystifier. In an earlier thread, I did find it necessary to defend Griffiths as not being a crackpot. After all, he is a Professor of Physics at Carnegie Mellon University.

But now, I'm not so sure about this...

He is definitely not crackpot. You can disagree about whether he has solved the conceptual problems of quantum mechanics through his approach without saying he's a crackpot.
 
  • #45
Maui said:
also known as 'superposition'

No, I wouldn't say that that's very accurate.
 
  • #46
DevilsAvocado said:
Thank you very much for this Demystifier. In an earlier thread, I did find it necessary to defend Griffiths as not being a crackpot. After all, he is a Professor of Physics at Carnegie Mellon University.

But now, I'm not so sure about this...

If Griffiths has made a mistake, where could it be? On the one hand, CH is not a realistic theory, so it seems that it could escape the Bell theorem.

In http://quantum.phys.cmu.edu/CQT/chaps/cqt24.pdf (p289) he writes that "Thus the point at which the derivation of (24.10) begins to deviate from quantum principles is in the assumption that a function ##\alpha(w_{a}, \lambda )## exists for different directions ##w_{a}##."

Well, so far I think what he says is ok, since Bell's point is indeed that these exist only if local realism holds, and quantum mechanics is not a local realistic theory.

Then he says "The claim is sometimes made that quantum theory must be nonlocal simply because its predictions violate (24.10). But this is not correct. First, what follows logically from the violation of this inequality is that hidden variable theories, if they are to agree with quantum theory, must be nonlocal or embody some other peculiarity. But hidden variable theories by definition employ a different mathematical structure from (or in addition to) the quantum Hilbert space, so this tells us nothing about standard quantum mechanics."

This seems fishy, because http://arxiv.org/abs/0901.4255 argues that the Bell theorem is compatible with quantum mechanics, since the wave function itself can serve as the hidden variable. It is simply that if one accepts "realism", then the wave function is nonlocal. So I don't think the Bell inequality is incompatible with quantum mechanics. Perhaps it is here that Griffiths has made a mistake.

Nonetheless, in the broader sense, it seems that Griffiths could be right, and CH could be local since it does seem to reject realism (ie. Griffiths's definition of "realism" is not common sense realism). Hohenberg's introduction to CH http://arxiv.org/abs/0909.2359, for example, says CH is not realistic theory - which given how some versions of Copenhagen don't favour realism - CH could I think be argued to be Copenhagen done right.

But exactly how is locality retained in CH? Hohenberg says it's because there is no single framework in CH in which Eq 11 http://arxiv.org/abs/0909.2359 is satisfied. Can that be the explanation? It seems it is not satisfied in the orthodox shut-up-and-calculate Copenhagenish view, but that doesn't make shut-up-and-calculate local. So is the explanation instead that P(A,B,a,b), where a and b range over non-commuting observables does not exist in any single framework?

What I'm asking is: in CH is the Bell inequality violated in any single framework?
 
Last edited:
  • #47
stevendaryl said:
No, I wouldn't say that that's very accurate.


It's accurate. There are many ways to define 'measurement'.
 
  • #48
Maui said:
It's accurate. There are many ways to define 'measurement'.

But "superposition" certainly doesn't mean the same thing as "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement".
 
  • #49
DevilsAvocado said:
Regarding Griffiths; the urge to 'eradicate' measurements altogether, I think has more to do with the problem that we do have empirical evidence (i.e. EPR-Bell experiments) that do not fit his consistent worldview – and the easiest thing to do is just to get rid of the whole enchilada, by some preposterous word-salad, that no one can take seriously.

I think that is way too harsh. I don't see it that way at all. As someone else said, I see it as a way of doing Copenhagen without making measurement devices primary to the formulation. Instead, it makes histories of observables primary. That is a little bit of an improvement, because observables do have a definite definition within the framework of quantum mechanics, which is not true of "measurement".

I think that there is a sense in which what is being done is just systematizing the practice of quantum mechanics, which is basically Copenhagen, with as few non-physical, fuzzy elements as possible.
 
  • #50
I think has more to do with the problem that we do have empirical evidence (i.e. EPR-Bell experiments) that do not fit his consistent worldview.

I don't know why you say that EPR "doesn't fit in his worldview". EPR experiments can perfectly well be analyzed from the point of view of consistent histories. All the possible outcomes of an EPR experiment form "consistent histories", and the consistent histories approach would allow you to compute the probabilities of those outcomes. At least, I would assume that to be the case---if it's not, then I agree with you that consistent histories is complete garbage.

