Rational functions in one indeterminate - useful concept?

In summary: As mentioned in the OP, I don't mean quotients of polynomials that are functions. I mean quotients of polynomials that are regarded only as "expressions" - the so-called polynomials "in one indeterminate". For example, the function ##f(x) = \frac{(x-3)(x-2)}{(x-6)} ## does not have a multiplicative inverse function that is defined on the same domain. However, the formal expression ## f([x]) = \frac{([x] -3)([x]-2)}{([x]-6)}## has the multiplicative inverse expression ##f
  • #1
Stephen Tashi
Science Advisor
7,861
1,598
TL;DR Summary
Is the concept of rational functions in one indeterminate useful in algebra?
The examples of "formal" power series and polynomials in one indeterminate are familiar and useful in algebra. However, I don't recall the example of rational functions (ratios of polynomials) in one indeterminate being used for anything. Is that concept useful? - or trivial? -or equivalent to something that's called by a different name?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
What do you mean by "useful"?

What are quotient fields of integral domains good for?
What are transcendental field extensions good for?
Where are rational transformations ##t \longmapsto \dfrac{ax+b}{cx+d}## used?
 
  • #3
fresh_42 said:
What do you mean by "useful"?
By useful, I mean of sufficient instructive value to be used in texts on algebra as an interesting example of some well known abstract structure - such as a ring or module or field.

What are quotient fields of integral domains good for?
Are you accusing me of being interested in applied mathematics? I am, but my question isn't about practical applications.
 
  • #4
I do not accuse anybody. I just don't understand the question. What is Lüroth's theorem good for? It exists. And quotient fields also exist, so does ##\mathbb{Q}(x)##. Same with transcendental extensions in contrast to algebraic extensions. They are algebraically useful for their insertion homomorphisms ##x \longmapsto \vartheta##. The restriction on one variable as well as on ##\mathbb{Q}## is what narrows down the usefulness. Otherwise we would enter algebraic geometry and general quotient rings.
 
  • #5
fresh_42 said:
I just don't understand the question.

I don't understand the replies formulated as questions. I can't tell whether your point is ask about the utility of algebraic structures in general or whether you mean each of your questions to hint at a case where rational functions in one indeterminate are a good example. If you can confirm that each of your questions is meant to hint at a use of rational functions in one indeterminate as an example , I can probably look up the details.
 
  • #6
There isn't much to it. You said rational functions, i.e. quotients of polynomials. Now we have
$$
\underbrace{\mathbb{Q}[x]}_{integral\;domain} \subseteq \underbrace{\mathbb{Q}(x)}_{quotient \;field}=\underbrace{\mathbb{Q}[x,x^{-1}]}_{transcendental \;extension}
$$
It is one specific example of a field. One can generalize it by changing the field of rationals to arbitrary rings, by more than one variable, by algebraic extensions instead of transcendental, by series instead of polynomials. But as is, it is just a certain field. To ask about its uses is similar to ask about the use of any other field.
 
  • Like
Likes Stephen Tashi
  • #7
What do you mean with rational functions? Quotients of polynomials? If yes, here are some applications:

- Möbius transformations in the complex plane.

- Rational functions are widely used in algebraic geometry in the theory of local rings to describe the local behaviour of curves (think about intersection numbers).

- Quotient fields give a way to canonically embed any domain in a field. This is often useful! If you want to prove something about a domain, embed it in its quotient field and use that you have more structure there to get information on the original ring. Gauss' lemma in ring theory comes to mind.

Last week I was wondering if we can embed every ring in a semisimple ring. For domains, this is easy because you can embed a domain in their fields of fractions. This made me realize I needed to find a non-domain if the answer is negative. That way, I quickly came up with the counterexample ##\mathbb{Z}/4 \mathbb{Z}## so yes, these fraction fields have good advantages and give good examples of rings.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #8
Math_QED said:
What do you mean with rational functions? Quotients of polynomials?

