In summary: That confirms my (still superficial) understanding that now I'm allowed to interpret ##\hat{\rho}## and the trace operation as expectation values in the usual statistical sense, and that makes the new approach much more understandable than what you called before "thermal interpretation".I also think that the entire conception is not much different from the minimal statistical interpretation. The only change to the "traditional" concept seems to be that you use the more general concept of POVM than the von Neumann filter measurements, which are only a special case.The only objection I have is the statement concerning EPR. It cannot be right, because local realistic theories are not consistent with the quantum-theoretical probability theory, which
  • #141
A. Neumaier said:
So you finally agree that standard quantum theory involves more than Born's rule in order to relate the mathematical formalsim to experiment!.

Indeed, standard quantum physics has a most pragmatic approach to the interpretation of the formalism: Anything goes that gives agreement with experiment, and Born's rule is just a tool applicable in some situations, whereas other tools (such as resonance observations or POVMs) apply in other situations.

Can we agree on that?
Sure, but the Born rule is one of the basic postulates that's behind all these pragmatic approaches. In Newtonian mechanics there's also much more then the "three laws" to apply it to the analysis of the pgenomena, but they are behind all the corresponding methods.
 
  • Love
Likes bhobba
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #142
vanhees71 said:
Sure, but the Born rule is one of the basic postulates that's behind all these pragmatic approaches.
behind all these??

How is Born's rule behind the measurement of the energy difference of two levels of a quantum system?
 
  • #143
You meassure it, e.g., by burning hydrogen and measure the wave lengths of the light using a grating. For that you accumulate a lot of photons. The intensity of the different lines is predicted using Born's rule.
 
  • #144
vanhees71 said:
You measure it, e.g., by burning hydrogen and measure the wave lengths of the light using a grating.
But nothing is burnt in a Penning trap, which is the example under discussion.
vanhees71 said:
For that you accumulate a lot of photons. The intensity of the different lines is predicted using Born's rule.
But the intensity of the lines gives no information at all about the energy differences.

The frequency of the photons emitted by the trapped electron, and hence the determination of the position of the resonance peaks from which the high precision gyrofactor is computed is independent of Born's rule.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #145
The evaluation of experimental data never uses the quantum formalism. The interpretation of these data of an electron in a Penning trap, however, and thus the "mapping" of measured "beat frequencies" and their mapping to the value of ##(g-2)## is based on the QT formalism. This is of course not directly related to Born's rule but to the evaluation of the energy eigenvalues of the electron in the trap (the "geonium"). Even the noisy signal should be predictable by QT and that's then again based on Born's rule.
 
  • #146
vanhees71 said:
The evaluation of experimental data never uses the quantum formalism. The interpretation of these data of an electron in a Penning trap, however, and thus the "mapping" of measured "beat frequencies" and their mapping to the value of ##(g-2)## is based on the QT formalism.
More precisely, on the quantum formalism without Born's rule.
vanhees71 said:
This is of course not directly related to Born's rule
It is of course not related at all to it.
vanhees71 said:
but to the evaluation of the energy eigenvalues of the electron in the trap (the "geonium"). Even the noisy signal should be predictable by QT
It is, again by the quantum formalism without Born's rule.
vanhees71 said:
and that's then again based on Born's rule.
Only because you apply again your magic wand that turns every quantum calculation into an instance of Born's rule.
 
  • #147
I think, we won't find an agreement on the status of Born's rule, which I still consider as one of the foundational postulates of QT, without which there's no interpretation at all. Of course, the frequencies in spectroscopy are differences of energy levels and not directly related with Born's rule but rather to the quantum dynamics, usually derived by 1st-order time-dependent PT in the dipole approximation for (spontaneous and induced) photon emission, i.e., based on the dynamical laws and the meaning of the Hamiltonian. The transition probabilities, also obtained in this same calculation, are of course based on Born's rule.

I stop this discussion at this point.
 