Let me do some Googling to see if there is a good analysis of EPR from the point of view of consistent histories. I would think that would be the very first thing that would be tried with any new foundation for quantum mechanics.
 
  • #51
atyy said:
If Griffiths has made a mistake, where could it be? On the one hand, CH is not a realistic theory, so it seems that it could escape the Bell theorem.

In http://quantum.phys.cmu.edu/CQT/chaps/cqt24.pdf (p289) he writes that "Thus the point at which the derivation of (24.10) begins to deviate from quantum principles is in the assumption that a function ##\alpha(w_{a}, \lambda )## exists for different directions ##w_{a}##."

Well, so far I think what he says is ok, since Bell's point is indeed that these exist only if local realism holds, and quantum mechanics is not a local realistic theory.

(24.10) is the CHSH inequality:

[itex]\rho(a,b) + \rho(a,b') + \rho(a',b) - \rho(a',b') \leq 2[/itex]

"Thus the point at which the derivation of (24.10) begins to deviate from quantum principles is in the assumption that a function ##\alpha(w_{a}, \lambda )## exists for different directions ##w_{a}##."

To me this means that as long as we only deal with the simplest case of parallel settings (i.e. the deterministic 1935 EPR picture), we're okay and LHV would still work, but as soon as we introduce more and 'tougher' settings for the measuring apparatus (polarizer), LHV does not work anymore, only NLHV does.

[my bolding]
atyy said:
Then he says "The claim is sometimes made that quantum theory must be nonlocal simply because its predictions violate (24.10). But this is not correct. First, what follows logically from the violation of this inequality is that hidden variable theories, if they are to agree with quantum theory, must be nonlocal or embody some other peculiarity. But hidden variable theories by definition employ a different mathematical structure from (or in addition to) the quantum Hilbert space, so this tells us nothing about standard quantum mechanics."

This seems fishy, because http://arxiv.org/abs/0901.4255 argues that the Bell theorem is compatible with quantum mechanics, since the wave function itself can serve as the hidden variable. It is simply that if one accepts "realism", then the wave function is nonlocal. So I don't think the Bell inequality is incompatible with quantum mechanics. Perhaps it is here that Griffiths has made a mistake.

Fishy indeed... or maybe worse...

The first bold part above is where things start to go quite wrong. Bell's theorem is not a description or definition of quantum mechanics; instead it sets a limit for a theory of local hidden variables, aka Bell's inequality, which is violated both theoretically and experimentally by quantum mechanics, hence leading to this simple form:

No physical theory of local hidden variables can ever reproduce all of the predictions of quantum mechanics.

Bell's theorem is an abstract mathematical formulation for the limit of theories of local hidden variables; it does not say anything specific about QM. And to use the Hilbert space as an argument is nothing but ridiculous – we have experiments for god's sake! And as I mentioned in a previous post, we could substitute QM for "Barnum & Bailey Circus", and Bell's theorem would still hold (though be it a little bit 'peculiar'):

No physical theory of local hidden variables can ever reproduce all of the predictions of "Barnum & Bailey Circus".

Bell's theorem is only about theories of local hidden variables; it does not say anything fundamental about theories violating the inequality (and of course the definition of local realism comes from the original 1935 EPR paper).

I don't know what to say about the second bold part... quantum mechanics violates Bell's inequality... it cannot be 'compatible' with it, Griffiths must have misunderstood the whole thing...

atyy said:
Nonetheless, in the broader sense, it seems that Griffiths could be right, and CH could be local since it does seem to reject realism (ie. Griffiths's definition of "realism" is not common sense realism). Hohenberg's introduction to CH http://arxiv.org/abs/0909.2359, for example, says CH is not realistic theory - which given how some versions of Copenhagen don't favour realism - CH could I think be argued to be Copenhagen done right.

Well, here is when things get so perplex that it is almost justified to talk about 'crackpotish' ideas...

If CH is local and non-real there is no problem whatsoever!

