Time and relationships (or, consciousness per Martin Heidegger)

AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on the complexities of consciousness and its relationship to time, as explored through Heidegger's "Being and Time." It contrasts Cartesian and Kantian perspectives, emphasizing that consciousness cannot be solely viewed as an objective property or as an abstract subjectivity. Heidegger proposes that consciousness is fundamentally about active engagement in relationships, challenging the traditional separation of mind and world. The conversation also critiques the limitations of scientific approaches to understanding existence and calls for a new ontology that recognizes interdependence. Ultimately, the dialogue seeks to bridge subjective experience with objective reality, highlighting the need for a deeper understanding of our participatory existence.
  • #151


ConradDJ said:
I don’t believe in a magisterial Reason that can see the whole universe from outside and grasp its Logic in a formula. What feels deeply right to me is that there’s a truth in seeing the world from one’s own unique viewpoint, enmeshed in one’s relationships. This kind of truth has no access to Certainty or to any “global” reference-frame... everything is “local” and in play, in the here and now. In my authentic view, I don’t even get to “see” both sides of a single relationship I’m in.

I agree that it is in fact fair to form a third person objective or globalised description of what you are actually trying to do - which is get completely away from that POV to have a view based on "just interactions". Which sounds exactly like Peirce's secondness BTW.

There is no choice but to look back and try to describe the indefinite, indeterminate in terms that are themselves then well defined in a way that what they refer to is not.

It is exactly the same with modelling vagueness or apeiron. So basing a philosophy on proto-interactions would be no different.

The only question is then whether such an approach can be made to work. But the quest itself has a legitimate goal and is not self-contradictory simply because it wants to talk about the ontically indefinite or proto-whatever in definite language.

And no, this is not a vote for pan-psychism which IMHO does not have a goal to explain anything in a causal fashion - answering the how or why questions - but simply posits that something is the case as brute fact. And reality's only acceptable brute fact is the fact that we subjectively exist [JDStupi's point]. All else must follow as explanation or I can't see how it is either philosophy or science, just an argument from faith.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #152


apeiron,

That is the problem with panpsychism of any stripe. Consciousness is explained away (as just something that is always there) rather than explained (as something that comes into being for a reason which is the object of the theory).

Is this really a good criticism? I ask because it seems that in any scientific or even philosophical theory, the search always stops somewhere with that which "just is, period". Fundamental forces, for example.

I can understand the idea that we should be very reluctant to add new fundamental substances or forces. But still, it seems someone can still argue in good faith that some things "just are" (even if they qualify that with "in this theory, which may one day turn out to be wrong").
 
  • #153


Ferris_bg said:
Lets say one invents a device with which one has the power to go "inside" in others and participate in their relationships exactly in the way they are. In other words my brain gets linked to yours, and I can feel your qualia, depending not on my "brain configuration", but on yours. So my experiences, during the time I participated in the world like you do, get stored somewhere and I can later access them somehow.

I don't believe in the possibility of such a device... but regardless -- if you had access to my brain-states, how would you know the "qualia" you experience -- given your very different life-history -- was anything like how I experience them? The beer I'm drinking might taste amazing to you, because you've never experienced my beer-qualia before, but to me it's just the same old taste that I take for granted, right?

The basic problem here is imagining experience as if it were something "real" -- confusing categories of objective reality with categories of existence, that can only be "one's own".

I'm going to indulge myself in a little mini-essay on this difference in the next post.
 
  • #154


Here’s a way of imagining our situation. Let’s say, there’s Reality and there’s Existence. These are two ways of talking about the same world we all live in together.

Reality is the world we imagine “objectively” – the world of things that are in fact what they are, without regard to the context they happen to be in at the moment, or the perspective from which they might be seen.

Existence is the world we experience “from inside”... only from our own point of view, in this particular moment now, in the context prepared by our own entire life-histories.

We’ve been very successful at learning to describe and understand Reality, especially in the sciences. We’ve evolved an elaborate array of sophisticated conceptual tools for sifting and interpreting evidence, to verify facts and uncover basic principles.

There are however two big holes in the scientific view of Reality. When it comes to the foundations of the physical world, or the basis of human consciousness, it seems pretty clear that we don’t have the conceptual tools we need. Let’s suppose, that’s because these two questions are not really about Reality. We’re no longer dealing with “things as they are in themselves” but with being in relationships.

When we try to apply our conceptual tools to these questions, we get nonsense. Quantum mechanics is very beautifully structured nonsense – we know the theory is right, because it explains far more about the world far more precisely than any other theory ever has. But no one understands at all what it means. The only thing that’s clear about it is that it doesn’t give us definite facts about physical systems “in themselves”.

But when it comes to “consciousness”, the nonsense really gives us nothing at all. When we apply the kinds of logic we’ve developed for Reality, we get notions like “qualia”. Because I’m a philosopher, I do sometimes try to “experience qualia”, with some success. To do that I have to “step beck” into my own mind and see the world around me merely as my own internal “perception”, and then try to isolate some tiny aspect of it, like a patch of color or a moment of sound. I can do that, but I guarantee you that my wife has never “experienced qualia” in her life. And the notion that our experience is essentially made of these bits and can be understood in terms of them is a typical misapplication of our reality-tools.

Likewise the idea that other animals “have qualia” or “have subjective awareness”. It’s not that this is wrong, since of course the sensory functions of other animals aren’t very different from ours. But it applies an objective mode of thinking in contexts where it can have no possible meaning.

And this is the fundamental issue in Existence – how do things come to have meaning? This is where our categories for Reality fail us, fail to provide even a starting-point. We hardly know what “meaning” means or where it comes from, even with regard to us humans, who can talk about. But it’s just as fundamental in physics, where things “have” definite states and properties only insofar as they make a difference to other things.

The goal of Being and Time was to make such a starting-point, for understanding Existence – the world “from inside” – as distinct from Reality.

Existence is always in a specific context of relationships, in this moment. The context is always “anticipatory” – a context of possibilities, so that what actually happens now can make a difference, can “mean” something... namely, to what can happen further on.

The context also has a built-in history, made of everything that’s gone on in all these different relationships I’m in, over many different time-scales, all of which go to make this present situation possible.

So Existence is an evolving “present moment”, from one’s own point of view, in many different relationship-contexts at once... where what happens in each relationship makes a difference to what can happen in others, and so “has meaning”. When the relationships are talking-relationships, e.g. between human beings, they generate an “internal” relationship of talking to yourself. And in a highly-evolved, literate culture, this self-relationship can evolve into something like a “consciousness” that thinks of itself as such.

Now as to basic categories. Reality gives us a vast body of fact, laid out in space and time. The purpose of our categories is to let us describe, accurately and insightfully, what it is.

Existence is always only “here and now”. But it has its own kind of depth and complexity. There are many, many layers of history built into it – personal history, cultural history, the history of life, and many layers of physical history as well. All of these are built into the context that makes possible whatever’s possible for us in this present situation.

So the kinds of categories we need for this, to untangle this kind of profound complexity, are the kinds that can distinguish all these different layers of “meaning” that constitute this present moment. Some have to do with the physical interactions with our environment we experience as sensation, some have to do with the many stages of biological evolution that support the functioning of our bodies and minds, some have to do with the many stages of evolution of language and thought.

This amounts to a kind of archaeology of the moment – uncovering all the distinct layers of relationships in which different dimensions of “meaning” arise, through which people and things make a difference to each other. Instead of describing “what is” in Reality, by talking about all the different kinds of things there are spread out in space and time, we’re trying to describe all the different kinds of meaning in all these distinct relationship-contexts, that support our Existence in this ongoing “now”.

This thread was titled “Time and Relationships”, because this was the key point I learned from Heidegger. Each of the many relationship-contexts that underlie Existence has its own “temporality” – not only its own time-scale, but its own way of “doing” time, its own way of making happening “meaningful”. The time of physics is different from the time of biology, which is different from the time in which you and I exist as “conscious” beings. And each of these “times” is made up of many distinct relationship-contexts, each distinguished by a different “timing”.

In sum – we have in Science an wonderful picture of Reality. When it comes to Existence, we’re still at about the stage of the pre-Socratic philosophers, who were struggling to find language for imagining the world as a whole, as “seen from outside”. In Heidegger we see just the first steps of an equally difficult struggle.
 
  • #155


But when it comes to “consciousness”, the nonsense really gives us nothing at all. When we apply the kinds of logic we’ve developed for Reality, we get notions like “qualia”. Because I’m a philosopher, I do sometimes try to “experience qualia”, with some success. To do that I have to “step beck” into my own mind and see the world around me merely as my own internal “perception”, and then try to isolate some tiny aspect of it, like a patch of color or a moment of sound. I can do that, but I guarantee you that my wife has never “experienced qualia” in her life. And the notion that our experience is essentially made of these bits and can be understood in terms of them is a typical misapplication of our reality-tools.

As a comment, I would say that I absolutley agree with this statement. It seems to me a perfect example of what I call the "Fallacy of Misplaced Linearity" which happens so frequently in certain philosophical discussions. Essentially, possibly due to the prominent role played by Analytic Philosophy in modern discussions, philosophers tacitly assume a belief in the primacy of formal logic in their reasoning. This is not inherently a bad thing, but frequently it seems to be that logical considerations and ways of conceptualizing the world are mistaken for ontological ways of thinking and conceptualizing the world. Formal logic can be viewed simply as yet another conceptual scaffolding, a scaffolding which enjoys no aprioricity with regards to justification. Formal logic is an abstract algebraic system with operators and primitive undefined terms, and it is we who apply this abstract algebraic system with its primitives, "The Proposition" serving the same role as "The Number" in other algebras. As such, it is subject to the same criticisms and epistemological uncertainties associated with the traditional scientific endeavor, for both involve the application of a formalized conceptual framework to reality.

Where the linearity comes into play, is in trying to formulate our conceptions in terms of this scaffolding. We take the whole of experience and break it up into "Qualia" some type of atomistic building block that linearly adds up to the sum of experience, we then isolate qualia and sicuss them as if experience were composed of qualia, but as you stated anybody who has really looked into experience, knows that qualia are absolutley not what experience is made of. In a Duhem analogy, there are always a conjunction of background "assumptions" and processes going on at any given time, and we cannot simply isolate one "qualia" out among others as being primitive. The most forceful illustration of this is in philosophers traditional lack of respect and appreciation for aesthetics. When you are sitting outside and the whole of a scenery takes on a perceptual sense, and it is not "this qualia" or "that qualia" but the whole field of consciousness that takes on an indescribable sense of calmness or beauty, this cannot be broken up into a "qualia".

This misplaced qualia abstraction then leads to misplaced science, because certain scientists influenced by a dominant philosophy will try to find one-to-one correspondances between "neural states" and "primitive qualia" and from there claim that the sum of the neural states associated with primitive qualia will successfuly explain consciousness. I am not saying the mind is separate from body, simply that the specific methodology associated with atomistic qualia will fail.

And this is the fundamental issue in Existence – how do things come to have meaning? This is where our categories for Reality fail us, fail to provide even a starting-point. We hardly know what “meaning” means or where it comes from, even with regard to us humans, who can talk about. But it’s just as fundamental in physics, where things “have” definite states and properties only insofar as they make a difference to other things

You see, I am certainly interested in this Heideggerian viewpoint, but what I keep seeing as problematic is the attempt to develop a "view from existence" because I see it is a continual banging our head against the wall, against the limits of what can be said. Namely, I think that Heidegger attemped to get down not to "beings" but to "The meaning of Being". His idea was, as you are saying, that our Western Metaphysical tradition has went away from what it means to "Be" and simply explicated upon "beings" while leaving behind the fundamental ontological question of "Being". As such he believed the only way to view the meaning of "Being" it self was to investigate it from the perspecctive of Being, of existence as you call it, and so analyze our human condition and authentic existence. I see this as a great idea. However, where it seems to run into problems is that, we are limited to and can only know our own way of existence and of Being and the meaning that Being takes on for us is a personal "Existential" question, the minute we attempt to create a framework for how other beings "Be" we are necessarily abstracting and extrapolating from our own mode-of-Being and nothing necessitates that this is the case for others. We cannot understand their mode of Being, almost by definition. So this is where we get into, what Apeiron (or rather Pierce) calls thridness, namely we have to speak of habits and regularities between the world of beings. We may even come to Secondness or the world of individual fact and relation between beings, but the question of Being is relegated to the world of Firstness or quality and cannot be explicated upon or built upon without turning into Secondness or Thirdness.