  • Like
Likes Lord Jestocost
  • #148
vanhees71 said:
Of course, the frequencies in spectroscopy are differences of energy levels and not directly related with Born's rule but rather to the quantum dynamics, usually derived by 1st-order time-dependent PT in the dipole approximation for (spontaneous and induced) photon emission, i.e., based on the dynamical laws and the meaning of the Hamiltonian.
I agree. No interpretation is needed for this; it predates Born's rule by at least a year.

But it shows that Born's rule doesn't explain quantum measurements of a spectroscopic nature. The latter includes all high precision determinations of constants of Nature such as gyrofactors, mass ratios, etc.
vanhees71 said:
The transition probabilities, also obtained in this same calculation, are of course based on Born's rule.
I agree. But this is independent of the value of the frequencies, and only the latter are measured in the experiment under discussion.
 
  • #149
Of course it's not only Born's rule but all the other postulates of QT too. Of course the predictions of "old QM" a la Bohr and Sommerfeld concerning atomic spectra predate "new QM" and thus also Born's rule by more than a decade (though they are all wrong except for hydrogen ;-)).
 
  • #150
fresh_42 said:
Do I miss something?

Probably not. Less formally a Von-Neumann observation is represented by disjoint positive valued operators Ei such that sum Ei = 1. A POVM is simply a generalisation that removes the need to be disjoint. It turns out Gleason's Theorem is much easier to prove for POVM's. In practice, they occur when for example you observe a system with a probe then observe the probe. See for example:
http://www.quantum.umb.edu/Jacobs/QMT/QMT_Chapter1.pdf

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes LittleSchwinger and vanhees71
  • #151
Perhaps you touched upon this elsewhere.
A. Neumaier said:
Yes, that's what quantum tomography is about.

To accurately determine a momentum vector one also needs more than one measurement.
From the perspective of inference: learning the hamiltonian is as much of a challenge as knowledge of the initial state, and in a real situation the two problems must interfere with each other. I think determining the state is referred to as the state tomography, but determining the hamiltonian is the process tomography?

If one insists that knowledge of the state and the state of the unitary evolution that is applied to the state both qualify as "information", how would one realize the simultaneous process of process and state tomography? Or do you reason as if the hamiltonian and hilbert space is given facts? (not subject to inquiry, subject to similarly critical analysis?)

/Fredrik
 
  • #152
Fra said:
Perhaps you touched upon this elsewhere.

From the perspective of inference: learning the hamiltonian is as much of a challenge as knowledge of the initial state, and in a real situation the two problems must interfere with each other. I think determining the state is referred to as the state tomography, but determining the hamiltonian is the process tomography?
Yes, in the special case where the system is conservative; otherwise no hamiltonian exists, only a system of Lindblad generators.
Fra said:
If one insists that knowledge of the state and the state of the unitary evolution that is applied to the state both qualify as "information", how would one realize the simultaneous process of process and state tomography?
This is called self-calibrating tomography. See p.38 of my paper, where I also give some references where further details can be found.
 
  • Like
Likes Fra and bhobba
  • #153
vanhees71 said:
The evaluation of experimental data never uses the quantum formalism. The interpretation of these data of an electron in a Penning trap, however, and thus the "mapping" of measured "beat frequencies" and their mapping to the value of ##(g-2)## is based on the QT formalism.
In the mean time I revised my tomography paper. The new version is better structured and contains a new section on high precision quantum measurements, where the 12 digit accuracy determination of the gyromagnetic ration through the observation and analysis of a single electron in a Penning trap is discussed in some detail.

The standard analysis assumes that the single electron is described by a time-dependent density operator following a differential equation. While in the original papers this involved arguments beyond the traditional (ensemble-based and knowledge-based) interpretations of quantum mechanics, the new tomography-based approach applies without difficulties.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and bhobba
  • #154
In the Penning-trap case aren't there the currents of the "mirror charges" in the trap electrodes observed? I'd also expect that what's measured follows within the standard framework is the current due to the motion of the electron within the trap. I'll have a look on your new chapter about this in terms of the POVM formalism.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #155
Ok, I had a look at it. In Sect. 9.4 you also don't construct a POVM explicitly for this standard Penning-trap setup. There's no formula there :-(.