But then... when Griffiths claim that CH is also consistent (which the name indicates), we're back in the rabbit hole of total confusion: What consistency is he talking about?? In which way is CH more consistent than any other QM interpretation?? I just don't get it. :bugeye:

CH is surely not consistent according to the classification adopted by Einstein and EPR:

[PLAIN said:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretations_of_quantum_mechanics]The[/PLAIN] [Broken][/PLAIN] [Broken] current usage of realism and completeness originated in the 1935 paper in which Einstein and others proposed the EPR paradox. In that paper the authors proposed the concepts element of reality and the completeness of a physical theory. They characterised element of reality as a quantity whose value can be predicted with certainty before measuring or otherwise disturbing it, and defined a complete physical theory as one in which every element of physical reality is accounted for by the theory. In a semantic view of interpretation, an interpretation is complete if every element of the interpreting structure is present in the mathematics. Realism is also a property of each of the elements of the maths; an element is real if it corresponds to something in the interpreting structure. For example, in some interpretations of quantum mechanics (such as the many-worlds interpretation) the ket vector associated to the system state is said to correspond to an element of physical reality, while in other interpretations it is not.

But what finally put the nail in the coffin for me, are statements like this:

http://quantum.phys.cmu.edu/CQT/chaps/cqt24.pdf (p289) said:
If quantum theory is a correct description of the world, then since it predicts correlation functions which violate (24.10), one or more of the assumptions made in the derivation of this inequality must be wrong.

Wow... "If" and "must"... looks like he's refuting QM and/or Bell's theorem in one sentence... not bad at all!

atyy said:
What I'm asking is: in CH is the Bell inequality violated in any single framework?

I don't know atyy, all this looks like a mess to me, but of course, I could be wrong (and then I will put on my red face, bowing to the floor, apologizing)...

This is what Wikipedia has to say:

[PLAIN said:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Interpretations_of_quantum_mechanics]The[/PLAIN] [Broken][/PLAIN] [Broken] consistent histories interpretation generalizes the conventional Copenhagen interpretation and attempts to provide a natural interpretation of quantum cosmology. The theory is based on a consistency criterion that allows the history of a system to be described so that the probabilities for each history obey the additive rules of classical probability. It is claimed to be consistent with the Schrödinger equation.

According to this interpretation, the purpose of a quantum-mechanical theory is to predict the relative probabilities of various alternative histories (for example, of a particle).

It just makes it worse, the rules of classical probability can't possibly be non-realistic... a complete mess...
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #52
stevendaryl said:
I think that is way too harsh. I don't see it that way at all. As someone else said, I see it as a way of doing Copenhagen without making measurement devices primary to the formulation. Instead, it makes histories of observables primary.

Okay, maybe too harsh (I do have my red face ready, in case you find anything ;), but I don't understand how you are able to make any 'consistency' whatsoever of things you know absolutely nothing about, except probability densities (before measurement)??

stevendaryl said:
Let me do some Googling to see if there is a good analysis of EPR from the point of view of consistent histories.

Great!
 
  • #53
DevilsAvocado said:
It just makes it worse, the rules of classical probability can't possibly be non-realistic... a complete mess...

I think it's alright as long as it is not logically inconsistent, ie. one doesn't incur a contradiction by adding an additional axiom. Since you brought up Goedel earlier, an analogy would be that the Goedel statement is true if we are talking about the natural numbers. However, at the syntactic level, since neither the statement nor its negation are provable from the Peano axioms, one could consistently add the negation of the Goedel statement as an axiom. We wouldn't have the natural numbers any more, but it would still be a consistent system with a model.
 
Last edited:
  • #54
DevilsAvocado said:
I don't know what to say about the second bold part... quantum mechanics violates Bell's inequality... it cannot be 'compatible' with it, Griffiths must have misunderstood the whole thing...

That was not a quote from Griffiths, that was another paper by a different author.

If CH is local and non-real there is no problem whatsoever!

But then... when Griffiths claim that CH is also consistent (which the name indicates), we're back in the rabbit hole of total confusion: What consistency is he talking about??

I think you misunderstood what Griffiths is talking about. The word "consistent" is a property of a set of histories. A "history" for Griffiths is a sequence of statements, each of which refers to a fact that is true at a particular moment in time. Basically, a history amounts to a record of the sort:

History [itex]H_1[/itex]:
At time [itex]t_{1 1}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{1 1}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{1 1}[/itex]
At time [itex]t_{1 2}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{1 2}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{1 2}[/itex]
...

History [itex]H_2[/itex]:
At time [itex]t_{2 1}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{2 1}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{2 1}[/itex]
At time [itex]t_{2 2}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{2 2}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{2 2}[/itex]
...

So history [itex]H_i[/itex] says that observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{i j}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{i j}[/itex] at time [itex]t_{i j}[/itex], where [itex]i[/itex] is used to index histories, and [itex]j[/itex] is used to index moments of time within that the history.