This is why I feel as though we can learn from Wittgenstein in that "What can not be said can only be shown" or "Whereof we cannot speak thereof we must remain silent" in that we are coming up against the limits of abstraction, and we can only attemp to point and describe in terms of secondness or thirdness, we can only attempt to wake people up to the "Radical root of their existence" as Ortegga y Gassat called it, but we cannot built a system of Being, for that would be against the spirit of Being itself. Then we would just have yet another "paragraph in a system".

I completely agree that we need to show people that there is a world of Being that lies beneath the world of beings, but I think that this is best achieved through "pointing" and the world of art. Art can form a bridge between beings and Being. This is also why I spoke of certain aspects of Zen earlier, namely that its entire project is of bringing us into closer realation with Being, and realizing that Being is not to be spoken of, but to Be.

This is another reason why, I think the meaning of Being is difficult to approach in our culture, a culture entirely built around beings. A culture whose religions are even sometimes formed around beings and shallow moral rules and outdated abstract belief systems, but if there is anything to religion it is not its abstractions or its moral rules (well not from an Existential point of view, maybe from a sociological point of view) but it is towards its means of orienting people towards Being, a pursuit largely neglected.

Essentially, I think we may remain at the level of the "Pre-Socratics" and the only way to improve would be to show people the "limits of language" and then we can use language to discuss this mode of Being simply by virtue of having a shared experience of it.

There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio,
Than are dreamt of in your philosophy.

And it shall always remain this way, neccessarily, for Being is not to be completely elucidated through speech.


I apologize for my long and winding post
 
  • #156


Conrad, again, you're taken with Heidegger's supposed sweeping away of traditional philosophy. You think "qualia" is some scientistic term to distract from authentic experience.

Qualia ARE authentic experience. Qualia are subjectivity. Qualia are mind.

Everything you do is the flux and flex of qualia. You are qualia. Your wife IS qualia.

These are all terms for exactly the same thing.

Reality, as you have defined it, is a construct of complex collections of qualia - human minds, in this case. Reality is, thus, dependent on the deeper reality of what you have called Existence. So Existence is what needs to be explained in any decent ontology.

And, again, this is what Whitehead and other sophisticated panpsychists have attempted to do.

You really need to read Panpsychism in the West and Griffin's Unsnarling the World-Knot. You might find that the vocabulary you claim doesn't exist has in fact been around for a long time.
 
  • #157


ConradDJ,

My example was influenced by that of Rama, in which he addresses the problem, which the third person account create.
'Phantoms in the Brain' said:
Like the superscientist in the previous example, you can study the neurophysiology of this fish and figure out how the electrical organs on the sides of its body transduce electrical current, how this information is conveyed to the brain, what part of the brain analyzes this information and how the fish uses this information to dodge predators, find prey and so on. If the fish could talk, however, it would say, "Fine, but you'll never know what it feels like to sense electricity."
These examples clearly state the problem of why qualia are thought to be essentially private. They also illustrate why the problem of qualia is not necessarily a scientific problem. Recall that your scientific description is complete. It's just that the your account is incomplete epistemologically because the actual experience of electric fields or redness is something you never will know. For you, it will forever remain a "third-person" account.
For centuries philosophers have assumed that this gap between brain and mind poses a deep epistemological problem - a barrier that simply cannot be crossed. But is this really true? I agree that the barrier hasn't yet been crossed, but does it follow that it can never be crossed? I'd like to argue that there is in fact no such barrier, no great vertical divide in nature between mind and matter, substance and spirit. Indeed, I believe that this barrier is only apparent and that it arises as a result of language. This sort of obstacle emerges when there is any translation from one language to another. (...)
But what if I were to skip spoken language as a medium of communication and instead hook a cable of neural pathways (taken from tissue culture or from another person) from
the color-processing areas in my brain directly into the color-processing regions of your brain (remember that your brain has the machinery to see color even though your eyes cannot discriminate wavelengths because they have no color receptors)? The cable allows the color information to go straight from my brain to neurons in your brain without intermediate translation. This is a farfetched scenario, but there is nothing logically impossible about it.
Earlier when I said "red," it didn't make any sense to you because the mere use of the word "red" already involves a translation. But if you skip the translation and use a cable, so that the nerve impulses themselves go directly to the color area, then perhaps you'll say, "Oh, my God, I see exactly what you mean. I'm having this wonderful new experience."
This scenario demolishes the philosophers' argument that there is an insurmountable logical barrier to understanding qualia. In principle, you can experience another creature's qualia, even the electric fish's. If you could find out what the electroceptive part of the fish brain is doing and if you could somehow graft it onto the relevant parts of your brain with all the proper associated connections, then you would start experiencing the fish's electrical qualia. Now, we could get into a philosophical debate over whether you need to be a fish to experience it or whether as a human being you could experience it, but the debate is not relevant to my argument. The logical point I am making here pertains only to the electrical qualia - not to the whole experience of being a fish.
The key idea here is that the qualia problem is not unique to the mind−body problem. It is no different in kind from problems that arise from any translation, and thus there is no need to invoke a great division in nature between the world of qualia and the material world. There is only one world with lots of translation barriers. If you can overcome them, the problems vanish.


Now let's go back to my "qualia map" example - we have three possible results from such an experiment (consider the experiment successful):
1) There is no chance for the establishing of such qualia map. My comparison differs from yours, that is to say I find your feeling of the beer better than mine and you don't, you find them the same. So, applied on a massive scale, where a lot of people participate (a lot of reports differ), such map is impossible to make and materialism is not the whole truth, so you can stop worrying about solving consciousness.
2) Such map can be established, but the gap can't be reduced - we are left with a property dualistic view, in which matter is everything, but mind as its supervenient property is unsolvable.
3) There is no gap, mind can be reduced to matter.
 
Last edited:
  • #158


apeiron, responding to #145:

Dual aspect panpsychism and panexperiential physicalism may be equated but I think, to be entirely clear here, it's important to stress that I am not saying: "There is substance/matter and it has a mental aspect." Rather, I am saying: "There is mind/matter (menter) and it is equally mind and matter as it oscillates from subjectivity to objectivity in each time quantum."

You have already said you accept Griffin's panexperiential panpsychism - and he is a strong panpsychist - so, yes, if you accept Griffin's views then you are a panpsychist. Why do you resist the Borg?

As for Pattee's views, I'll assume that your appeal to authority substitutes for a lack of a good response. This forum is about debate, not appeals to authority.

As I explained previously, I'm not asking you to reconstruct historically the actual events that took place with the emergence of life - I'm asking you to describe your criteria for deciding exactly when "life" exists and thus how it emerged phylogenetically on our planet and ontogenetically with each new life form springing forth from its parents, seeds, spores or what have you.

You state: "So there is still no story on how that first drop of experience arises out of a prior state of non-experiencing. Where does this power to prehend come from? It is sounding very chicken and egg, is it not? You need a locus to prehend, and prehension to have a locus."

No, it is not chicken and egg. I'm not sure why you're battling me on this one because it seems our views are pretty much identical on the apeiron and the limitation of pure potentiality (apeiron) by actuality (the physical universe). We'll never know exactly how this process takes place because pure potentiality is necessarily inferred not detected. But we can theorize. And Anaximander, Plotinus, Whitehead and many others have written extensively on how pure potentiality becomes actuality.

Whitehead appeals to a complex process of "ingression" of "eternal objects" (akin to Plato's forms) and "prehension" of "actual entities." Ingression and prehension for each actual entity leads it to transition from unformed subjectivity to objectivity (or "superjectivity"). The set of eternal objects may be equated to apeiron/ether/Brahman. The set of actual entities may be equated with the physical universe.

Thus, each locus is, for me, akin to a three-dimensional pixel that manifests as space or matter as the sum of ingressions and prehensions suggests. Whitehead doesn't state this, but I imagine the substrate as an infinite 3-D grid through which the physical universe moves. Each actual entity/physical object is translated through this grid in each moment as it moves. And each translation is a result of the ticking of the time quanta that constitutes the creative advance, in each corner of the universe.

You state: "That is the problem with panpsychism of any stripe. Consciousness is explained away (as just something that is always there) rather than explained (as something that comes into being for a reason which is the object of the theory)."

I agree that the panpsychist assertion that all things have a mental aspect doesn't get us very far in explanations. But it's a very key starting point. The necessary follow up is the framework I've outlined here and in more detail in my forthcoming JCS paper. The key follow up question is: what determines the boundary of each unitary subject? This is the "boundary problem" or the "combination problem." And this is what my three-part theory of complexity addresses:

The Perception Index (PI) x the Connectivity Index (CI) = Omega (the capacity for phenomenal content).

But we must establish the extent of field coherence in each candidate subject in order to apply this formula. And establishing the extent of the applicable field coherence is a matter of empirical inquiry, as I will flesh out in Part 2 of my paper.

Here's an example from Part 1 of my paper:

The fruit fly’s brain is mostly devoted to visual processing and contains about 100,000 neurons.[1] If we assume about 100 dendrites for each neuron, we have about 10,000,000 synapses, which are the internal connections quantified by CI in this case. (We would also, to be comprehensive, have to determine what neural subunits exist in the fly brain and quantify interconnections between neural subunits in addition to the simple internal connectivity of all synaptic connections.) For the purposes of this example, we can translate this calculation to a normalized CI value of 4 (again, the normalization rules will be described in Part 2 of this paper). Recalling the PI value of 3 for fruit fly vision, we obtain an Omega of 12 for the fruit fly’s visual system. In actuality, of course, there is no separation of senses in the complex subject that is a fruit fly. But, again, this is just a dramatically simplified example to illustrate the formalisms.

[1] Rein, K., et al., (2002). Chiang, et al., (2010).

And with respect to field coherence, I state:

“Field coherence” refers to the coherence in time of the various constituents of the complex subject. Reality is conceived as a series of snapshots – chronons – that represent an entire slice of the universe in each moment. Chronons are incredibly brief in duration – possibly as short (or shorter) as the Planck moment, which is about 5 x 10-44 seconds. Each constituent of the universe resonates at some chronon multiple. When different constituents near each other resonate at the same chronon multiple, they bind together into a single subject in addition to the constituent subjects. That is, as each constituent oscillates back and forth at the same frequency, they are bound together in such a way that a new larger-scale subject is formed. This process is, when conditions are supportive, hierarchical (holarchical[1]) and iterative. Simple subjects bind together to form a complex subject, then bind together again to form a higher level complex subject, and so on, up to the rarefied heights of human subjects and perhaps higher in the ontological chain. Each constituent of the complex subject at issue achieves synchrony through a jostling process that must occur within the time limits of the iterative process that constitutes the laying down of reality (the creative advance), like a sieve producing layers of dust, dirt, small pebbles, larger pebbles, etc. As more and more constituents become linked, and oscillate at the same frequency, the subject at issue becomes more complex. The limit on this process is the finite speed of information between the complex subject’s constituents. As constituents become linked through connections that provide faster and faster information flows, the possible size of complex subjects increases. Quantum entanglement is the fastest physical connection we know of currently and it appears to operate at least 10,000 times faster than the speed of light. This is still, however, a finite speed. Quantum entanglement may be a necessary condition for complex subjects.

[1] Wilber (1995, 2000) is adamant that the true nature of reality is hierarchical/holarchical all the way up and all the way down. I agree that nature is hierarchical/holarchical, but I differ with Wilber in that I do posit a lowest level holon, what I call “simple subjects.” My rationale is simple: for there to be anything at all there has to be some initial ontological emergence from pure potentiality, particularly if we agree with Whitehead’s views on time as the creative advance. Accordingly, this initial ontological emergence, which happens as each chronon ticks, produces my simple subjects.

Now, with respect to your cerebellum/cortex example, can you state your question clearly and I'll take a crack at giving you a good answer?
 
  • #159


Ferris, my previous post also addresses your points.
 
  • #160


JDStupi said:
You see, I am certainly interested in this Heideggerian viewpoint, but what I keep seeing as problematic is the attempt to develop a "view from existence" because I see it is a continual banging our head against the wall, against the limits of what can be said...

...we can only attempt to wake people up to the "Radical root of their existence" as Ortega y Gasset called it, but we cannot built a system of Being, for that would be against the spirit of Being itself...

Essentially, I think we may remain at the level of the "Pre-Socratics" and the only way to improve would be to show people the "limits of language" and then we can use language to discuss this mode of Being simply by virtue of having a shared experience of it.
Thanks very much for your comments, JD... I can see you appreciate where the problem lies. If there can be an adequate way of understanding existence, it will have to operate with a conceptual language quite different from what we’re used to. And you’re right – it will need to bring us closer to our shared experience instead of distancing us from it.