As mentioned in the OP, I don't mean quotients of polynomials that are functions. I mean quotients of polynomials that are regarded only as "expressions" - the so-called polynomials "in one indeterminate". For example, the function ##f(x) = \frac{(x-3)(x-2)}{(x-6)} ## does not have a multiplicative inverse function that is defined on the same domain. However, the formal expression ## f([x]) = \frac{([x] -3)([x]-2)}{([x]-6)}## has the multiplicative inverse expression ##f[x] = \frac{([x]-6)}{([x] -3)([x]-2)}##. There is no worry about dividing by zero, because the operations are defined as algorithms applied to symbolic expressions - the way a naive algebra student would manipulate them.
 
  • #9
Stephen Tashi said:
As mentioned in the OP, I don't mean quotients of polynomials that are functions. I mean quotients of polynomials that are regarded only as "expressions" - the so-called polynomials "in one indeterminate". For example, the function ##f(x) = \frac{(x-3)(x-2)}{(x-6)} ## does not have a multiplicative inverse function that is defined on the same domain. However, the formal expression ## f([x]) = \frac{([x] -3)([x]-2)}{([x]-6)}## has the multiplicative inverse expression ##f[x] = \frac{([x]-6)}{([x] -3)([x]-2)}##. There is no worry about dividing by zero, because the operations are defined as algorithms applied to symbolic expressions - the way a naive algebra student would manipulate them.
You don't need absolute values. It works for ##f(x)=\dfrac{(x-3)(x-2)}{x-6}## as well, and it is what I described in post #6. It's a transcendental extension of degree one, the quotient field of the integral domain, the polynomial ring in one variable. @Math_QED didn't mean functions, except perhaps the Möbius transformation. As it is a quotient field, it is a standard example how they are created. The way from integers to rationals is the same. ##x## isn't a variable here. it is an element of a ring, resp. a field.
 
  • #10
fresh_42 said:
You don't need absolute values.

Agreed. I typed square brackets to hint that "##[x]##" is not a numerical argument.

As I understand the notation "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" and "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" can denote distinct concepts. With "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" there is the fact that ##(\sqrt{2})(\sqrt{2}) = 2 \in \mathbb{Q}##. However, with "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" there is no implication that some polynomial in ##x## can be identified with an element of ##\mathbb{Q}##. Is that correct?
 
  • #11
No, both are rings, so the concept is the same. ##\mathbb{Q}[\alpha]## denotes the ring of rational expressions ##a_0 \alpha^n+\ldots +a_{n-1}\alpha+a_{n}## regardless whether ##\alpha = \sqrt{2}## or ##\alpha=x##. In the first case we have an algebraic extension of the rationals where ##\alpha^2-2=0## holds, in the second a transcendental where no such algebraic identification exists. We can as well write ##\mathbb{Q}[x]\cong\mathbb{Q}[\pi]\cong\mathbb{Q}[e]##.
 
  • #12
fresh_42 said:
In the first case we have an algebraic extension of the rationals where ##\alpha^2-2=0## holds,
That's what I was asking about. The notation "##Q[\sqrt{2}]##" conveys to the reader that the special condition ##\alpha^2 -2 = 0## is understood to hold.

Although ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## is distinct from a set of functions, it is still possible to think of composing members of ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## using the manpulations from elementary algebra that implement substituting one expression in for another. What is the proper term for ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## with this added structure? Or am I being too optimistic that that composition of members of ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## can be well defined?
 
  • #13
I do not understand what you mean. There is an "insertion" ring homomorphism
$$
\varphi_r\, : \,\mathbb{Q}[x] \longrightarrow \mathbb{Q}[r]
$$
where the polynomials are evaluated at ##x=r\in \mathbb{Q}##.

If in the previous example with ##\alpha^2-2=0##, then we can consider the ideal ##\mathcal{I}\subseteq \mathbb{Q}[x]## generated by the polynomial ##p(x)=x^2-2##. In this case we get an isomorphism
$$
\mathbb{Q}[x]/\mathcal{I}=\mathbb{Q}[x]/\langle x^2-2\rangle \cong \mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]=\mathbb{Q}[\alpha]
$$
The (principle) ideal ##\mathcal{I}## consists of all polynomials of ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## which are divisible by ##x^2-2\,.## So in a way ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## is the special case where ##p(x)=0##. For ##p(x)=1## we get ##\{\,0\,\}##, and for ##p(x)=x## we get ##\mathbb{Q}##. This all is basic algebra, or commutative algebra in this case.
 