I also don't understand, what's problematic with the standard treatment in Brown and Gabrielse's RMP article. It's just 1st-order perturbation theory in RPA approximation (in Sect. V.A).
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #156
vanhees71 said:
what's problematic with the standard treatment in Brown and Gabrielse's RMP article.
What's problematic, especially for the ensemble interpretation (and Rigo et al. explicitly acknowledge that it goes beyond the standard treatment) is that they use a density operator to describe a single electron rather than an ensemble of electrons. This ensemble is purely imagined (sa, Brown and Gabrielse state explicitly) and has no physical reality. It is needed to derive the formula by which the gyromagnetic ratio is measured.
vanhees71 said:
In the Penning-trap case aren't there the currents of the "mirror charges" in the trap electrodes observed?
Their paper says that they measured two particular frequencies (how doesn't really matter for my paper, but you can find more details by reading their paper yourself), whose quotient gives the gyromagnetic ratio to 12 decimal places.
vanhees71 said:
In Sect. 9.4 you also don't construct a POVM explicitly for this standard Penning-trap setup.
This is because parameter determination such as that of the gyromagnetic ratio, and in fact most of spectroscopy, is not a quantum measurement in the sense of Born's rule nor is it one in in the sense of POVMs. But is uses the objective existence of the density operator and its dissipative dynamics, which are consequences of the detector response principle DRP on which the whole paper is based. That's why I added the material to the paper.

Note that my paper is not primarily about POVMs but about how quantum tomography explains quantum mechanics. Deriving the POVM formalism, including Born's rule where it applies is only a small part of the whole story.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #157
What's measured are currents, and the necessary amplifiers and the ampere meter do some "time averaging". I thought, it would be possible to describe this with the POVM formalism. So my challenge is standing: How can the abstract POVM formalism be made applicable to describe a real-world experiment in the lab. I've never heard anybody using it to describe a real-world experiment yet.

Another (gedanken) experiment is the measurement of a "trajectory" of a single particle in a cloud chamber. You can put some radioactive material in there and make a movie of the tracks forming, i.e., you can measure directly how the track forms, i.e., a position-momentum joint measurement. The standard quantum description a la Mott is very clear and for me describes the appearance of "trajectories" in this setup satisfactory, but maybe it's interesting to discuss it within the POVM framework too?
 
  • #158
vanhees71 said:
So my challenge is standing: How can the abstract POVM formalism be made applicable to describe a real-world experiment in the lab.
The whole of Section 4 of my paper is devoted to real-world experiments that use POVMs rather than projective measurement, with reference to other people's work.
vanhees71 said:
I've never heard anybody using it to describe a real-world experiment yet.
This can only mean that you never bothered to read the associated literature. For example, the quantum information textbook by Nielsen and Chuang is full of POVMs.
Nielsen and Chuang (p.91) said:
Most introductions to quantum mechanics describe only projective measurements, and consequently the general description of measurements given in Postulate 3 may be unfamiliar to many physicists, as may the POVM formalism described in Section 2.2.6. The reason most physicists don’t learn the general measurement formalism is because most physical systems can only be measured in a very coarse manner. In quantum computation and quantum information we aim for an exquisite level of control over the measurements that may be done, and consequently it helps to use a more comprehensive formalism for the description of measurements. [...]