The thing is – this is the reason I fell in love with the history of Western thought, when I was much younger – that over and over again these remarkable people were inventing new kinds of language, starting with the earliest Greek poets and philosophers. When the pre-Socratics began, there was simply no way of talking about “reality”... the concept had to be built up through a series of metaphors, piece by piece, until it finally emerged in Plato and Aristotle. Even in Plato “really” is still essentially an adverb, a way of emphasizing that one thing is more true than another. The concept of one exclusive truth about the world, that somehow encompasses all the differences and shades of truth we know in our lives... that notion of “reality” as a noun required not just a new word, but a whole new way of talking with each other. Eric Havelock is worth reading on this – e.g. The Muse Learns to Write. He points out for example that the construction “X is Y”, which came to dominate Western thought through philosophy, is almost absent from the language of pre-literate culture and from the earliest writing, e.g. Homer and Hesiod. It took many generations to establish the possibility of “theorizing” about the world.

At every stage, in the development of Christian dogma and then Medieval theology, in the emergence of modern philosophy and science, people were learning how to imagine the world in ways that just hadn’t been possible before. But you’re right – when it comes to “existence”, we face a new kind of challenge. And so it’s not so surprising that philosophy more or less gave up the ghost in the 20th century. The conceptual creativity of our tradition from 11th to the 19th centuries was unparalleled... but it’s hard to imagine anything like that coming out of our Philosophy Departments today.
JDStupi said:
Namely, I think that Heidegger attempted to get down not to "beings" but to "The meaning of Being"... As such he believed the only way to view the meaning of "Being" itself was to investigate it from the perspective of Being, of existence as you call it, and so analyze our human condition and authentic existence. I see this as a great idea. However, where it seems to run into problems is that, we are limited to and can only know our own way of existence and of Being and the meaning that Being takes on for us is a personal "Existential" question, the minute we attempt to create a framework for how other beings "Be" we are necessarily abstracting and extrapolating from our own mode-of-Being and nothing necessitates that this is the case for others.
Yes, this is very good. If there’s an “authentic” way of thinking about existence, it can’t be a matter of generalizing from what I experience to what people in general experience... let alone to what animals or plants or atoms “experience”.

As soon as we start down that path, we lose what’s essential about existence, that it’s only “one’s own”. Each of us has only our own life, in this web of connections with others. It’s remarkable how much we can share with each other, but the “own existence” that each of us has is not something anyone can share.

So I strongly disagree, for example, with the perspective of Ramachandran quoted by Ferris_bg in #157 above. The point is not that there are objective “experiences” going on in my brain that could be transmitted to someone else’s brain through “a cable of neural pathways.” Apart from the fact that I think this completely misconstrues how the brain works, what gives me my own unique, “private” perspective on the world is not the fact that my “brain-state” at a given instant is walled off and hidden in my head. It’s that I’m the only one who will ever have lived my life, from beginning to end.

But then – If we can’t generalize about “what it means to Be”... does that mean there’s nothing to understand about it? Or is it that we need to find language for an appropriate kind of understanding?

My thought is that understanding has two directions. The one that we’re very accomplished at has to do with gaining knowledge – investigating the facts, and finding explanations that lead to further investigation. The premise is that there’s a lot out there we don’t know... including, of course, a lot we don’t yet know about us humans, how our brains and our cultures work, etc.

The other direction of understanding has to do with what we all already know, but take for granted. What’s hardest for us to understand are the things closest to us, that we’re all intimately familiar with, that we’ve all experienced ever since we were born. Time, for example. There are no mysteries about time, nothing “unknown” about it. We all know how this business of “past, present and future” works. But it’s very hard to describe it, or even to think about the time we actually live in. Our language about “flow” and “passing” and “lengths” of time all describe something we don’t experience.

Now I don’t see why it’s impossible to develop adequate language for this. But the point is not to develop a “correct theory” about time – i.e. to generalize about our “internal sense of time”, for example. Gaining knowledge about that is a valid task for psychology, part of the traditional task of understanding Reality.

The point of understanding our Existence is to stop taking it for granted... to appreciate what each one of us has been given as our own. As you say, “to wake people up.” But I don’t see this as a one-shot deal, like a spiritual awakening you achieve once and for all. It’s not at all possible or desirable simply to stop taking everything for granted at once. This was Kierkegaard’s objection to Descartes, that he presumed to “doubt everything” intellectually, while still going on with his daily life, taking so much for granted. That there’s a beautiful planet for us to live on, that the laws of physics are so reliable, that life evolved, that we can talk with each other and have such a rich culture, on and on.

The realm of Existence, of what we all know but take for granted, is maybe just as vast as the realm of objective Reality. These are not two different worlds, but two sides of the same world we all live in. So the intellectual project of “not taking for granted” will maybe turn out to be just as extensive as the project of gaining scientific knowledge. And the two are not unrelated.

Look, in physics today, virtually everything is known. We have good theoretical explanations for virtually all observable phenomena. But, because the theories themselves don’t make any sense to us, we go on and on looking for further knowledge – about “branes” and “hidden dimensions” of reality, etc. – in the hope that it will somehow clarify things.

But the problem isn’t that something is still unknown, the problem is in what we take for granted about the physical world. That it happens “in real time”, for example, or that everything about it is “measurable”. We know all about how to measure things... but we don’t know how to think about that, we don’t have the conceptual tools that would let us not take it for granted.

So the issue of thinking “existentially” is not just about us humans. It’s about finding a different point of view and learning to think in a different direction, for a different purpose. There’s more to life, and there’s more to understand about life, than this business of gaining factual knowledge and arguing about theories.
 
Last edited:
  • #161


At every stage, in the development of Christian dogma and then Medieval theology, in the emergence of modern philosophy and science, people were learning how to imagine the world in ways that just hadn’t been possible before. But you’re right – when it comes to “existence”, we face a new kind of challenge. And so it’s not so surprising that philosophy more or less gave up the ghost in the 20th century. The conceptual creativity of our tradition from 11th to the 19th centuries was unparalleled... but it’s hard to imagine anything like that coming out of our Philosophy Departments today

Ahhhh so your saying that you're much more optimistic about the creation of a new conceptual language because, historically, this has had to be the case for even the abstractive language we now take for granted.

So I strongly disagree, for example, with the perspective of Ramachandran quoted by Ferris_bg in #157 above. The point is not that there are objective “experiences” going on in my brain that could be transmitted to someone else’s brain through “a cable of neural pathways.” Apart from the fact that I think this completely misconstrues how the brain works, what gives me my own unique, “private” perspective on the world is not the fact that my “brain-state” at a given instant is walled off and hidden in my head. It’s that I’m the only one who will ever have lived my life, from beginning to end

I too would say I disagree with this mainly because I am skeptical of any overly "linear" ideas about how cognition and perceptual experience work. The way in which the very field of your consciousness is carved out is highly underappreciated, and I think that the way in which perceptual experience manifests itself in quality is intimatley related to your personal history, your body, your culture and the interaction between all of them. And again when I say "your x, your y" my language doesn't convey what I mean, I don't think there is a "you" to posess some body and some culture, you are these things.
Moreover, Rama explicitley stated that his idea was merely to show the logical possibility of connecting cables to the brain and "sharing" subjective experience, but this is not much, all it amounts to saying is it isn't a necessary truth under any definition. But then again, who ever thought that empirical knowledge was a matter of logical necessity?

The point of understanding our Existence is to stop taking it for granted... to appreciate what each one of us has been given as our own. As you say, “to wake people up.” But I don’t see this as a one-shot deal, like a spiritual awakening you achieve once and for all. It’s not at all possible or desirable simply to stop taking everything for granted at once. This was Kierkegaard’s objection to Descartes, that he presumed to “doubt everything” intellectually, while still going on with his daily life, taking so much for granted. That there’s a beautiful planet for us to live on, that the laws of physics are so reliable, that life evolved, that we can talk with each other and have such a rich culture, on and on.

Again I am finding I need to be more careful with the implications of my language, and I apologize for my blunders in this area. I do not mean to imply that it "waking people up" is sufficient, only necessary. "Waking people up" is only the first step, but continurally learning to see your existence from a new perspective is a life-long endeavor, an act of continual becoming. Yes, C.S. Pierce too spoke of how you can only start philosophy from where you are and that Descartes "doubt everything" dictum is not an actuality.

But then – If we can’t generalize about “what it means to Be”... does that mean there’s nothing to understand about it? Or is it that we need to find language for an appropriate kind of understanding?

I certainly do not want to seem like I am saying "there is nothing to understand" if anything I was doubting that it could be understood soley on the basis of discursive thought.

Now regarding "finding a language" would you agree with my notion ("my" as if it is all mine) that the "language" of art seems to be stronger at communicating this type of "thought" at this time? Mainly that language is simply communication and certain types of poetry or music may be able to better convey the depth of "Being"?

I hate to sound like some type of Eastern pundit, which I am surely not, but simply in the interest of discussing these notions I do still say that turning East would be a fruitful idea. I have yet to dig into the East's philosophy, but as you have stated it is the West who largely developed this abstractive mode of communication. Quite possibly, many of the germinal seeds for the creation of this new authentic mode of speech is already to be had in Eastern thought. Something like the Dao-de-jing with its "The way that can be named is not the true way" may help us seek thought in that direction.

Of course, the problem with that is that it will be very difficult to open our culture up to for a number of reasons. First, if you wish to discuss Being authentically, it cannot be discussed as divorced from "Ethics" and by ethics I simply mean "how you exist" in a broad sense. Talking about ethics and how we exist is not something people like to do or are used to, our "Ethics" many times consists of abstract moral principles rather than transforming your Being itself. Another thing is talking about "Being" and "personal existence" and "The way in which we live our life from the inside" will seem repulsive to some of our culture's "knowledgeable fellows" they will conflate non-logical language with illogical language and think that talking about existence isn't a serious affair or that it should be left to religion, another lingering shadow of our dualism. As though "serious" "professional" people don't think about such things as "Existence itself" from the "inside". Professional people are supposed to be impersonal, "objective", but "friendly" to everyone. "Belief" is a matter of everybody's own personal opinion and what right have we to discuss the validity of personal beliefs because "Everybody is equal".

That is something that also needs to be discussed, not only developing a language for "the web of relationships from the inside" and authenticity, but communicating it. As you may agree, any communication about authenticity must be of a different type, must be "authentic". How are we to communicate about "authenticity" in a culture that is anathema to authenticity? We have dug so deep into dualism and have divided our life so much we have become "nihilistic". I do not know how the world is, I am in the US, I do not know where you are, but if you are in the US I am sure you can agree that our culture is diametrically opposed to authenticity in every form. We have a culture where everyone's beliefs are equal and ever person believes they are equal and all opinions are equally valid. We have a rampant relativism motivated by a lack of wanting to have to think. We have cultural idols who have lots of money and buy lots of products. We have popular music based around partying and purchasing. We have the notion that a "Successfull" existence is one in which you "get a good job" and run the rat race and have lots of things. Even the people who think they have "values", they make a big stint about curse words or sex or people mkaing fun of people, as though there weren't things by far more important to your existence. By the way, the psychologist Erich Fromm wrote a book you may like called "To have or to be?"


And I apologize for what partly is a rant about our culture, but it certainly is a problem. Authenticity requires a mode of communication where we share some amount of common ground. In order to do this we must change our culture, the mindset of our people, and this is largely a difficult thing.
 
  • #162


JD, there is indeed a limitation to language - many. But it's important to keep in mind the broader issues:

1) We try in philosophy to explain the world through words and the abstractions represented by words. Ontology seeks to at least in theory explain everything through the (hopefully) simplest set of words and concepts - while matching the evidence we glean from our senses.

2) A deeper understanding of the universe is experienced rather than conceptualized - it is beyond words. Some can go through life with words alone but for those seekers who want to plumb the depths more authentically, there is a need to abandon words - at least at times.

Eastern traditions emphasize 2) over 1) and vice versa in the West. But there is no exclusivity of modes.

Here's my best effort to explain the limitations of words and logic in a recent essay entitled On the Heart.
______________________________

The kindness of strangers seems irrational to some people and wouldn’t generally be considered economically rational behavior to an economist focused on pure cost/benefit analysis. Thankfully, humans aren’t entirely rational creatures, despite the assumptions of economists. We follow our hearts as much or probably more than we do our heads.

This latest essay in my series on absent-minded science continues the exploration of reason and logic, begun in my last installment. Part X will conclude the series with a light-hearted examination of why certain explanations are more compelling than others.

A broader insight into such kindnesses may be arrived at when we consider what it really means to be “rational.” Like a lot of concepts, we think at first blush we know what this word means. But there’s really no clear and defensible definition of rational behavior or “rationality” more generally. What time frame are we referring to? How broad are our considerations in making “rational” decisions? These details are key to any conclusion regarding “rational behavior” in any situation; and these details depend on the choices of the person acting in each situation. (As discussed in my last essay, truth is perspectival in all situations, other than definitions that are independent of any particular space-time.)