  • #14
Stephen Tashi said:
Agreed. I typed square brackets to hint that "##[x]##" is not a numerical argument.

As I understand the notation "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" and "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" can denote distinct concepts. With "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" there is the fact that ##(\sqrt{2})(\sqrt{2}) = 2 \in \mathbb{Q}##. However, with "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" there is no implication that some polynomial in ##x## can be identified with an element of ##\mathbb{Q}##. Is that correct?

I think it is clearer to introduce this notation in a more formal setting. Let ##K,F##be fields with ##F\subseteq K##. Let ##\alpha\in K##.

Then ##F[\alpha]## is by definition the smallest subring of ##K## containing ##\alpha## and ##F##.

So, it really can be thought of as: adjoin ##`\alpha\in K## to ##F## and see what ring it generates.

In our case,we just add ##\sqrt{2}## to ##\mathbb{Q}## and see what the smallest ring is containing both ##\mathbb{Q}## and ##\sqrt{2}##.

One can prove that:

$$F[\alpha]=\{f(\alpha)\mid f\in F[X]\}$$

and you can then visualise this ring as
a polynomial ring ##F[X]## with ##X## replaced by ##\alpha##, but with possibly more relations! Hence the notation we give it makes sense. At least that'the way I view it.
 
  • #15
fresh_42 said:
I do not understand what you mean. There is an "insertion" ring homomorphism
$$
\varphi_r\, : \,\mathbb{Q}[x] \longrightarrow \mathbb{Q}[r]
$$
where the polynomials are evaluated at ##x=r\in \mathbb{Q}##.

I was thinking about a substitution that amounts to composing functions. For example, ##f(x) = x^3 + 2x + 1, g(x) = x^2 - 6 ## , ##f(g(x)) = g(x)^3 + 2(g(x)) + 1 ## = some 6th degree polynomial.
 
  • #16
Math_QED said:
I think it is clearer to introduce this notation in a more formal setting. Let ##K,F##be fields with ##F\subseteq K##. Let ##\alpha\in K##.

Then ##F[\alpha]## is by definition the smallest subring of ##K## containing ##\alpha## and ##F##.

I agree that giving all the background information is clearer. As I interpret tradition, it's traditional to leave it up to the reader to supply the identity of ##K## based on inferring what familiar field contains ##\alpha##.
 
  • #17
Stephen Tashi said:
I agree that giving all the background information is clearer. As I interpret tradition, it's traditional to leave it up to the reader to supply the identity of ##K## based on inferring what familiar field contains ##\alpha##.

Yes, because it doesn't matter, in the following sense:

Let ##F \subseteq K \subseteq L## and ##\alpha \in K##. Then you can form ##F_K[\alpha], F_L[\alpha]## as I explained earlier (in the fields ##K,L##). You can then show that ##F_K[\alpha] = F_L[\alpha]##, so the notation ##F[\alpha]## is justified.

So, whether you consider ##\sqrt{2}\in \mathbb{R}## or ##\sqrt{2}\in \mathbb{C}## or ##\sqrt{2} \in \mathbb{C}(X)##, it won't affect what ##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]## is.
 
  • Like
Likes fresh_42
  • #18
Math_QED said:
Let F⊆K⊆LF \subseteq K \subseteq L and α∈K\alpha \in K.

I think of "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" as denoting a ring of polynomials and "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" as denoting a field. Is there a feature of the notation that I'm missing which distinguishes between ring and field?

If I consider "##[3]##" to denote a member of ##\mathbb{Z}_7## then (to me) the notation "##\mathbb{Q}[[3]]##" conveys the idea of forming all possible polynomials in powers of ##[3]## and then simplifying the powers according to the arithmetic of ##\mathbb{Z}_7##. So I'm trying to extend the field ##\mathbb{Q}## by an element that is not in a field containing ##\mathbb{Q}##. Is there special notation or terminology for this type of extension?
 