The entire collection [itex]H_1, H_2, H_3, ...[/itex] of possible histories is said to be a consistent collection if the histories are mutually exclusive. That is, it is impossible (or vanishingly small probability) that more than one history in the collection could be true. (Mathematically, each history corresponds to a product of time-evolved projection operators, and the condition of consistency is that the two histories, as projection operators, result in zero when applied to the initial density operator, or something like that).

So the word "consistent" is not talking about any particular history being consistent, or about Griffiths' theory being consistent. It's talking about it being consistent to reason about that collection of histories using classical logic and probability.

But what finally put the nail in the coffin for me, are statements like this:

Quote by http://quantum.phys.cmu.edu/CQT/chaps/cqt24.pdf (p289)
If quantum theory is a correct description of the world, then since it predicts correlation functions which violate (24.10), one or more of the assumptions made in the derivation of this inequality must be wrong.​

Wow... "If" and "must"... looks like he's refuting QM and/or Bell's theorem in one sentence... not bad at all!

You're a lot harsher than I would be reading that statement. To me, it's only saying "If the conclusion of a theorem is false, then one of the assumptions must be false."

Bell's theorem is of the form: If we assume that we have a theory of type X, then that theory will satisfy inequality Y. Since quantum mechanics does not satisfy inequality Y, then the assumption that it is a theory of type X must be false.

That's all he's saying. He's not "refuting" Bell. To say that an assumption is false is not to refute the theorem.
 
  • #55
atyy said:
Why don't you consider CH to be a version of local nonrealism without a measurement problem?
First, it is not clear to me whether CH is supposed to be about realism or nonrealism. Second, even if I accept CH to be a version of local nonrealism without a measurement problem, I do not consider it to be a very satisfying version. That's because I cannot easily diggest a change of the rules of logic (unless it is absolutely necessary, which in the case of QM is not).
 
  • #56
Demystifier said:
First, it is not clear to me whether CH is supposed to be about realism or nonrealism. Second, even if I accept CH to be a version of local nonrealism without a measurement problem, I do not consider it to be a very satisfying version. That's because I cannot easily diggest a change of the rules of logic (unless it is absolutely necessary, which in the case of QM is not).

Surely, we must consider the laws of logic to be a purely mathematical construct and not given to us as a feature of nature. That must mean that we're free to define them how we like.

Provided that we're clear about which set of logical rules we are using, their selection should be arbitrary and I can't see how we can arrive at an unsatifsying conclusion.

If a set of logical rules is complete and self-consistent then I would expect it to arrive at the same conclusion as any other.

The set of logical rules that we use is so deeply ingrained in our way of thinking, that an attempt to use another set is very likely to fail into the trap of mixing and matching rule sets, which would give rise to inconsistencies and unsatisfying conclusions.
 
Last edited:
  • #57
atyy said:
I think it's alright as long as it is not logically inconsistent, ie. one doesn't incur a contradiction by adding an additional axiom.

Yes, maybe you're right. Still I find it very confusing, and what 'bothers' me (that is never explicitly spelled out), is that maybe the most straightforward name of this interpretation should be "Classical Histories"... There's no doubt that Griffiths does not like what Bell is telling us:

[PLAIN said:
http://quantum.phys.cmu.edu/CQT/chaps/cqt24.pdf]In[/PLAIN] [Broken] summary, the basic lesson to be learned from the Bell inequalities is that it is difficult to construct a plausible hidden variable theory which will mimic the sorts of correlations predicted by quantum theory and confirmed by experiment. Such a theory must either exhibit peculiar nonlocalities which violate relativity theory, or else incorporate influences which travel backwards in time, in contrast to everyday experience. This seems a rather high price to pay just to have a theory which is more “classical” than ordinary quantum mechanics.

And maybe most mindboggling is that he makes the correct conclusion regarding premises for LHV, but do not [here] present his "third alternative" of "subjective logic" and "forbidden frameworks", but just conclude that "this seems a rather high price to pay".

And what on Earth is "a theory which is more “classical” than ordinary quantum mechanics", I'm totally lost...

atyy said:
Since you brought up Goedel earlier, an analogy would be that the Goedel statement is true if we are talking about the natural numbers. However, at the syntactic level, since neither the statement nor its negation are provable from the Peano axioms, one could consistently add the negation of the Goedel statement as an axiom. We wouldn't have the natural numbers any more, but it would still be a consistent system with a model.