Paulo Coelho’s masterpiece, The Alchemist, has much to say about the heart. This amazing little book is a parable about how to live a good life by finding and achieving one’s “personal legend.” Alchemy is unsurprisingly a consistent theme in the book, meant as a metaphor for personal transformation. The book is still on bestseller lists despite its release in the early 1990s.

The book’s main character, a young sheepherder from Andalusia, Spain, travels with the Alchemist through the desert of North Africa looking for his personal legend. He asks the Alchemist: “Why do we have to listen to our hearts?”

‘“Because wherever your heart is, that is where you’ll find your treasure.”

‘“But my heart is agitated,” the boy said. “It has its dreams, it gets emotional, and it’s become passionate over a woman of the desert. It asks things of me, and it keeps me from sleeping many nights, when I’m thinking about her.”

‘“Well, that’s good. Your heart is alive. Keep listening to what it has to say.”’

The boy had a long conversation with his heart there in the desert. He came to understand his heart. “He asked it, please, never to stop speaking to him. He asked that, when he wandered far from his dreams, his heart press him and sound the alarm. The boy swore that, every time he heard the alarm, he would heed its message.”

The secret that alchemists have pursued over the centuries, according to Coelho, is known as the “Master Work.” The Master Work is written on an emerald and describes how to create the Elixir of Life and the Philosopher’s Stone. But the Master Work, according to the Alchemist, “can’t be understood by reason alone. It is a direct passage to the Soul of the World.”

This metaphor stands for life in general. Can we grasp life, can we understand our own lives and find meaning, with reason alone? It seems not. Reason is a very powerful tool and it is certainly a good guide to most aspects of life. But reason has limitations. Reason depends on representations, on models of reality. To try and grasp life with reason alone is like trying to describe the most beautiful sunset you’ve ever seen with words alone. It can’t do it justice.

The problems go far deeper, however.

A prominent Second Century CE Buddhist philosopher, Nagarjuna, concluded that there is no ultimate truth: All doctrines are ultimately empty. Jan Westerhoff writes in his introduction to Nagarjuna’s work (Nagarjuna’s Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction): “According to [Nagarjuna’s] view of truth, there can be no such thing as ultimate truth, a theory describing how things really are, independent of our interests and conceptual resources employed in describing it.”

But if there is no ultimate truth, even this doctrine cannot be true, so there is ultimate truth. We end up in paradox, a problem inherent in all logical or conceptual systems, as discussed in more depth in my last essay.

This is a key insight of the Zen Buddhist tradition (which came much later than Nagarjuna’s version of Buddhism, but still relies in part on Nagarjuna’s thinking): Langauge and concepts ultimately fail in leading us to true understanding. They are, at best, pointers to reality. Hence the use of paradoxical koans as teaching aids, the most famous of which is, “What is the sound of one hand clapping?” These mind-twisters have no correct answer – they are intended to show that logic itself is illogical.

Reality is apparently deeper than logic.

Nancy Cartwright, a respected philosopher of science, makes a great case in her 1999 book, The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science, that science does indeed exist within fairly limiting boundaries. Even our best theories of physics, biology, economics, etc. consist of a “dappled” patchwork of ideas and mathematics. Despite the fact that we have accomplished truly great things over the last few hundred years—modern medicine, powerful computers that fit in our palm, marvels in entertainment, etc.—we are just scratching the surface of what the universe has to offer.

Science, while limited, has obviously been tremendously important in helping us to understand the world and create useful technologies. This trend shall certainly continue, probably in perpetuity.

We know with certainty, however, that we will never know the fullness of nature because we never know the full extent of what we don’t know. We are like a hiker seeking the top of a mountain who thinks she sees the top not far away only to find as she crests the hill she is on that she sees yet another hill above her, and so on. We will never know where the top is because we don’t know the full extent of what we don’t know.

To extend the physical metaphor further: This mountain springs from an ocean of unreason, with other islands of reason rising from the ocean’s surface in the dappled manner suggested by Cartwright and other thinkers. The best we can hope for is to navigate this vast ocean of unreason and scale the islands of reason we come across with equanimity and grace.

The kindness of strangers often demands this, as does a more complete experience of the universe.
 
  • #163


JDStupi said:
Now regarding "finding a language" would you agree with my notion ("my" as if it is all mine) that the "language" of art seems to be stronger at communicating this type of "thought" at this time? Mainly that language is simply communication and certain types of poetry or music may be able to better convey the depth of "Being"?


I do agree with you. And you probably know that Heidegger wrote several essays on poetry as a kind of fundamental thinking... drawing mainly on Rilke and Holderlin.

I would say that art and music and poetry are the primary language we have for articulating existence – as contrasted with describing reality. Literature (fiction-writing) usually operates on both sides at once – describing the object-world we live in from a personal point of view. As ordinary conversation also does.

The thing about art and music and poetry is that they have the power to pull you into the present moment, if you can teach yourself how to pay attention to them. When I was in college I wanted to be a composer, and spent a lot of time learning how to listen to music. You have to stay focused and think about what you’re hearing, because music articulates “the moment” over different time-scales – notes and phrases and extended melodies, and the “architecture” of the piece as a whole, that supports a kind of drama, of one theme or one section contrasting with what came before. But the purpose of this “thinking” is to stay with the music in the moment and feel what’s going on. So this was an education for me in the “back-and-forth” aspect of paying thoughtful attention. It’s not just letting yourself be immersed in the moment, getting lost in it, but about using your mind to participate in it.

Art doesn’t have this aspect of articulating time, as music does. But it’s also all about being there in the moment with a painting or photograph, or whatever. Seeing becomes a kind of listening, you stay with it and see what happens, as you look at it. So there’s a similar kind of back-and-forth of attention, thinking “in your head”, but also coming back into the moment and focusing on a real-time relationship with something. And the same with poetry. Unlike fiction, poetry tends to trip you up with unexpected language, making you stop and think. But again, it’s not the kind of thinking that comes up with “ideas”, primarily. The goal is “appreciation” – which may sound trite, but I think it might be the best word we have for thinking in relation to existence.
 
  • #164


JDStupi said:
I hate to sound like some type of Eastern pundit, which I am surely not, but simply in the interest of discussing these notions I do still say that turning East would be a fruitful idea. I have yet to dig into the East's philosophy, but as you have stated it is the West who largely developed this abstractive mode of communication. Quite possibly, many of the germinal seeds for the creation of this new authentic mode of speech is already to be had in Eastern thought. Something like the Dao-de-jing with its "The way that can be named is not the true way" may help us seek thought in that direction.


I wouldn’t want to discount the Eastern traditions... if we want to think about evolving human consciousness, it’s important to get to know something about them, because they developed very sophisticated ways of “thinking” in completely different directions from the West. I put “thinking” in quotes because the word doesn’t really even have the same meaning in all these different traditions.

And personally, I very much appreciate the expression of Taoist philosophy in Tai Chi. But the Western tradition is unique, in a certain way. It started out with the Greeks, who invented a kind of “abstractive” thinking that was actually fairly primitive, in comparison with the Indian or Chinese traditions. And if you only look at Greek thought – say, through the development of neo-Platonism in the 3rd century AD – you have a tradition that’s more or less comparable to the much more sophisticated traditions that developed in the East. All of them reached a certain point of development and then essentially leveled off.

But in the West, the Greek intellectual language got taken over by Christianity, in the development of its complex body of “doctrine”. This time I put the word in quotes because no other religious tradition has anything really comparable. There was a very strange fusion here between two utterly different way of thinking – you can see it maybe most clearly in Augustine. On the one hand there was the intellectually detached, “scientific” frame of mind of the Greeks, and on the other a passionate religious commitment to finding an ultimate meaning in day-to-day human existence.

Considered as an intellectual invention, Christian doctrine is just bizarre. It makes claims about reality that are deliberately paradoxical. It was a weird compromise created through a series of intellectual battles between those who believed in rational, intellectually satisfying explanation, and those who insisted on personal faith as the “meaning of Being”. And these conflicting commitments continued through the entire Western tradition. Look at Newton, for example, who was just as deeply engaged in theological debates (from a fairly fanatical point of view, incidentally) as he was with the creation of mathematical physics.

Now of course every tradition has its own history of conflicts and resolutions. But there’s something unique about the Western tradition that has kept it evolving, questioning its own foundations again and again in a long series of intellectual revolutions. So yes, this is why I believe in the possibility of another revolution in thought.

As to your “rant”, I’m much in sympathy with you. But our culture has many sides – even here in the US. In the 1950's and 60's there was a lot of talk about “authenticity” – Erich Fromm being a good example – and the intellectual world felt very alive, very engaged. Since then we’ve seen a long period in which “intellectuals” have been essentially irrelevant to what’s going on in the world. But I don’t think that will last.
 
  • #165


An interesting comparison of Whitehead and Heidegger - the author concludes:

"Focusing particularly on Whitehead’s concept of prehension, I propose that the reconciliation between [the scientific and religious] tendencies of the West have been achieved. I argue that Heidegger has achieved a similar reconciliation within the context of Continental thought, but ultimately betrayed this delicate synthesis with the anti-humanistic and anti-scientific thrust of his later philosophy. Thus, I argue that it is the metaphysical vision of Whitehead which has set the dialogue between religion, science, and philosophy upon a new course."

http://www.google.com/url?sa=t&sour...gA-Ur-KzQ&sig2=rCnQtvSpXCfHALyqyKKVXw&cad=rja
 
  • #166


PhizzicsPhan said:
An interesting comparison of Whitehead and Heidegger -

Thank you, this is indeed an interesting paper, and it describes just the issue I was getting at very briefly in my last post. The direct link seems to be
http://www.metanexus.net/conference2005/pdf/weidenbaum.pdf"

Early on in his career my Dad also thought highly of Whitehead’s “process” philosophy, and I get why it’s attractive. This paper shows that if what you’re looking for is a nice, comfortable “reconciliation of these dual tendencies of the West,” Whitehead is a good place to settle.

The author says, “From Scholasticism to liberal theology, innumerable philosophical systems have been proposed to achieve the final synthesis of these two worldviews” – i.e. “the synoptic vision of the Greeks and the spiritual legacy of Abraham.” I agree that this goes to the heart of our intellectual tradition. And he seems to feel Whitehead has done a good job with this reconciliation. So I guess we should be glad that the driving conflict behind so many centuries of creative work finally got resolved, early in the 20th century. Now we can get on to other business of tidying things up, like reconciling Whitehead with Buddhism, and then we’ll be all set.

I apologize for the sarcasm, I know that’s not polite or appropriate, but I can’t help it. I don’t even want to disparage this paper – I recommend it, because I would guess most philosophy students these days don’t get this kind of viewpoint on their tradition. But when the author more or less equates the issues of Kierkegaard and Heidegger with those of William James and Whitehead, I don’t think he’s grasped what’s essential.

This paper is written from a viewpoint in which the obvious purpose of philosophy is to come up with a satisfying theory of the world. It doesn’t necessarily have to explain much – we can leave that to Science – it just needs to give us a friendly feeling that we’ve got the world more or less wrapped up and accounted for, that we have the kinds of basic concepts that can more less "explain" everything, and resolve all the conflicts that arise from our various one-sided viewpoints.

The thing is, the people on the “religious” side of this age-long conflict were not after this sort of reconciliation. They were radicals who believed in conceptual revolution, as I do too. So if you want, you can interpret Kierkegaard’s attack on Hegel as a philosophical “refutation of totalization”, which is handled even more intelligently by Whitehead, and in a more balanced way. But Kierkegaard wasn’t trying to achieve a “correct” philosophical system. He was trying to break through the comfortable self-assurance of 19th century intellectuals, trying to show that with all their comprehensive theories they hadn’t even begun to think about what’s most important in human life.

I would agree with you that Whitehead was quite successful in developing a coherent intellectual system. Heidegger certainly was not. And now at the start of the 21st century, despite the radical breakthroughs in science a century ago, we’re still thinking pretty much in the same old 19th-century categories. Whitehead didn’t accomplish it single-handed, but it seems that teachers of philosophy have pretty much convinced their students that there’s no revolution on the horizon.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #167


Conrad, I get the impression that you haven't read much Whitehead yet - I think you should before you judge him as inadequate.

And I'm still not sure what you're looking for exactly. You seem to be suggesting that philosophy is perhaps a failed enterprise from the outset - in which case the vehicles of words and concepts aren't going to be much help for you no matter their nature. If you're seeking a more spiritual route, there are many options.