A physicist trained in the use of projective measurements might ask to what end we start with the general formalism, Postulate 3? There are several reasons for doing so. First, mathematically general measurements are in some sense simpler than projective measurements, since they involve fewer restrictions on the measurement operators; there is, for example, no requirement for general measurements analogous to the condition ##P_iP_j = \delta_{ij}P_i## for projective measurements. This simpler structure also gives rise to many useful properties for general measurements that are not possessed by projective measurements. Second, it turns out that there are important problems in quantum computation and quantum information – such as the optimal way to distinguish a set of quantum states – the answer to which involves a general measurement, rather than a projective measurement. A third reason [... is ...] the fact that many important measurements in quantum mechanics are not projective measurements.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #159
vanhees71 said:
the measurement of a "trajectory" of a single particle in a cloud chamber. You can put some radioactive material in there and make a movie of the tracks forming, i.e., you can measure directly how the track forms, i.e., a position-momentum joint measurement. The standard quantum description a la Mott is very clear and for me describes the appearance of "trajectories" in this setup satisfactory, but maybe it's interesting to discuss it within the POVM framework too?
The POVM description of this is similar to that of the joint position-momentum measurement of particle tracks in my Section 4.4, except that the arrangement of wires is replaced by the pixels of the video taken.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #160
f1.png

-
f2.png

-
Repeated, nondestructive measurements of the same quantity of the same system should yield the same result each time, I think. This isn't guaranteed for POVMs right? Is there a distinction between asserting a detector imperfectly measures a standard observable built from a projective decomposition, and a detector exactly measuring a quantity built from a POVM like the one above?
 
  • #161
Morbert said:
Repeated, nondestructive measurements of the same quantity of the same system should yield the same result each time, I think. This isn't guaranteed for POVMs right? Is there a distinction between asserting a detector imperfectly measures a standard observable built from a projective decomposition, and a detector exactly measuring a quantity built from a POVM like the one above?
The distinction is the word 'projective'. Dirac and von Neumann considered only measurements whose repetition yield the same result each time, and were thus lead to the class of projective measurements.

But most measurements in practice are not of this kind, as either each realization of the system can be typically measured only once, or each measurement on the system measures a different state of the system but never the projected one.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes bhobba, vanhees71, gentzen and 1 other person
  • #162
A. Neumaier said:
or each measurement on the system measures a different state of the system but never the projected one.
The typical example is a faint temporary interaction which changes the system state only slightly (not by projection) but leaves an irreversible record, hence counts as measurement. Particle track detectors are based on this.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba, gentzen and vanhees71
  • #163
As an aside, I think this important character of POVMs (repeated measurements not yielding identical results) is preserved even if we expand the state space to recover a projective measurement a la Luis and Sanchez-Soto (equation 1). The significance of the projector |k><k| in equation 1 is merely that the record of a single measurement will not change no matter how many times the record is reviewed.
[edit]- Then again, maybe the carelessness of the researcher reviewing past records can be modeled with a POVM : )
 
  • #164
But I think, that's a feature of the POVM approach. Almost all real-lab measurements are not projective measurements, and it doesn't make sense to assume a collapse to the projection of the state to the eigenspace of the measured eigenvalue of the self-adjoint operator that represents the measured observable as a generally valid postulate. It rather depends on the kind of interaction between the measured object and the measurement device, what happens to the object in measurement. E.g., if you detect a photon usually it's absorbed in the material. Usually what's used in photon detection is the photo effect, i.e., afterwards there's no photon left to be in any state, and thus you also don't need a state for this photon to describe its behavior. In such cases I guess one could use a POVM to describe the measurement process. However, so far nobody could give a concrete example, how to describe a given measurement procedure with a POVM. I always get the answer that one cannot do that.