Yes, but it could still never be proven to be complete and consistent from within itself. :wink:
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #58
stevendaryl said:
I think you misunderstood what Griffiths is talking about. The word "consistent" is a property of a set of histories. A "history" for Griffiths is a sequence of statements, each of which refers to a fact that is true at a particular moment in time. Basically, a history amounts to a record of the sort:

History [itex]H_1[/itex]:
At time [itex]t_{1 1}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{1 1}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{1 1}[/itex]
At time [itex]t_{1 2}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{1 2}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{1 2}[/itex]
...

History [itex]H_2[/itex]:
At time [itex]t_{2 1}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{2 1}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{2 1}[/itex]
At time [itex]t_{2 2}[/itex] observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{2 2}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{2 2}[/itex]
...

So history [itex]H_i[/itex] says that observable [itex]\mathcal{O}_{i j}[/itex] had value [itex]\lambda_{i j}[/itex] at time [itex]t_{i j}[/itex], where [itex]i[/itex] is used to index histories, and [itex]j[/itex] is used to index moments of time within that the history.

The entire collection [itex]H_1, H_2, H_3, ...[/itex] of possible histories is said to be a consistent collection if the histories are mutually exclusive. That is, it is impossible (or vanishingly small probability) that more than one history in the collection could be true. (Mathematically, each history corresponds to a product of time-evolved projection operators, and the condition of consistency is that the two histories, as projection operators, result in zero when applied to the initial density operator, or something like that).

Thank you for explaining this; however what use do we have of this in providing "a natural interpretation of quantum mechanics"? If we take EPR-Bell test experiments, this is the Bell state:

[itex]\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} \left( | \uparrow \rangle_A |\uparrow \rangle_B + |\rightarrow \rangle_A |\rightarrow \rangle_B \right)[/itex]

In standard QM this is interpreted as a quantum superposition in the shared wavefunction. Now, if CH wants to make consistent histories out of this, I guess it is okay, but afaik this can only happen afterwards, right? And what "prediction power" has CH then?

And most interesting of all:

Exactly how does CH explain the outcome of EPR-Bell test experiments if the "hidden observables" did have definite values all along??

stevendaryl said:
So the word "consistent" is not talking about any particular history being consistent, or about Griffiths' theory being consistent. It's talking about it being consistent to reason about that collection of histories using classical logic and probability.

Thank you very much for this, and I'm sorry if I went too far in my criticism of CH.

However, I believe it is not possible to explain EPR-Bell experiments outcome, using only classical logic and classical probability.

stevendaryl said:
You're a lot harsher than I would be reading that statement. To me, it's only saying "If the conclusion of a theorem is false, then one of the assumptions must be false."

Bell's theorem is of the form: If we assume that we have a theory of type X, then that theory will satisfy inequality Y. Since quantum mechanics does not satisfy inequality Y, then the assumption that it is a theory of type X must be false.

That's all he's saying. He's not "refuting" Bell. To say that an assumption is false is not to refute the theorem.

Okay, we are interpreting this differently. To me "If quantum theory is a correct description of the world", means that the writer questions if quantum theory is correct, and "one or more of the assumptions made in the derivation of this inequality must be wrong", to me means that the writer questions Bell's theorem.

We all know the outstanding precision and validity of QM, the gadget world of today would simply stop if there was slightest error in QM's "description of the world". John Bell was nominated for the Nobel Prize in Physics the same year he died (without ever knowing it). Anton Zeilinger and Alain Aspect will get it any year now.

Then to write this kind of 'insinuations' is just not right.
 
  • #59
DevilsAvocado said:
John Bell was nominated for the Nobel Prize in Physics the same year he died (without ever knowing it).

For his inequality or for the chiral anomaly?
 
  • #60
Inequality

Edit:
I can't find an exact verification... I just took it for granted... it seems illogical not to reward him for what many agrees is one of the most profound discoveries in science, but you never know with these old farts in Stockholm, they've done bigger mistakes...


A Chorus of Bells
http://arxiv.org/abs/1007.0769
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes 1 person
  • #61
DevilsAvocado said:
However, I believe it is not possible to explain EPR-Bell experiments outcome, using only classical logic and classical probability.
If the statement A is true in history H1 and the statement B is true in history H2 the statement A AND B may be meaningless because the histories themself are not compatible. In this sense, you could say that Griffiths abandons classical logic but I don't think this is a very accurate description of the situation.