There is in fact already a huge literature on Whitehead and Buddhism and these two traditions are fairly compatible in their philosophies. Here's a recent talk I gave on this topic at UC Santa Barbara (where I am a visiting scholar):

http://tamhunt.blogspot.com/2010/10/process-philosophy-buddhism-and-western.html
 
  • #168


apeiron, going back to an earlier criticism of yours: I agree with Skrbina that Koestler should be labeled a panpsychist, by implication if not by self-labeling. See page 220 of Skrbina's Panpsychism in the West, in which he discusses Koestler's various arguments on this issue. Koestler's final statement, from Janus: A Summing Up, is that psyche proceeds in a step-wise fashion at all levels of existence. This is panpsychism, even if Koestler himself didn't like the label:

http://books.google.com/books?id=Zd...&resnum=1&ved=0CC8Q6AEwAA#v=onepage&q&f=false
 
  • #169


ConradDJ said:
I couldn’t get to page 221 in the Existentialism book, so I’m not sure what you’re referring to. The Harvard article is very interesting.

In Heidegger’s thinking, “language” always refers not just to the words and grammar and syntax, but to the whole world of communicative connection that humans grow up inside.

The Harvard article ends with the question “Do people think before they speak or do words shape their thoughts?” I would say, the experiments described here are exploring the world of human meaning in which young children already participate, before they begin learning actual words. This is important, because if we want to maintain that language is what’s most essential to being human, we need to think of “language” in this broader way.

When human “consciousness” first began to evolve, branching off from the primate mainstream, I doubt very much that it involved anything like a “language” in the narrow sense of the word. I imagine it involved giving certain kinds of experiences a special emotional weight that people could share with each other and pass on... out of which something like “symbols” could eventually emerge.

The key point is that something got passed on, from individual to individual, from generation to generation, something that kept on getting itself passed on. It’s hard to imagine what this earliest form of communicative connection might have been like, as it’s hard to imagine how self-replicating entities first got going, as the basis for the evolution of life.

We could maybe say – the essence of “language” is the feeling that at bottom it’s important to connect with others, to understand them and make ourselves understood. I would guess that whatever it was that first began to get itself passed down among our proto-human ancestors must have been able to communicate some such feeling, to hook children into to the process of reproducing what eventually became human culture.

As to my point of view being “free from confusion” – as if! It certainly is not. My hope is only that it may eventually lead toward some clarity on this matter of “consciousness”. I don't feel that mysticism or panpsychism are heading in that direction.

From this I take it you are saying that although initially confusing it may offer a better alternative to firstly, something which you say only results in confusion and secondly, to pansychism ( that may have the same result). I don’t know that these are exculsive or that this offers an exhaustive choice.

But, Heidegger is presented as an alternative, with a nebulous outcome that may be better, it may ‘eventually lead toward some clarity on this matter of “consciousness”’.

Regarding how this may be appreciated, Whitehead was about hermeneutical concerns, his metaphysics being about an interrelated matrix of experience giving an interpretive context where experience has meaning. Much like Derrida, there is interest in language, and the limitations it involves. That is why I mentioned Derrida when Conrad first wrote of Heidegger here, a long time ago. Whitehead is probably more suited.

Some suggestions as to things that may be authentic here have been art including poetry and meditation. Elsewhere, Descartes mentioned dreams and madness, hence Foucoult’s “Madness and Civilization”. Silence is another.

There was mention here and elsewhere about the origins of language and ideas about a relationship with music. This may interest:
https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=413657&page=15
Post #236 and the next.

JDStupi said:
“but if you are in the US I am sure you can agree that our culture is diametrically opposed to authenticity in every form. We have a culture where everyone's beliefs are equal and ever person believes they are equal and all opinions are equally valid. We have a rampant relativism…

Will you explain the conclusions drawn about inauthenticity and relativism?
 
Last edited:
  • #170


PhizzicsPhan said:
Conrad, I get the impression that you haven't read much Whitehead yet - I think you should before you judge him as inadequate.


Tam – You’re right. I looked in my library and found only his one little book on The Function of Reason, written for a general audience, around the same time as his major work Process and Reality. It begins with a nice summary:

“History discloses two main tendencies in the course of events. One tendency is exemplified in the slow decay of physical nature. With stealthy inevitableness there is degradation of energy... The other tendency is exemplified by the yearly renewal of nature in the spring, and by the upward course of biological evolution... Reason is the self-discipline of [this second] originative element in history. Apart from the operations of Reason, this element is anarchic.”​

Of course this doesn’t get at what’s most original in his work, but it gives a feeling for his view of the world. And whether this kind of thinking is inadequate depends on what you’re trying to accomplish. You seem to be looking for a bridge between Science and Buddhism, and there’s certainly nothing wrong with that. I believe you that Whitehead is more than adequate for this.

His work is not “adequate” if you believe, like Heidegger, that Western thought came to an impasse at the end of the 19th century, with Nietzsche, and has to find a new starting-point. Not because it was wrong, but because it couldn't get to what's fundamental.

I looked into Whitehead’s “process” ontology many years ago, and didn’t spend much time with it, although it has some similarity to the ideas I was trying to develop. But it seemed clear to me that he’s operating within a pretty standard intellectual frame of reference. As represented in the quotation above, he has a quite traditional view of the role of reason and is content with some rather vague notions about science. This was the opposite of what I was looking for.

The bottom line for me is that Whitehead is still envisioning the world “from outside”, from the usual objective point of view. Instead of a world of objects, it’s a world made of “actual occasions” or “experiences”... Here’s a little summary from Wikipedia:

“Whitehead's philosophy resembles in some respects the monads of Leibniz. However, unlike Leibniz's monads, Whitehead's occasions of experience are interrelated with every other occasion of experience that precedes it in time. Inherent to Whitehead's conception is the notion of time; all experiences are influenced by prior experiences, and will influence all future experiences. This process of influencing is never deterministic; an occasion of experience consists of a process of prehending other experiences, and then a reaction to it. This is the process in process philosophy. Because no process is ever deterministic, free will is essential and inherent to the universe.”​

I have no real objection to this, but it has the same sort of vague relationship to science as the previous quotation. Many have found it adequate and interesting, as an alternative to the “materialist” view. But to me the discoveries of science are much more interesting than this kind of philosophical debate. What’s actually going on in Quantum Mechanics is not going to be illuminated by these tired old categories of “mind” and “matter”.

Leibniz made a real breakthrough in imagining the world – in essence, he saw the universe not as a single vast entity but as the coordination of all our unique individual worlds. But he still framed this within the unimaginable “mind of God”, i.e. from the traditional philosophical standpoint “outside the world”. I see Whitehead’s ontology as a version of this same kind of thinking, that was revolutionary back in the 18th century, but quite calmly “rational” in the 20th.

This is inadequate only if you’re looking for a more radical viewpoint. What I found in Heidegger was a way of thinking that’s trying not to “back away” from one’s own unique perspective in a world of relationships, that’s not trying to achieve an all-embracing view of the world as a whole, but to understand the nature of existence “from inside”. Instead of seeing the world from a distance, laid out along a time-line of "before" and "after", like Whitehead, he's trying to see it "in real time", as in fact we all do.

Whether that will turn out to be a new beginning remains to be seen. But it’s an attempt to find a radically different perspective.
 
  • #171


Conrad, you write: "I looked into Whitehead’s “process” ontology many years ago, and didn’t spend much time with it, although it has some similarity to the ideas I was trying to develop. But it seemed clear to me that he’s operating within a pretty standard intellectual frame of reference. As represented in the quotation above, he has a quite traditional view of the role of reason and is content with some rather vague notions about science. This was the opposite of what I was looking for."

This is not accurate. Whitehead was a truly original thinker and I think you'll find a lot of what you're looking for in his work. Remember previous posts of yours in this thread where I've said I agree 100%? I agreed because the point of view you were expressing is the point of view that Whitehead came from (which I share, not because of any blind devotion, which is not the case, but because after decades of searching for an adequate ontology I found that Whitehead's system fits the bill in many many ways).

What you're looking for is, I believe, in Whitehead and his successors. His whole point is to recognize the fundamentality of the inside - which I've mentioned a number of times to you in this thread - and then to explain the relationship of the inside to the many outsides each inside is confronted with.

No, my primary purpose is not to reconcile Buddhism with any Western philosophy. I've crafted my own philosophy/spirituality over the decades and expressed it in the in-progress book I've linked to in this thread (Mind, World, God). My ideas draw on Western process philosophy, Vedanta, Buddhism, and many other traditions.

Again: you really should read Science and the Modern World and Process and Reality. And if you find that you need some easing into his ideas, check out Griffin's Unsnarling the World-Knot or a Key to Whitehead's Process and Reality (this is the route I took).
 
  • #172


I forgot to mention that Whitehead's philosophy does in fact provide key insights into quantum mechanics, as well as just about every other major area of science or philosophy. You write: "What’s actually going on in Quantum Mechanics is not going to be illuminated by these tired old categories of “mind” and “matter”."

To the contrary, David Bohm's "ontological interpretation" of QM is explicitly based in Whitehead's ideas. It resolves the wave/particle duality conundrum by suggesting that there is an actual particle in each case but there is also a "guiding wave" or "quantum potential" that influences the particle's course, like a small boat tossed on the ocean during a storm. So the wave is not a particle at the same time - they are, rather, two aspects of a single phenomenon.

I would go a bit further, however, and suggest that these two aspects can be united more closely when we consider the oscillatory nature of actual entities. So rather than there being a particle that remains a particle, and a guiding wave that represents the quantum potential, we can suggest that each particle oscillates with its wave aspect over time. When it is objective and measurable it is a particle, but between each particle aspect it is a wave, which is its subjective/prehensive aspect. This is why the double slit experiment can reveal wave or particle behavior depending on the conditions - particles aren't just windowless monads, they are, instead, feeling and choice-making entities, albeit at an extremely rudimentary level.

Other conundrums that the process view of the world helps to resolve:

- the hard problem of consciousness (discussed at length in this thread)
- spiritual experience
- "origin" of life - all things are alive to some degree because life and mind are different terms for the same thing
- free will - also fundamental, as I illustrated with the wave/particle issue (it compounds as matter compounds in its complexity, with true individuals exercising free will at every level, as opposed to mere aggregates, which are not true individuals)
- the nature of time: it is the result of all actual entities oscillating from subject to object to subject to object, which Whitehead calls the "creative advance"
- many problems in evolution, including the source of variation for evolution and a naturalization of mind
 
  • #173


If apeiron is still tuned in, I wanted to respond to an earlier point I left hanging. Apeiron acknowledged the difficulty in establishing the exact point of emergence of life (and thus of mind in his theory), but said just because it's hard to pin down it doesn't mean it's not there. Just as we can't clearly distinguish the shore from the ocean, he wrote, we can't clearly distinguish life from non-life but we still know there is a transition.

His analogy is in fact strong support for my thesis of panzoism (life is omnipresent and it's all a matter of degree, literally). We can in fact exactly identify the border between the shore and the ocean because we can define clearly what "shore" and "ocean" mean. Ocean is water, which is uncontroversially defined as H2O mixed with various other trace elements and the creatures that inhabit the ocean. Shore is uncontroversially defined as solid rather than liquid - not H20. Thus we can exactly delineate the boundary between shore and ocean as the exact point where solids become H20. This point surely changes in each moment due to erosion, etc, but it is easily identifiable at any particular point.

Not so with life. Apeiron hasn't even given any particular criteria for what life is, other than to appeal to a fuzzy "epistemic cut," which seems by its very name to be an epistemological not an ontological notion.

As I've explained previously, any criteria-based notion of life falls prey to arbitrariness in selection of criteria (must life be DNA-based?) or non-discreteness, that is, the criterion at issue exists on a continuum. For example, metabolism: does self-replicating RNA metabolize as it replaces its molecules? Does an atom that exchanges electrons metabolize? Only if we circularly define metabolism as limited to cell-based life can we answer these questions in the negative.

The far simpler and cleaner approach to life is to acknowledge that "life" is simply a term we give to the more obviously complex features of our universe. Cell-based life has complexified to the point that it appears to be discontinuous, but it's really not - it's just an example of exponential complexification. We can arbitrarily choose to designate this a difference in kind, but when we think deeply we realize that's it's "just" a difference in degree.
 
  • #174


Looking again at my earlier posts in this thread, I don’t think I did justice to the concept of “authenticity”. So I’d like to try one more time. My earlier attempts at this were in https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3225035&postcount=12".

The very odd thing about this notion in Being and Time is that it has a very personal tone – what JDStupi called “ethical”. Authenticity is about “being yourself”, as opposed to living within a point of view determined by others. Yet at the same time Heidegger presents it as the key to “fundamental ontology”, as leading to a new way of conceptualizing our world.