  • #19
Stephen Tashi said:
I think of "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" as denoting a ring of polynomials and "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" as
##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]## is constructed as ring, yes, which is why the brackets are squarish. But
$$
\dfrac{1}{\sqrt{2}} = \dfrac{1}{2} \cdot \sqrt{2}
$$
implies, that it is at the same time a field, i.e. ##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]=\mathbb{Q}(\sqrt{2})## which is not the case for transcendental extensions.

IIRC the notation ##\mathbb{Q}[[\cdot]] ## is reserved for power series. And you must not switch between different characteristics. How should arithmetic be possible in such a set?
 
  • #20
Stephen Tashi said:
I think of "##\mathbb{Q}[x]##" as denoting a ring of polynomials and "##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]##" as denoting a field. Is there a feature of the notation that I'm missing which distinguishes between ring and field?

Let's go back to our formal setting.

##F[\alpha]## is by definition the smallest subring of ##K## containing ##F## and ##\alpha##
##F(\alpha)## is by definition the smallest subfield of ##K## containing ##F## and ##\alpha##.

It is well known that ##F[\alpha] = F( \alpha)## if and only if ##\alpha## is algebraic over ##F##, i.e. ##\alpha## is a root of a non-zero polynomial with coefficients in ##F##.

So, you are right ##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]## is a field, because ##\sqrt{2}## is algebraic over ##\mathbb{Q}## (it is a zero of ##X^2-2##). Thus ##\mathbb{Q}[\sqrt{2}]= \mathbb{Q}(\sqrt{2})##.

As @fresh_42 correctly pointed out, it is in general not true that ##F[\alpha]## is a field. Indeed, ##\mathbb{Q}[\pi]## is not a field because ##\pi## is not algebraic over ##\mathbb{Q}##.
 
  • #21
Math_QED said:
As @fresh_42 correctly pointed out, it is in general not true that ##F[\alpha]## is a field. Indeed, ##\mathbb{Q}[\pi]## is not a field because ##\pi## is not algebraic over ##\mathbb{Q}##.

A conceptual distintion that I see between extending ##\mathbb{Q}## by an "indeterminate" and extending it by a transcendental number is that extending by an indeterminate opens the possibility of defining an operation on two elements of ##\mathbb{Q}[x]## that corresponds to the composition of two functions, as mentioned in post #15. In ##\mathbb{Q}[\pi]## it would be awkward to think of substituting an arbitrary element of ##\mathbb{Q}[\pi]## for ##\pi##.
 
  • #22
The Wikipedia article on "composition ring" https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Composition_ring includes a polynomial ring ##R[x]## as an example. However, I think the article does not define composition in a technically correct way. The article treats the elements of ##R[x]## as if they are necessarily functions. Given how tedious it is to define operations in ##R[x]## without assuming the elements are functions, I forgive the authors.
 
  • #23
A few remarks: if f(x,y) is an irreducible polynomial with complex coefficients, then the locus f=0 defines a plane curve N in C^2, whose ring of polynomial functions equals the integral domain C[x,y]/(f). I.e. this is the ring of polynomial functions on the plane restricted to N, so that those which equal zero on N are set equal to zero. The field of fractions of this domain is called the field of rational functions on N. This field is isomorphic to the field of meromorphic functions on the Riemann surface of N, i.e. the compactified desingularization of N. It is a theorem that a compact non singular connected one dimensional complex manifold is determined up to isomorphism by its field of meromorphic functions.

The special case where f = y, gives the field C(x), rational functions of one variable. the associated Riemann surface is the Riemann sphere, hence a Riemann surface is isomorphic to the Riemann sphere if and only if its field of meromorphic functions is isomorphic to the field C(x). An irreducible plane curve N is called rational if its field of rational functions is isomorphic to C(x), if and only if its Riemann surface is isomorphic to the Riemann sphere.

So fields of rational functions are a fundamental invariant of Riemann surfaces, and the simplest example is C(x). Notice that for almost any function f as above, (except for f = x-a), the field C(x) is a subfield of the fraction field of C[x,y]/(f), corresponding to the fact that we can project a plane curve (other than a vertical line) surjectively onto the x axis. Thus it is natural to study any Riemann surface via such a projection, making the surface a finite cover of the Riemann sphere (the compactified x axis). Correspondingly, any rational function field of any plane curve is a finite algebraic extension of the basic field C(x). In this way the field C(x) is a very basic tool for studying all Riemann surfaces. Riemann himself for example proved that if a Riemann surface S has topological genus g, and if d is the smallest integer d ≥ (g/2)+1, then S is a finite cover of the Riemann sphere of degree d. Equivalently, the rational function field of S is an algebraic extension of C(x) of degree d.