My challenge stands: The most simple example for a unsharp joint measurement of position and momentum of a particle seems to be the example that is described (imho fully satisfactory) by Mott in the famous paper about the tracks of a charged particle in a cloud chamber. One can extend this indeed to an observation of approximate positions and momenta by simply taking a movie and measuring the position of the end of the track as a function of time and then deduce both a position and the momentum of the particle along this track. Shouldn't it be possible to describe this (gedanken) experiment in terms of a POVM?
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #165
vanhees71 said:
But I think, that's a feature of the POVM approach. Almost all real-lab measurements are not projective measurements, and it doesn't make sense to assume a collapse to the projection of the state to the eigenspace of the measured eigenvalue of the self-adjoint operator that represents the measured observable as a generally valid postulate. It rather depends on the kind of interaction between the measured object and the measurement device, what happens to the object in measurement. E.g., if you detect a photon usually it's absorbed in the material. Usually what's used in photon detection is the photo effect, i.e., afterwards there's no photon left to be in any state, and thus you also don't need a state for this photon to describe its behavior. In such cases I guess one could use a POVM to describe the measurement process. However, so far nobody could give a concrete example, how to describe a given measurement procedure with a POVM. I always get the answer that one cannot do that.
I'm going to naively apply consistent histories to try and construct one.
Say you want to destructively measure the linear polarisation of a photon (system ##s##), which is registered by a detector (system ##D##) at time ##t_1##. Unitary evolution would look like $$U\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(|V\rangle+|H\rangle)|D_0\rangle = \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(|D_V\rangle+|D_H\rangle)$$ We write down the histories $$C_H=|H\rangle\langle H|(t_1-\delta t) \otimes D_H(t_1)$$$$C_V=|V\rangle\langle V|(t_1-\delta t) \otimes D_V(t_1)$$
We can construct the POVM with the two members $$P_V=\mathrm{tr}_D \rho_D C_VC_V^\dagger$$$$P_H=\mathrm{tr}_D \rho_D C_HC_H^\dagger$$
 
  • #166
How can unitary transformation go out of the Hilbert space? A unitary operator is an isomorphism on a fixed Hilbert space and not between two different Hilbert spaces as you write in your 1st formula.
 
  • #167
vanhees71 said:
How can unitary transformation go out of the Hilbert space? A unitary operator is an isomorphism on a fixed Hilbert space and not between two different Hilbert spaces as you write in your 1st formula.
I am assuming ##|D_H\rangle,|D_V\rangle## are members of ##\mathcal{H}_\mathrm{phonon}\otimes\mathcal{H}_\mathrm{detector}## but not ##\mathcal{H}_\mathrm{detector}##, such that e.g. ##U^\dagger|D_H\rangle = |H\rangle|D_0\rangle## but maybe this is too naive
 
  • #168
vanhees71 said:
I always get the answer that one cannot do that.
That's not true. You always got the answer that it can be done only if you specify the full measuring process from the interaction of the measured system till the measurement results. And then you lost patience or interest, and didn't follow up on my answers.

vanhees71 said:
The most simple example for a unsharp joint measurement of position and momentum of a particle seems to be the example that is described (imho fully satisfactory) by Mott in the famous paper about the tracks of a charged particle in a cloud chamber.
Mott does not perform a single measurement in his analysis. So how can one extract a POVM from his discussion if nothing is measured? The POVM would depend on details about how the cloud chamber track is observed to actually get the results of the measurement.

vanhees71 said:
One can extend this indeed to an observation of approximate positions and momenta by simply taking a movie and measuring the position of the end of the track as a function of time and then deduce both a position and the momentum of the particle along this track. Shouldn't it be possible to describe this (gedanken) experiment in terms of a POVM?
Now that you defined a recipe for getting a position and momentum that can be carried out experimentally, this is indeed possible. Your recipe leads to a POVM in essentially the same way as my analysis in Section 4.4 of v4 of my quantum tomography paper, except that the grid of wires is replaced by a grid of pixels encoding the video. That this POVM is complicated comes from the fact that extracting a position and a momentum from a video is complicated.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and dextercioby
  • #169
Morbert said:
I am assuming ##|D_H\rangle,|D_V\rangle## are members of ##\mathcal{H}_\mathrm{phonon}\otimes\mathcal{H}_\mathrm{detector}## but not ##\mathcal{H}_\mathrm{detector}##, such that e.g. ##U^\dagger|D_H\rangle = |H\rangle|D_0\rangle## but maybe this is too naive
This is not too naive but too sloppy to be correct. In fact you define
##|D_H\rangle :=U(|H\rangle|D_0\rangle)## and similarly ##|D_V\rangle##, and your formula follows.
 