People often object to this notion of an “existential” basis for philosophy. E.g. Apeiron’s comment in his post #4, that “Heidegger remained too attached to the human condition and a narrowly psychological model.”

Now apart from his very personal standpoint, Heidegger’s thinking essentially follows the same path taken by Descartes and Kant. Each of them wants to make a new beginning for philosophy by going back to one’s own immediate experience of the world... since after all, this is the only point of view any of us ever have. If we can’t build philosophy on our own actual experience, then all we’re doing is accepting the stories people tell us about things.

Descartes believed that the application of reason to the data of our senses would get us to an ultimate, objective truth about the world – which is the basic perspective of modern science. Kant understood that even the world of our “immediate perception” is something we ourselves actively construct, in our minds – so there can really be no such thing as a pure, unbiased viewpoint. We have no access to reality “as it is in itself,” but we can learn the principles on which our mental constructions work. I would say, the dialogue between these two perspectives underlies most of modern thought.

Why then does Heidegger want to “personalize” this issue? Why does he want to make it about how we live our lives, about “being yourself” instead of just seeing the world from your own viewpoint?

Because so long as the issue is how we see the world and what we can know about it, we’re in effect “standing outside” the world as observers. From this “inauthentic” standpoint, we automatically conceptualize the world as a thing, an object we can look at from various points of view, about which there are facts to be found out. Even the “post-modern” perspective – which Heidegger would characterize as neo-Kantian – still tends to maintain this kind of intellectual distance from the world it constructs.

This is not a bad thing, for many purposes. But there is a basic aspect of the world it can’t grasp. I tried to summarize our situation in my second post –
ConradDJ said:
We know how to describe “systems” of many kinds objectively, from the outside... and we’ve developed ways to investigate the structure of our internal subjective experience. But the deep problem is how to reconceive the “outside” world of relationships from the standpoint of one participating in it.

It’s not that our view of the world “from outside” is inaccurate. The problem isn’t that our objective scientific theories are wrong, but that they’re not fundamental – they’re operating with the wrong notion of what a foundation should look like. So we can know all about the physical world, down to an incredible level of detail, and still have no clue what the picture is showing us.


So what does “authenticity” have to do with foundations? The thing is, when we see the world as an object, a set of given facts, then we’re looking for some ultimate set of given facts as its “foundation”. Or from the Kantian perspective, we’re looking for the ultimate ground of subjectivity. In either case, what’s fundamental seems as though it ought to be something “basic” – simple and singular. We model what’s fundamental in the world on what we take as fundamental in our own being.

But for Heidegger, our “actual experience” of being is not a matter of “observing” but of participating and communicating. “Having one’s own point of view” in the world is not just an intellectual problem. “Being yourself” is hard for human beings, because we don’t exist independently of how other people see us and feel about us. For us to “be who we are” depends on being able to express ourselves to other people, and to understand and care about them, and to let them “be who they are.” This all has to work, or we have no way even to find out “who we are” authentically. Whether or not we think about it much, we all grow up inside a complicated nexus of personal relationships, and it’s never easy for us to be clear about the point of view that’s uniquely our own... even though this is the only point of view any of us ever really has.

So in a participatory world, the foundations are not simple. It’s not easy to be a basis for anything, and nothing ever depends on only one other thing as its foundation. Everything depends on a context of relationships with other things, each of which depends on some other, quite different context of relationships. And not much of what goes on in this kind of world can be nailed down as definite fact – since all the information exchanged between things is seen from some particular point of view in some particular situation.

In short, the “authentic” perspective gives us a different sense for what to look for as fundamental. The issue is not how to reduce complex facts to simple, basic facts. Instead the issue is how to understand the kinds of support each thing needs, in its relationships, in order to be what it is.

For Descartes, to be “authentic” meant to doubt systematically what we learn from others, to test what we believe against our own experience, in the light or reason. This is all to the good. This is the perspective of an independent mind, focused on a factual reality that just is what it is, in and of itself. But this doesn’t describe the world of interdependent existence that you and I live in.

So unless we start from the very personal difficulty of “being ourselves” in the world, we remain stuck in the “inauthentic” intellectual perspective of a detached observer, modeling the world on his own detached logic. That has worked very well, for analyzing facts and uncovering principles. But it doesn’t let us grasp what’s fundamental – i.e. where the facts are coming from, and what the principles are for. I don’t think we’ll be able to see what our world is actually doing unless we learn to see it from inside, from the unique viewpoint of something that’s helping to do it.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #175


ConradDJ said:
In short, the “authentic” perspective gives us a different sense for what to look for as fundamental. The issue is not how to reduce complex facts to simple, basic facts. Instead the issue is how to understand the kinds of support each thing needs, in its relationships, in order to be what it is.

For Descartes, to be “authentic” meant to doubt systematically what we learn from others, to test what we believe against our own experience, in the light or reason. This is all to the good. This is the perspective of an independent mind, focused on a factual reality that just is what it is, in and of itself. But this doesn’t describe the world of interdependent existence that you and I live in.

So unless we start from the very personal difficulty of “being ourselves” in the world, we remain stuck in the “inauthentic” intellectual perspective of a detached observer, modeling the world on his own detached logic. That has worked very well, for analyzing facts and uncovering principles. But it doesn’t let us grasp what’s fundamental – i.e. where the facts are coming from, and what the principles are for. I don’t think we’ll be able to see what our world is actually doing unless we learn to see it from inside, from the unique viewpoint of something that’s helping to do it.

Again Conrad, you are presenting a very clear and useful argument. But I still see Peirce as offering the step forward from Descartes, Kant and the rest.

I think where these conversations keep floundering is with the urge to assert that the situation is fundamentally this (ie: monistically boiling down to authenticity, to the primacy of subjective interaction) and so not fundamentally that (ie: the antithetical notion of the inauthentic, the objective view of a collection of interacting subjects).

But what is real only exists because it is separable into figure and ground, event and context, the particular and the general, or whatever hierarchical dichotomy you choose to describe the situation.

It becomes tenditious to call one "authentic", and the other not, when nothing could actually exist without them both being present and having a precisely complementary and synergistic relationship. So stepping back, the real interaction we should be focused on is the global one between the authentic and inauthentic, using your terms, not simply the localised play of interactions which you call the authentic.

Philosophy, like all forms of knowing, is about generalisation - the forming of universal ideas or universal truths. Descartes' faculty of reason is simply the result of a history of such generalisation about the world, the accumulated knowledge of how things work, how causality operates, the invariant seeming principles by which reality self-organises.

So when you say...

The issue is not how to reduce complex facts to simple, basic facts. Instead the issue is how to understand the kinds of support each thing needs, in its relationships, in order to be what it is.

...then it is general systems principles which explain how particular points of view can even be. There has to be a context (of universalised constraints). This is what supports the existence then of localised interactions.

Imagine some kind of interaction between two points. Draw a line. It seems easy to do. At a stroke, there can be a crisp and unambiguous relationship. It seems fundamental. You can now imagine building upwards to construct a world of point-to-point authentic interactions in this fashion.

Yet to draw that line, you also needed a generalised context, an empty backdrop. The line could only be definite to the extent that the absence of line everywhere else was equally definite. It was the dichotomy between event and context that was the fundamental relationship. And this fact needs to be central to the philosophy.

Say instead you tried to draw a line in some chaotic space where there was just a foam of possibility and no simple unmarked backdrop. How could the line have been clearly a line (when it is lost in a general confusion). It would be like painting a trace on a choppy sea.

So Heidegger's approach does not tackle the necessary existence of a global context for any localised notion of an authentic interaction.

Yes, you can argue that all philosophising must start with personal experience. The subjective stance. But it also seems clear enough that our subjective mind already has a history of development and carries its own heavy freight of context.

The marks of our own thoughts in any instant are crisp and clear because they are made against a living backdrop of all the other possible thoughts that we are not having, but could have had. The information we suppress (to create the blank page of our thinking) is just as fundamental to our current mental stance as the information we represent (as the chosen marks which construct our specific state of interaction at that moment).

This is the psychological reality. Thinking involves a dichotomisation into figure and ground, particulars and generals. The two parts of the process go hand in hand (even if they seem actions in opposite directions - in your terms, one a striving after the authentic, the other a stepping back to the inauthentic). And so a complete philosophy would have to embrace that essential dynamic. It would value both the particular and the general. And seek to account for the whole of nature in terms of that most fundamental interaction.
 
  • #176


during meditation i catch little glimpses of a "place" where there is no thought. no me. it is slightly deeper than awareness. by that i mean when i realize I'm there, i can't stay there. it is difficult to explain how all the concepts I've read in this post remind me of that "place" and the layers i have to shed to get there. could it be consciousness?
 
  • #177


Darken-Sol said:
during meditation i catch little glimpses of a "place" where there is no thought. no me. it is slightly deeper than awareness. by that i mean when i realize I'm there, i can't stay there. it is difficult to explain how all the concepts I've read in this post remind me of that "place" and the layers i have to shed to get there. could it be consciousness?

The different ontic stances expressed here would give you completely different answers I would say.

A panpsychist might want to agree that you are describing a dissolution of the particular self into some more primal or global state of self.

But the pansemiotic view would be that consciousness exists at the top end of things, rather than being materially fundamental. It is the result of developmental complexity rather than primal simplicity. So meditation and letting go cannot be taking you towards some "higher state of being". Instead it would be doing the opposite - taking you towards merely a vaguer, less developed, state of being. The reverse of enlightenment in fact.

Not sure how the Heideggerian view would fit though. It would seem to demand a sharp sense of self, or at least a precise sense of orientation and location, to also have a sharply defined state of authentic interaction.
 
  • #178


apeiron said:
Not sure how the Heideggerian view would fit though. It would seem to demand a sharp sense of self, or at least a precise sense of orientation and location, to also have a sharply defined state of authentic interaction.

i sense the things that i use to define myself most of the time. after i tune out external sensations and later emotions and memories i can experience thoughts without words in them, bet there is still a strong sense of self. its only when i get past the thinking that i lose orientation,self, and the ability to interact. any attempt to do anything forces me back a few steps then i usually give up.
 
  • #179


aperion, have you heard about Dr. Amit Goswami, Ph.D? i recently watched a documentary of his. i haven't looked further into it but it seems to be along the same lines as this post. i don't know enough about the scientific side of consciousness to form any opinion about his ideas. from reading your posts you seem like you could argue for or against him. that would help me a great deal as i can ask you questions. if you don't mind.
 
  • #180


Darken-Sol said:
from reading your posts you seem like you could argue for or against him.

I would argue against him for sure. But that would be too far off-topic here.
 
  • #181


apeiron said:
I would argue against him for sure. But that would be too far off-topic here.

not trying to jack your thread. consciousness interests me more than any other topic. where should i start, scientifically?
 
  • #182


apeiron said:
I think where these conversations keep floundering is with the urge to assert that the situation is fundamentally this (ie: monistically boiling down to authenticity, to the primacy of subjective interaction) and so not fundamentally that (ie: the antithetical notion of the inauthentic, the objective view of a collection of interacting subjects).

But what is real only exists because it is separable into figure and ground, event and context, the particular and the general, or whatever hierarchical dichotomy you choose to describe the situation.

It becomes tenditious to call one authentic , and the other not, when nothing could actually exist without them both being present and having a precisely complementary and synergistic relationship.


Apeiron – I really appreciate your patience with me, considering how stubbornly I resist your point of view. Your response is very much on point.

You’re right that there’s something “tendentious” about these terms “authentic” and “inauthentic”... even though I’ve tried to emphasize that the inauthentic viewpoint – that is, objectivity – is in no sense “wrong”. In fact, it defines a fundamental kind of truth, the truth of facts – the kind of truth that remains true no matter what perspective anyone has on it.

And you’re right that there’s a kind of “synergistic” relationship between these standpoints. Even though my own point of view is the only one I will ever have, I have to grow up into a world as discussed and determined by other people, before I can even begin to develop a perspective that’s uniquely my own. I not only need to learn the customs and conventions of the society I was born into, but I have to learn how to transcend this particular socially-determined viewpoint and envision some kind of higher, universal truth – which is the mission of the many philosophical and spiritual traditions, and also of science.

It’s only from this kind of detached, transcendent perspective – which does not have to be an intellectual one – that the issue of how to be authentically yourself arises. It’s only when you’ve really internalized the notion of a universal truth, that you can see the possibility of something further, another kind of foundation, in which the unique particularity of the individual plays the basic role.