E.g. if S is a torus of genus one, then S is a double cover of the Riemann sphere, (branched at 4 points). Equivalently a rational function field of genus one is a quadratic extension oif the field C(x). E.g. the elliptic curve y^2 = x(x^2-1), has rational function field generated by x and y, where y is quadratic over C(x), by virtue of this defining equation. But quadratic rational function fields can have any genus g, by considering curves with equations of form y^2 = x(x-1)(x-2)...(x-(2g+1)).

Remark: Thus some curves of genus g are 2-1 covers of the sphere, but the curve x^4+y^4 = 1 of genus 3, is a 3-1 cover but not a 2-1 cover of the Riemann sphere. I.e. the curves of genus g listed 2 or 3 lines above, are all double covers of the sphere, hence are not general curves of genus g, but special ones.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes fresh_42
  • #24
one more remark about the usefulness of rational functions as opposed to everywhere regular functions (polynomials). Although rational mappings are not well defined at the zeroes of their denominators, this can actually be an advantage! Consider the polynomial mapping taking t to (t^2,t^3), from the t- line to the plane cubic curve y^2 = x^3. This curve is not smooth but has a "cusp" at the origin, where the curve comes to a point. Still the map is bijective from the smooth t-line to the curve. The cusp prevents the map from having a regular inverse, but nonetheless it has a rational inverse defined by sending (x,y) to y/x. The fact that this map is not well defined at (0,0) is essential, and it still defines an inverse to the original map, everywhere one exists. In general such rational maps are used to desingularize curves with singularities, by mapping them to curves without singularities, in a way which is as close as possible to an isomorphism, but of course necessarily not quite an isomorphism.

here is another similar one but with a small difference: map t to (t^2-1, t(t^2-1)), to parametrize the curve y^2 = x^2(x+1), also by the t-line. This curve is also singular but has a node at the origin, i.e. it crosses itself transversely there and there are two points of the t-line which map to the point (0,0), namely both t=1 and t= -1. The "inverse map" again takes (x,y) to y/x, and is not defined at (0,0) precisely because it is impossible, by a regular map, to send (0,0) back to both its preimages. Nonetheless this crucial feature allows us to desingularize this curve by this inverse map, the closure of whose image is the non singular t-line. The inverse map is a bijection from the curve minus the origin, to the open complement of the two points {1, -1} in the t-line. In general a desingularization of a singular curve is defined as a regular "proper" map from a smooth curve onto the singular curve, and that is isomorphic except over the singular points. But how to find such a map? I.e. how do we know which non - singular curve to use, since it is only the singular curve we have our hands on? We do this by constructing a sequence of rational maps from our singular curve, until we at last find a non singular image curve. This is called "blowing up" singularities, and the rational maps can be constructed by using projections from the singularities on a singular curve embedded in high dimensional space.

Notice that projection of the projective (x,y,z) plane to the (x,y) axis, a projective line, is not defined at the point (0,0,1) in the plane, since (0,0) is not a point in the projective line, so rational maps give an algebraic realization of the geometric process of projection.

E.g. the map of the nodal plane curve y^2 = x^2(x+1) to a line, can be realized geometrically by sending a point (x,y) away from (0,0) to the line through the origin spanned by the origin and the point (x,y). This maps the complement of the origin in the affine plane, to the projective line, and one can see that as we approach the origin along either branch of the node, the limiting value of the map, i.e. of the secant lines dfetermined by (0,0) and (x,y), is the corresponding tangent line to the nodal curve at the origin. Since there are two such tangent lines, we get in the limit a map sending the origin to two different points of the t- line, depending on which direction we approach the origin along the singular curve. Since t = y/x, the affine coordinate t of course only parametrizes the affine subset x≠0 of the projective (x,y) line. Note also that y/x, i.e. the slope, is a natural coordinate for the line through (x,y) and (0,0).