Like stevendaryl, I don't see the quotes you gave regarding Bell's theorem as controversial. The "third way" is simply not to introduce hidden variables. The only thing in CH which could be called a hidden variable is which history belongs to our world. But such a history is a history of observations and doesn't include simultaneous sharp values of incompatible observables.

/edit: As far as the measurement problem is concerned, it is not obvious to me if and how CH eliminates measurements as primitives but I haven't read the paper yet
 
Last edited:
  • #62
Regarding "classical logic": would it be it would be more accurate to say, like Devils Avocado's comment above, that the usual rules of probability to classical reality are not applied?

Is Bell's theorem meaningless in CH simply because P(A,B,a,b), where A,B are measurement outcomes and a,b are measurement settings, is declared not to exist? A,B,a,b are all classical realities, and we can certainly form P(A,B,a,b) over them without any problem. Or does CH obtain locality by some other means?
 
  • #63
It would appear that if you can live with negative probabilities there should be no problem. This is the only concession to realism that is really necessary. Rather than meaningless perhaps it would be better to think of the amplitude as being imaginary, so the probability is negative. Of course we measure that as a zero hence the violation of the inequality.
http://drchinese.com/David/Bell_Theorem_Negative_Probabilities.htm
 
  • #64
@atyy, kith, Jilang

I think the key to all this is:

[PLAIN said:
http://quantum.phys.cmu.edu/CQT/chaps/cqt24.pdf]This[/PLAIN] [Broken] seems a rather high price to pay just to have a theory which is more “classical” than ordinary quantum mechanics.

And the "high price" is to abandon either locality or realism, which Griffiths obviously is not willing to do.

Problem: No one in this thread seems to be sure on how Griffiths actually preserves this "new" local realism.

Hint: Since Bell was nominated for the Nobel Prize for 'destroying' local realism, I'm pretty sure Griffiths now will get the Nobel Prize for 'restoring' the darned thing, i.e. if we just can get hold of the actual proof...

To-Do: Someone must email Zeilinger & Aspect, and warn them that their experiments will stop working as soon as we have found Griffiths proof!


:smile:
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #65
DevilsAvocado said:
@atyy, kith, Jilang

I think the key to all this is:
And the "high price" is to abandon either locality or realism, which Griffiths obviously is not willing to do.

Problem: No one in this thread seems to be sure on how Griffiths actually preserves this "new" local realism.

Hint: Since Bell was nominated for the Nobel Prize for 'destroying' local realism, I'm pretty sure Griffiths now will get the Nobel Prize for 'restoring' the darned thing, i.e. if we just can get hold of the actual proof...

To-Do: Someone must email Zeilinger & Aspect, and warn them that their experiments will stop working as soon as we have found Griffiths proof!:smile:

Regardless of whether CH is local, I think it is nonrealistic because there are multiple incompatible frameworks, and you can choose anyone of these frameworks to describe "reality". To me the question is whether CH is nonlocal and nonrealistic, or local and nonrealistic. And if it is the latter, why exactly does it evade the Bell theorem? Is it just that P(A,B,a,b) where A,B are classical measurement outcomes and a,b are classical measurement choices?
 
  • #66
atyy said:
I think it is nonrealistic because there are multiple incompatible frameworks, and you can choose anyone of these frameworks to describe "reality".

They consider it realistic, but have their own peculiar version of realism - weak property realism:
http://www.siue.edu/~evailat/pdf/qm12.pdf

Things like this make me laugh - like I say its defining your way out of problems. In doing that I believe it complicates things unnecessarily.

I don't want to be too hard on it however - I have Griffiths book - Consistent Quantum Theory - and its actually quite good. Certainly an excellent source for coming to grips with some of these issues and seeing how CH handles it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #67
According to Laloe http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0209123 (p86, p50), Griffiths's version of CH is local because it rejects counterfactual definiteness, which is an assumption in the proof of Bell's theorem. But if I reject counterfactual definiteness, isn't even dBB local, since the Bell inequality doesn't exist?
 
  • #68
atyy said:
But if I reject counterfactual definiteness, isn't even dBB local, since the Bell inequality doesn't exist?
No. First, you can see that dBB is non-local even without Bell inequality. Indeed, Bell FIRST noted that dBB is non-local, and only AFTER discovered his inequality, as a tool to see non-locality of QM without referring to dBB.
Second, I don't see how one might accept dBB and reject counterfactual definiteness at the same time.
 