Now to me, what’s genuine and powerful in the point of view you’ve developed from Peirce, is the determination always to include both sides. If you look at Greek thought, or the various Eastern traditions, there’s a powerful belief in transcendence, so the particular is always caught up and pulled into the universal truth. But the Western tradition, with its long immersion in Christianity, again and again comes back to the individual as having a basic kind of truth of its own. After all, each of us only has our own existence. The universal truth is after all only an Idea, not something anyone can live and breathe.

The Western tradition has been so creative, intellectually, just because it keeps on insisting on both sides. It wants universal principles, but it also wants them to arise out of individual existence. In your terms, what’s completely universal is to begin with merely Vague, non-differentiated. It has to become individual, local and particular in order to develop any shape or structure.
apeiron said:
So stepping back, the real interaction we should be focused on is the global one between the authentic and inauthentic, using your terms, not simply the localised play of interactions which you call the authentic.


Now here is the heart of our disagreement. In trying to understand this creative, evolving interplay, you and Peirce want to focus on the universal Idea of the interplay. The “real” interaction is the global one that happens between the principles of global and local, etc. Of course, you’re not talking about a battle of principles that takes place on some abstract level – the principles are always instantiated in particular, local events.

But this is why I keep referring back to Hegel. He was a true “existentialist” in his time. He believed that even the highest, universal truth works itself out in and through the daily grind of individual, material existence. But he found a universal Logic in it – as did Peirce. I can see reasons for preferring Peirce’s logic to Hegel’s, which is all too “binary”, too close to the traditional logic of “A” or “not A”. But the spirit is the same – the quest for Universal Idea that’s adequate to encompass all the particularity of existence.

Kierkegaard and Heidegger made the opposite choice. They wouldn’t agree with you that the “real” relationship we need to grasp is a relationship between Ideas. From their point of view, to the extent that global principles have meaning, it’s because they arise out of the “local” relationships between unique individuals in their particular contexts.

To you, this is a non-issue, because in any case we need both “global” and “local”. It’s foolish to argue about which is bigger or better or more basic – the point is to clarify the universal logic of their global interaction.

But for me, this “stepping back” to a global perspective where principles are what’s “real” is exactly the issue. What I want to emphasize about existence is precisely what becomes invisible when my individual, moment-to-moment existence gets pulled out the “here and now” of real life and turned into a principle.
apeiron said:
Philosophy, like all forms of knowing, is about generalisation - the forming of universal ideas or universal truths. Descartes' faculty of reason is simply the result of a history of such generalisation about the world...

...then it is general systems principles which explain how particular points of view can even be. There has to be a context (of universalised constraints). This is what supports the existence then of localised interactions.


What you say makes sense, and this is the time-honored perspective. And I feel I should apologize for my persisting – but I believe that philosophy can take a new direction.

We agree that “evolution” and “development” are both important, in the emergence of life. And I keep insisting on evolution, because to me it’s by far the best image available of an “existential” science – one based not on universal principles but on the contingencies and exigencies of particular, accidental situations. It’s just because the quest for a general theory of development is seeking a universal systems logic, that I think it’s misguided.

You will say – yes, but even the effort to understand evolution must try to generalize about it. But if you look at the vast amount we do understand about evolution, not much of it has to do with general principles. The systems theorists have the goal of making biology look more like physics, based on a compact set of principles. My goal would be to make physics look more like biology. Ultimately we are where we are because of history, and not much of that is logical.

So on the one hand, “foundation” refers to an Idea, a Process that’s the basis for everything. And on the other it ultimately refers to something individuals provide for each other in their “local” relationships. My existence depends on my mother and father, my context of family and friends, on all the extremely improbable events that led to my “here and now”. There is something deep we need to understand about this, but I don’t think it will take the form of a set of global principles.
 
  • #183


apeiron said:
Imagine some kind of interaction between two points. Draw a line. It seems easy to do. At a stroke, there can be a crisp and unambiguous relationship. It seems fundamental. You can now imagine building upwards to construct a world of point-to-point authentic interactions in this fashion.

Yet to draw that line, you also needed a generalised context, an empty backdrop. The line could only be definite to the extent that the absence of line everywhere else was equally definite. It was the dichotomy between event and context that was the fundamental relationship. And this fact needs to be central to the philosophy.


I get your point... but what kind of imaginative space are we in, here? We’re imagining an “empty backdrop” that you and I are not actually in. We’re not looking at this line between two points from any specific angle, or thinking of it as something that’s happening right now between us. So this image of a line between two points is nothing at all like the kind of relationship that people have with each other... or for that matter, the kind of relationship that two oxygen atoms have with each other to form a molecule.

I think it’s a deep reflection on our intellectual situation today that the world “relationship” does not distinguish at all between these two utterly dissimilar cases... on the one hand, the relationship between 2 and 4, or between local and global, or between two points on a line. And on the other, the relationships we actual beings “have” with each other, without which we couldn’t exist.

Our deepest difficulty, in trying to be philosophers and scientists today, is that this abstract mental space in which we envision a relationship between two points is such a natural and normal place for us to be. We’re completely comfortable in this space, which was not available at to the pre-Socratic philosophers, writing before Euclid.

In contrast, we can hardly begin to imagine the world we actually experience, from a point of view inside. All of these relationships we’re in, at the moment, happening in the context of all these other relationships... I use the word “context” because I haven’t found a better one. But there’s barely any similarity between the way words on a page made a literal context for each other, and the way what happens in a relationship makes it important what happens in another relationship.
apeiron said:
Say instead you tried to draw a line in some chaotic space where there was just a foam of possibility and no simple unmarked backdrop. How could the line have been clearly a line (when it is lost in a general confusion). It would be like painting a trace on a choppy sea.

So Heidegger's approach does not tackle the necessary existence of a global context for any localised notion of an authentic interaction.


This is right – but I question again whether a global context is really necessary. “Global” or “universal” is basic to the logic of our traditional philosophy, but does it correspond to anyone’s actual experience of anything? “Global” refers of course to the wholeness of the Earth, but we don’t know that the universe has that kind of wholeness. The world we actually experience, from a point of view “inside”, is unbounded in every direction.

Where everything happens, in our existence, is in our local “here and now”, in relationships with other things present nearby, and also things distant from us, both in space and time. The structure of this world has hardly been described – mainly because we take for granted that our image of the world in that abstract mental space of “objectivity” is adequate.

And of course it is adequate, for describing objects. It was Heidegger’s point that we need a different conceptual structure for describing the “here and now” of relationships in which we exist, each from our own point of view.

So “global” / “universal” is a basic logical category in the object-world. But we shouldn’t assume it plays the same role in relation to existence. The category “authentic” doesn’t operate within the object-world at all. It’s not at all the same as“local” or “particular” as aspects of reality. What’s particular about me is how I differ, objectively, from other people. But “authentic” refers to my own viewpoint, my own existence – which is neither “like” or “unlike” anyone else’s existence, because in existence there is never more than one’s own point of view, in relation to others. There is no comparing one existence with another.

And in existence, “local” doesn’t mean “in some certain locality” that could be anywhere in the world... it means only here, only in this moment. So to articulate the world from inside requires a very different set of conceptual tools.
 
  • #184


apeiron said:
Yes, you can argue that all philosophising must start with personal experience. The subjective stance. But it also seems clear enough that our subjective mind already has a history of development and carries its own heavy freight of context.


Yes... to try to understand the world “out there”, or even to understand yourself and where you come from — you need to able to get outside your own point of view and grasp the facts of your situation, your history and your psychology. The goal is not to do without the objective viewpoint, or the logical categories we've developed for the object-world.
apeiron said:
And so a complete philosophy would have to embrace that essential dynamic. It would value both the particular and the general. And seek to account for the whole of nature in terms of that most fundamental interaction.


But for you the essential dynamic is something that can be envisioned and analyzed “from outside”, in that abstract mental space. And for me, the essential dynamic is between authentic and inauthentic ways of being, which can only be envisioned from the standpoint of one’s own life and one’s own personal difficulties.

On the one hand, we observe the dynamic of the local and the particular, the clear, crisp foreground against the vague, empty or chaotic background.

On the other, we struggle to find out how to be ourselves and also be in our relationships.

These are very different visions of an essential dynamic, involving different kinds of essential differences. In the one case the world evolves through logical dichotomies... in the other through our existential dilemmas. In the one case there’s a given basis of universal principles... in the other a history of successful relationships that were the basis for new kinds of problems, calling for new ways in which things can be a basis for each other.

It hardly makes sense to argue about which of these visions is “right”... since the contexts are so different. But I very much appreciate the opportunities you’ve given me to try to articulate a point of view.
 
  • #185


Yes... to try to understand the world “out there”, or even to understand yourself and where you come from — you need to able to get outside your own point of view and grasp the facts of your situation, your history and your psychology. The goal is not to do without the objective viewpoint, or the logical categories we've developed for the object-world.

This is agreed; any attempt at understanding must begin from a transcendental standpoint, or that of the individual. That is to say, the most fundamental type of experience or understanding must account for the conditions of our consciousness to which all facts that we possesses are subject; essentially, the conditions that color and make my experience possible. Of course, conditions of consciousness are not static apparati; they cannot be abrogated, but cannot ever be fully accounted for either. The necessity of the "objective" standpoint is obvious at this point--we can only strive to understand these conditions of consciousness, as you said, through a rigorous descriptive psychology and exegesis of socio-historical reality. Inasmuch as the content of human existence is the only means which we have for analyzing the human, we must harness this objective world with the ultimate goal of coming to a richer understanding of the transcendental standpoint of self.

But for you the essential dynamic is something that can be envisioned and analyzed “from outside”, in that abstract mental space. And for me, the essential dynamic is between authentic and inauthentic ways of being, which can only be envisioned from the standpoint of one’s own life and one’s own personal difficulties.

On the one hand, we observe the dynamic of the local and the particular, the clear, crisp foreground against the vague, empty or chaotic background.

On the other, we struggle to find out how to be ourselves and also be in our relationships.

These are very different visions of an essential dynamic, involving different kinds of essential differences. In the one case the world evolves through logical dichotomies... in the other through our existential dilemmas. In the one case there’s a given basis of universal principles... in the other a history of successful relationships that were the basis for new kinds of problems, calling for new ways in which things can be a basis for each other.

It hardly makes sense to argue about which of these visions is “right”... since the contexts are so different. But I very much appreciate the opportunities you’ve given me to try to articulate a point of view.

I also agree with respect to this. "Abstract mental space" must still submit to the conditions of consciousness; inasmuch as this is concerned, it follows that the organic conditions of consciousness must play a vital role in relationships between the individual and other individuals and the individual and the world. As the amorphous (yet existent) conditions of consciousness are changed and shaped by the individual's experience, his understanding, appreciation, and search for meaning are fundamentally altered as well. There exists a living, holistic, and dynamic relationship between the individual and what is there for him in both inner and outer experience.
 
  • #186


Conrad, have you read Whitehead's Science and the Modern World or Process and Reality yet?

I actually agree with almost everything that Apeiron wrote in #175 and I also agree that Peirce has much insight on these issues. But Whitehead went further than anyone else it seems, in concordance with the development of modern physics, in his career - which was not an option for Peirce due to his point in history and was not taken up by Heidegger because he was paralyzed by the same word games and concepts that you have raised so many times in this thread.

Philosophy is indeed about generalization, about reducing complexity to simplicity and showing how simple assumptions can lead to complexity. Yes, humans exist necessarily in complexity, not simplicity. We are the result of at least 4 billion years of evolution - or 12 if we start from the beginning of this universe. But philosophy and science are about reasonable inference regarding origins and evolution. We'll never KNOW how the world became so complex - how I, or you, or apeiron, became so complex. But we can make reasonable inferences that are hopefully testable. And thus philosophy and science move forward in creating a (hopefully) increasingly accurate picture of the world independent of any particular human - and, yes, always interdependent.

Whitehead's ontology is all about melding the subjective with the objective, in a perpetual oscillation between subject and object, which is thus all about interdependency.

Heidegger, Peirce and Whitehead are almost completely commensurable - there's nothing "wrong" about any of their ideas (well, maybe some...). They're all looking at the same basic issues, but tackling different pieces of it and reaching different conclusions. But if we're seeking the broadest, most reasonable, most useful, and also the most hopeful, philosophy I think Whitehead and his successors have much to teach us.
 
Last edited:
  • #187


Darken-Sol, my view is that there are "twin ultimates" and that various types of religious/spiritual experience can be explained by a metaphor of "holonic navigation." Holons are parts/wholes, which are all conscious in their own right, to varying degrees. With perhaps one very large exception: the most basic ground of being/Brahman/apeiron/ether is, I believe, probably not conscious. It transcends subject/object. It is pure Spirit. To be reunited with this ground of being - to lose one's ego, one's sense of self, is to experience pure bliss (satchitananda).