Note also that the two examples of singular plane curves had parametrizations which failed to have a regular inverse in different ways. The parametrization of the cusp was bijective but at t=0 the velocity vector was zero, so it was not locally invertible there. the parametrization of the node had two preimages of the origin, hence was not globally invertible, but at both of these preimages the velocity vector of the parametrization map was non zero. To have a regular inverse, a map must be both globally and locally invertible, but the rational inverses we found existed in both cases, i.e. rational maps solve both types of problems of non invertibility, which is rather wonderful!
 
Last edited:
  • #25
to mr. tashi, re post #21: it is true such "substitutions" seem odd, but maybe one can make sense of it by abstracting the ordinarily intuitive process of composition, or substitution. The process of "substitution" of an element a of a ring R (with identity), in place of x, in a polynomial, is equivalent to defining the ring homomorphism Z[x]-->R, which sends x to a. I.e. the fact that one can substitute anything for x in a polynomial just means that there is a ring map Z[x ]-->"anything" that sends x to anything you like (as long as the ring "anything" is commutative with identity element).

Similarly, since Z[π] ≈ Z[x], the ring Z[π] has exactly the same algebraic properties. So saying one can "substitute" an element a of R for the symbol π, is just the fact that one can define a ring homomorphism from Z[π]-->R that sends π to a. I.e. "substituting a for π" just means sending π to a by a ring map. Does this have any (at least logical) appeal?
 
  • Like
Likes Stephen Tashi
  • #26
mathwonk said:
to mr. tashi, re post #21: it is true such "substitutions" seem odd, but maybe one can make sense of it by abstracting the ordinarily intuitive process of composition, or substitution.

So saying one can "substitute" an element a of R for the symbol π, is just the fact that one can define a ring homomorphism from Z[π]-->R that sends π to a. I.e. "substituting a for π" just means sending π to a by a ring map. Does this have any (at least logical) appeal?

Yes, it does. Can each homomorphism ##\mathbb{Z}[x] \rightarrow \mathbb{R}## be realized as such a map?

As I understand the ring of polynomials in one "indeterminate" and similar mathematical constructs, they are defined essentially as strings of symbols together with rules for deriving strings from given strings. If done properly, this would be phrased in the same style as is used to define computer languages and in the modeling of formal logic as strings of symbols. I've never seen a algebra text that adopts that style of presentation. In algebra texts it is taken for granted that the reader understands how "substitution" can be used to map a polynomial in one indeterminate to an element in another ring. The concept of "substitution" is so intuitive and universal in mathematics that it isn't formalized. Using the concept of "substitution", we can implement the idea of "composition" of polynomials.

What make me intellectually uneasy is not understanding what, if any, limitations are imposed on the concept of "ring" by assuming it must have a structure that is a string of symbols whose operations are described by manipulating the strings. There is a viewpoint in Group Theory where groups are described in such a manner. I haven't seen this view extended to representing rings.
 
  • #27
mathwonk said:
A few remarks: if f(x,y) is an irreducible polynomial with complex coefficients, then the locus f=0 defines a plane curve N in C^2, whose ring of polynomial functions equals the integral domain C[x,y]/(f). I.e. this is the ring of polynomial functions on the plane restricted to N, so that those which equal zero on N are set equal to zero. The field of fractions of this domain is called the field of rational functions on N. This field is isomorphic to the field of meromorphic functions on the Riemann surface of N, i.e. the compactified desingularization of N. It is a theorem that a compact non singular connected one dimensional complex manifold is determined up to isomorphism by its field of meromorphic functions.

The special case where f = y, gives the field C(x), rational functions of one variable. the associated Riemann surface is the Riemann sphere, hence a Riemann surface is isomorphic to the Riemann sphere if and only if its field of meromorphic functions is isomorphic to the field C(x). An irreducible plane curve N is called rational if its field of rational functions is isomorphic to C(x), if and only if its Riemann surface is isomorphic to the Riemann sphere.