  • #69
DevilsAvocado said:
Hint: Since Bell was nominated for the Nobel Prize for 'destroying' local realism, I'm pretty sure Griffiths now will get the Nobel Prize for 'restoring' the darned thing, i.e. if we just can get hold of the actual proof...
If Bell was nominated for the Nobel Prize, it was because he made a new measurable prediction, which was tested by an actual experiment. I don't think that it was the case with Griffiths.

Speaking of nominations for the Nobel Prize, is there an official site where one can see who was nominated and when?
 
  • #70
atyy said:
According to Laloe http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0209123 (p86, p50), Griffiths's version of CH is local because it rejects counterfactual definiteness, which is an assumption in the proof of Bell's theorem. But if I reject counterfactual definiteness, isn't even dBB local, since the Bell inequality doesn't exist?

The whole point of dBB is that it is counterfactual definite. If you take dBB and remove counterfactual definiteness then all you're left with is the pilot wave. At this stage you haven't chosen locality or objective realism yet. You could choose either or both but you certainly don't have dBB anymore.
 
<h2>1. What is "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement"?</h2><p>"Quantum Mechanics without Measurement" is a theoretical framework that suggests that the act of measurement or observation does not play a fundamental role in quantum mechanics. It proposes that the wave function collapse, which is a central concept in traditional quantum mechanics, is not necessary and can be explained through other means.</p><h2>2. How does this differ from traditional quantum mechanics?</h2><p>In traditional quantum mechanics, the act of measurement or observation is considered to be the cause of the wave function collapse, which determines the state of a quantum system. In "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement", the wave function collapse is not considered to be caused by measurement, but rather by other factors such as entanglement or decoherence.</p><h2>3. Is there any evidence to support this theory?</h2><p>There is ongoing research and debate in the scientific community about the validity of "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement". Some experiments, such as the delayed-choice quantum eraser experiment, have shown results that support this theory. However, more research and evidence is needed to fully understand and validate this framework.</p><h2>4. How could this theory impact our understanding of the universe?</h2><p>If "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement" is proven to be a valid framework, it could revolutionize our understanding of the universe and the fundamental laws of physics. It could potentially lead to new technologies and a deeper understanding of quantum phenomena.</p><h2>5. What are the implications of this theory for the famous Schrödinger's cat thought experiment?</h2><p>In Schrödinger's cat thought experiment, the cat is in a superposition of being both alive and dead until an observer opens the box. In "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement", the wave function collapse is not caused by the act of observation, so the cat would not be in a superposition state. This challenges the traditional interpretation of the thought experiment and raises questions about the role of observation in quantum mechanics.</p>

1. What is "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement"?

"Quantum Mechanics without Measurement" is a theoretical framework that suggests that the act of measurement or observation does not play a fundamental role in quantum mechanics. It proposes that the wave function collapse, which is a central concept in traditional quantum mechanics, is not necessary and can be explained through other means.

2. How does this differ from traditional quantum mechanics?

In traditional quantum mechanics, the act of measurement or observation is considered to be the cause of the wave function collapse, which determines the state of a quantum system. In "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement", the wave function collapse is not considered to be caused by measurement, but rather by other factors such as entanglement or decoherence.

3. Is there any evidence to support this theory?

There is ongoing research and debate in the scientific community about the validity of "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement". Some experiments, such as the delayed-choice quantum eraser experiment, have shown results that support this theory. However, more research and evidence is needed to fully understand and validate this framework.

4. How could this theory impact our understanding of the universe?

If "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement" is proven to be a valid framework, it could revolutionize our understanding of the universe and the fundamental laws of physics. It could potentially lead to new technologies and a deeper understanding of quantum phenomena.

5. What are the implications of this theory for the famous Schrödinger's cat thought experiment?

In Schrödinger's cat thought experiment, the cat is in a superposition of being both alive and dead until an observer opens the box. In "Quantum Mechanics without Measurement", the wave function collapse is not caused by the act of observation, so the cat would not be in a superposition state. This challenges the traditional interpretation of the thought experiment and raises questions about the role of observation in quantum mechanics.

Similar threads

Replies
2
Views
787
Replies
11
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
12
Views
613
Replies
2
Views
345
Replies
12
Views
687
Replies
1
Views
561
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
890
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
3
Views
195
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
3
Views
134
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
876
Back
Top