  • #170
A. Neumaier said:
That's not true. You always got the answer that it can be done only if you specify the full measuring process from the interaction of the measured system till the measurement results. And then you lost patience or interest, and didn't follow up on my answers.
You never gave a concrete answer. That's the problem.
A. Neumaier said:
Mott does not perform a single measurement in his analysis. So how can one extract a POVM from his discussion if nothing is measured? The POVM would depend on details about how the cloud chamber track is observed to actually get the results of the measurement.Now that you defined a recipe for getting a position and momentum that can be carried out experimentally, this is indeed possible. Your recipe leads to a POVM in essentially the same way as my analysis in Section 4.4 of v4 of my quantum tomography paper, except that the grid of wires is replaced by a grid of pixels encoding the video. That this POVM is complicated comes from the fact that extracting a position and a momentum from a video is complicated.
Were is the concrete POVM given in this paper?
 
  • #171
vanhees71 said:
You never gave a concrete answer. That's the problem.

Where is the concrete POVM given in this paper?
The very concrete answer is in the last paragraph of Section 4.4 on p.32. I had several times referred to it. The POVM consists of the quantum measure together with a reindexing of the matrices by the measurement results.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #172
There are many words, no concrete construction of the POVM.
 
  • #173
vanhees71 said:
There are many words, no concrete construction of the POVM.
The words define in the first sentence a unique quantum measure. The relabeling needed to get the POVM is described in the remainder, and can be exactly described by the computer programs used to analyze the video (in your version of the experiment), summing the contributions that lead to the same label. Since you described the analysis of the video in words only, I cannot do better.

Thus the construction of the POVM is as concrete as your gedanken experiment.
 
  • #174
We obviously have a different understanding what "concrete" means. I don't know, how experimental particle physicists program their computers, but I'm pretty sure, it's not based on the POVM paradigm of quantum measurement theory. I don't blame you, but I simply like to understand, what's behind this POVM idea in a physical context rather than a mathematical abstract concept.

It seems to be very difficult to construct it for even a so much simpler setup as a measurement of "particle tracks" with a cloud chamber...
 
  • #175
vanhees71 said:
We obviously have a different understanding what "concrete" means. I don't know, how experimental particle physicists program their computers, but I'm pretty sure, it's not based on the POVM paradigm of quantum measurement theory.
That's not necessary to apply the POVM principles. They also don't base it on the projective paradigm of quantum measurement theory that you favor.

Instead they rely on the claims of manufacturers or peers how the equipment works. Almost every experimental reasoning is completely classical, together with a little semiclassical quantum mechanics for some crucial points.

vanhees71 said:
I don't blame you, but I simply like to understand, what's behind this POVM idea in a physical context rather than a mathematical abstract concept.

It seems to be very difficult to construct it for even a so much simpler setup as a measurement of "particle tracks" with a cloud chamber...
This is because your question is not adapted to how POVMs are actually used.

In practice, people (i) either have a given setup and want to calibrate it; so they do quantum tomography to find the POVM. Or (ii) they want to realize a given POVM with a suitable experiment. The latter is particularly relevant for potential applications in quantum computing.

In my paper, (i) is described in full detail and full generality in Section 2.2, and (ii) is described for a multiphoton setting in Section 4.1, and in more detail in the papers by Leonhardt cited there.

The exact POVM of concrete experiments is as complex as the experimental setting itself. But when one measures something one is not interested in these details unless ones want to construct a more accurate detector. Thus one usually idealizes the description to the bare minimum.

One can do the same for POVMs. For a joint measurement of position and momentum this is done in Section 4.2. The formula there is physically motivated and as simple as one can want it; the experimental realization is given in the paper cited there. For the partition of unity one can take any collection of hat functions describing the smearing, divided by their sum.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
42
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
35
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
13
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
687
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
7
Replies
223
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
11
Replies
376
Views
10K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
94
Views
4K
Back
Top