So fields of rational functions are a fundamental invariant of Riemann surfaces, and the simplest example is C(x). Notice that for almost any function f as above, (except for f = x-a), the field C(x) is a subfield of the fraction field of C[x,y]/(f), corresponding to the fact that we can project a plane curve (other than a vertical line) surjectively onto the x axis. Thus it is natural to study any Riemann surface via such a projection, making the surface a finite cover of the Riemann sphere (the compactified x axis). Correspondingly, any rational function field of any plane curve is a finite algebraic extension of the basic field C(x). In this way the field C(x) is a very basic tool for studying all Riemann surfaces. Riemann himself for example proved that if a Riemann surface S has topological genus g, and if d is the smallest integer d ≥ (g/2)+1, then S is a finite cover of the Riemann sphere of degree d. Equivalently, the rational function field of S is an algebraic extension of C(x) of degree d.

E.g. if S is a torus of genus one, then S is a double cover of the Riemann sphere, (branched at 4 points). Equivalently a rational function field of genus one is a quadratic extension oif the field C(x). E.g. the elliptic curve y^2 = x(x^2-1), has rational function field generated by x and y, where y is quadratic over C(x), by virtue of this defining equation. But quadratic rational function fields can have any genus g, by considering curves with equations of form y^2 = x(x-1)(x-2)...(x-(2g+1)).

Remark: Thus some curves of genus g are 2-1 covers of the sphere, but the curve x^4+y^4 = 1 of genus 3, is a 3-1 cover but not a 2-1 cover of the Riemann sphere. I.e. the curves of genus g listed 2 or 3 lines above, are all double covers of the sphere, hence are not general curves of genus g, but special ones.
Isn't a cover a local homeomorphism? If so, how can a 1-d curve be a cover for a sphere? I guess I am missing something obvious. Is it just that the topological 2-sphere is a 1d Complex manifold?
 
  • #29
Infrared said:
A (nonsingular) complex curve is a 2D as a real manifold. And here he means a branched cover (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Branched_covering), which is not everywhere a local homeomorphism.
Yes, thanks, wanted to verify it was a complex curve so that dimensions matched up.
 
  • #30
my bad, mixing my metaphors. If I am going to speak of the projective line as the [riemann] sphere, then i should speak of a [complex curve] as a riemann surface. thanks for this clarification.
 
  • Like
Likes WWGD
  • #31
mathwonk said:
my bad, mixing my metaphors. If I am going to speak of the projective line as the [riemann] sphere, then i should speak of a [complex curve] as a riemann surface. thanks for this clarification.
Kind of strange, to me at least, to see how Complex lines become spheres through projectivization.
 
  • #32
just as the real line is one copy of the real numbers, the complex line is one copy of the complex numbers, thus homeomorphic to the real plane. projectivizing the (affine) line means adding one point at infinity, and thus the complex projective line is the one point compactification of the real plane, i.e. the usual 2-sphere.
 
  • Like
Likes WWGD

1. What is a rational function?

A rational function is a mathematical expression that represents the ratio of two polynomial functions. It can be written in the form f(x) = p(x)/q(x), where p(x) and q(x) are polynomials and q(x) is not equal to 0.

2. How is a rational function useful in real life?

Rational functions are useful in many real-life applications, such as in economics, physics, and engineering. They can be used to model relationships between different quantities, such as cost and production, velocity and time, or pressure and volume.

3. What is the domain of a rational function?

The domain of a rational function is all the values of x for which the function is defined. In other words, it is the set of all real numbers except for the values that would make the denominator equal to 0. These values are called the vertical asymptotes of the function.

4. How do you simplify a rational function?

To simplify a rational function, you can first factor the numerator and denominator and then cancel out any common factors. This will help to reduce the complexity of the function and make it easier to analyze and solve.

5. What is the difference between a rational function and an irrational function?

The main difference between a rational function and an irrational function is that a rational function can be expressed as a ratio of two polynomials, while an irrational function cannot. Irrational functions involve irrational numbers, such as pi or the square root of 2, and cannot be written as a ratio of two integers.

Similar threads

  • Linear and Abstract Algebra
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Linear and Abstract Algebra
Replies
1
Views
1K
Replies
139
Views
4K
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
17
Views
2K
  • Linear and Abstract Algebra
Replies
2
Views
943
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
2
Replies
43
Views
4K
  • STEM Educators and Teaching
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
787
Replies
4
Views
741
Back
Top