This is holonic navigation to the ground, the base.

But other types of navigation are possible, it seems: upward navigation. So rather than dissolving one's ego into pure Spirit, more personalized experiences of religious ecstasy seem to suggest a merging with a higher level holon. Just as the cells in our body are individuals in their own right (with most likely an extremely rudimentary consciousness) that form the higher level consciousness we call our "self," so this self may merge at least temporarily with an even higher level consciousness.

I'm not entirely convinced of this higher level holonic navigation because it seems that we should have more evidence of higher level intelligences than we do. But I am quite convinced of the downward holonic navigation - there is abundant evidence for this, and I have personally experienced this type of dissolution of ego on more than one occasion.

I think the model of holonic navigation is potentially quite powerful and it is one item on my increasingly long list to use this as the basis for a "general theory of spirituality." One day...
 
  • #188


Energystrom said:
This is agreed; any attempt at understanding must begin from a transcendental standpoint, or that of the individual.

PhizzicsPhan said:
Whitehead's ontology is all about melding the subjective with the objective, in a perpetual oscillation between subject and object, which is thus all about interdependency.


The deep question is – what is this “standpoint of the individual”? Maybe just because this standpoint is the only one we ever have, it’s the most difficult thing to be articulate about. Because it’s the thing that’s hardest not to take for granted.

The “standpoint of consciousness” is what we’re always looking through. It’s invisible to us in the same way that light is invisible: even though all we see is light, we look right through it and perceive the world of objects around us. And our basic mental orientation is to this world of objects in space and time, that we share with everyone else. It’s very difficult to shift back to the standpoint that’s truly our own, and consider the world of present-time interaction and communication in relationships.

First Descartes and then Kant made heroic efforts to take the standpoint of consciousness. Because of their efforts, modern thought became familiar with the subjective point of view, the idea that each of us has a world of our own “in our heads”. This left philosophy with a strange conundrum: the only universe each of us has is the universe within our own minds, yet our own minds clearly exist as part of the objective universe.

Tam’s statement about Whitehead above seems correct. His is one of a long series of attempts to “meld the subjective with the objective” in some way. To my mind, though, these attempts don’t really take the “standpoint of the individual” seriously enough. They end up talking about “mind” or “apperception” as something going on out there in the real world of objects. That is, these philosophies all live in that abstract mental space in which we envision the world “from outside”, as if we weren’t actually there.

Just to be clear, I repeat – there’s nothing wrong with this traditional theoretical viewpoint at all... so long as we’re talking about the object-world. The error is in taking this point of view for granted in trying to grasp what’s truly fundamental.

When we do that, we can easily convince ourselves that the radical conundrum of subject and object is not really such a big problem. Tam just says, look, they’re exactly the same – everything is both subject and object. True, I get that. Everything has its own point of view in the world, and everything can be seen from some other point of view – fine. We can relax and feel we’ve accomplished something. But to me this kind of “armchair philosophy” is not helpful, that sits on the sidelines of existence and comprehends it all from a distance. This doesn’t get us any closer to appreciating what’s involved in being here, Heidegger’s “Da-sein”, the “standpoint of the individual”.

It’s not merely that our point of view on the world is “subjective”. It’s that everything we ever experience is this universe of our own experience. As Leibniz put it, “the monad has no windows.” I believe the human mind is the most radically isolated, self-enclosed entity there has ever been. No one else will ever have any clue about what your world looks like or feels like, since hardly anything of what you see and feel, moment to moment, can be put into words. And (as Kant said), you have absolutely no access to a world that exists beyond the world you imagine.

Unless we grasp this isolation of our own minds emphatically, we can’t have any idea of what this word “relationship” really means. Communication between two human minds is like communication between two entirely separate universes. It works only because you and I both imagine that it works. We believe in a world outside our own minds, and we imagine how other people feel and think. This is what Heidegger means by “transcendence” – that we reach, in our own minds, for something beyond, out there in the world, and everything we do and think happens in the context of that unconscious reach.

It’s not easy to appreciate the point Heidegger’s trying to make. It’s much easier just to say, obviously humans get information about the world around them, through their senses... obviously humans communicate with each other, through language. What’s the problem? And then we continue to take for granted that abstract mental space, in which what’s truly fundamental can’t appear.

For most practical purposes, our minds are not isolated from each other, of course. For most practical purposes, the objective viewpoint works great for understanding what’s here in the world around us. Forget about “the standpoint of the individual” – it’s no big deal, it’s just something we all have, right?

But I think, if we want to understand how human consciousness evolved, or how the physical universe evolved, we have to find ways to stop taking so much for granted, specifically about our relationships, and our ability to communicate. Human minds could only evolve this level of “self-consciousness”, this awareness of our own existence in our own unique mental space, because our relationships with each other evolved to make that meaningful, through the language we’ve evolved for mutual imagining and believing. Something like “mind” could never have evolved by itself, in isolation. We can be the most radically isolated beings in the universe only because we’ve evolved a sense of connection between us that can bridge the gap even between two different universes.

This is hard not to take for granted. I think even Heidegger wasn’t able to appreciate the depth of what’s involved in this business of “having a relationship”. He didn’t focus on the one-on-one aspect of existence, that’s expressed in the word “you”. Instead he wrote about “being-in-the-world” in general – and it was all too easy for his readers to mistake this for the usual “subjective” viewpoint of the mind in relation to the object-world.

Apeiron objected to my focusing on personal, one-on-one relationships. His objections make sense, but only so long as we’re operating within the usual abstract mental space occupied by theorists and philosophers. But I don’t believe what’s fundamental in existence can be seen within that space. You have to be here, it won’t do to keep on imagining the world from outside. You have to work from the standpoint of what’s fundamental to your own existence... and for me that means one-on-one, personal connections.
 
  • #189


ConradDJ said:
I think, if we want to understand how human consciousness evolved, or how the physical universe evolved, we have to find ways to stop taking so much for granted, specifically about our relationships, and our ability to communicate.


Here’s a link to another thread that didn’t go very far, but tried to open up the question –

https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=334249"

Also, in case anyone is interested in what this approach could possibly have to do with physics, here are a couple more links to old threads. Essentially I’m taking “measurement” in quantum theory as equivalent to “communication”. The idea is that we take it for granted that physical communication just means “data transfer” between systems – despite the fact that data is never just “copied” from one system to another, in physical interaction -- any more than data gets physically copied from one person’s brain to another’s. In both cases we’ve hardly begun to understand what sort of environment of real-time relationships can actually support defining and communicating information between different systems with different points of view.

https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=314441"

https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=332292"
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #190


Conrad, I think what you're really looking for is life experience, not philosophy. I don't know how old you or what your background is, but it seems that you don't need words and ideas - you need raw experience.

Whitehead did not assert, and nor have I asserted, that subject and object are the same thing. Rather, they are alternating dual aspects of each actual thing. Whitehead's "concrescence" is the process by which each actual entity becomes actual, starting from a subject, "prehending" the universe (a generalized term for perception), and then making a choice as to how to manifest objectively based on the sum total of prehensions. Whitehead's scheme is actually much more complicated than this, involving also "eternal objects" (Platonic forms essentially) as well, but what I've wrote captures the essence.

As such, the universe is nothing more than the sum total of each actual entity oscillating from subject to object in an eternal cycle of prehension, objectification, perishing of subjectivity and then revival again. It starts very simple but complexifies through the combination of actual entities at various levels.

Whitehead explicitly disavowed Leibniz's windowless monads and, instead, posited fully windowed monads. Actual entities are akin to Leibniz's monads but each actual entity is fully interconnected and interdependent with literally every other actual entity in the universe because it is part of the causal fabric that constitutes the universe. Leibniz's system was rather strange and required positing an omniscient God to coordinate monads in a "preestablished harmony." This is hardly an explanation of anything because it necessarily raises the question: where did God come from? Plausibility is much enhanced if we posit the brute facts of our system as being very simple, rather than a priori complex, leading to complexity through reasonably inferred processes.

We are indeed isolated minds in terms of not KNOWING anything other than our own experience, our own minds, but we can through reasonable inference know other minds - and other minds include literally everything in the universe. As we expand our conception and perception of self, we can come to know the entire universe.
 
  • #191


Just simply, can this particular interpretation of Daesin or authenticity be authentically explained? Is there an awareness of authenticity that isn't inauthentic?

Can it communicate authentically? For instance, can it communicate without an inauthentic awareness of itself, or further, the existence of others?

I’ll quote Apeiron, too, from another thread, but mentioned in relation to this one, in case that helps.
apeiron said:
Langauge clearly objectifies the subject, the doer, along with the doings and the done-to (the verbs and the objects). It already lifts us out of any local particular notion of the subject, the active agent, the effective cause, and forces us into a generic or objective stance where we are just an example of such a locus of agency, the cause that produces the effects.

Although, I would qualify that position.
 
Last edited:
  • #192


fuzzyfelt said:
Is there an awareness of authenticity that isn't inauthentic?

Can it communicate authentically? For instance, can it communicate without an inauthentic awareness of itself, or further, the existence of others?


No. I think the most important thing to understand about authenticity (in Heidegger's sense) is that it can't do without inauthenticity. The point is not to get rid of inauthenticity.

As Apeiron says, inauthenticity -- the ability to imagine the world from no perspective in particular, to "see" a world that goes far beyond the actual "here and now" -- is fundamental to language and to being human. I would say, it's what most radically distinguishes human "consciousness" from the kinds of awareness other animals have.

If you want a "pure" authenticity (or the state of "no-mind", that JDStupi discussed) – a kind of awareness that's fully in the present moment – just imagine how a cat or a dog sees the world.

The thing is, it can be very difficult for us to find our way back into a point of view that's truly our own. And to me, this doesn't involve undoing the inauthentic viewpoint or escaping from it, back to something like the zen ideal of "no mind". It is important to be able to disengage, to stop the self-talk in your head, to come back into the present moment -- because that's the only place we're really connected with the world and with other people. But for me the point is not to leave behind everything we've evolved in our heads, but to bring it and use it to re-engage, in our relationships.

So in physics, we certainly don’t want to leave behind everything we’ve learned about the world from an objective viewpoint. But I think in order to understand what’s going on in the physical world, we also have to see the world “from the standpoint of the observer” – i.e. from the standpoint each of us actually has, in the moment. This is something physics has only been able to do to a very limited extent – e.g. in Carlo Rovell’s “http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9609002v2" .”


 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #193


I have a couple of comments on Apeiron’s note in the Vygotsky thread, mentioned above –
apeiron said:
... the inauthentic view seems in fact fundamental to humans in this regard. Langauge clearly objectifies the subject, the doer, along with the doings and the done-to (the verbs and the objects). It already lifts us out of any local particular notion of the subject, the active agent, the effective cause, and forces us into a generic or objective stance where we are just an example of such a locus of agency, the cause that produces the effects.

The open question is whether animals also have some kind of proto-objectification and cause and effect thinking wired in.


Yes, certainly the brains of other animals have built-in neural “hardware” that enables them to identify and track relevant “objects” out in the world. If you think about how difficult it is to get a computer to do this effectively, you know that this involves many very sophisticated, very complex processing systems.

Human language is a separate “software” system that makes use of this animal hardware. It’s “software” in the sense that it gets “installed” in our brains from outside as we learn to communicate with others. And it’s this that gives us that “inauthentic” ability to “see” the world from no point of view in particular, to keep track of people and things even when we don’t see them for days or years... even to make pictures in our heads of things of things no one will ever see.

But Apeiron says “language clearly objectifies the subject, the doer”... I would rather say, written language does this. In purely oral cultures there is much less of a sense of things as “objects” just existing in themselves with certain characteristics. There is much more of a sense of things as “agents”, “doers” that behave in certain ways.

In pre-literate culture there is a kind of built-in balance between authentic and inauthentic – and thinking about this is a good way of seeing how these two aspects of human awareness work together. Langauge allows us to “step back” out of our own immediate experience, but in a purely oral culture, language only exists in “real time” relationships, in the moment. Talking is “doing” something with other people, expressing oneself from one’s own point of view, much more than it is just a description of reality. And telling stories is a much more basic function of language than arguing about objective truth.

In our culture, which has been more and more shaped by written language over some 2,500 years, the objectifying, “representational” function of language becomes more dominant, particularly in the intellectual sphere. Some even claim that making statements about reality is the function of language, or at least the most important one. And only in a literate culture is it conceivable that the inauthentic, “objective” viewpoint on the world is the only one worth considering.

Obviously I’m not saying there’s anything wrong with literacy, any more than with objectivity. But I would say that our culture, and above all our academic culture, has lost the balance between authenticity and inauthenticity that was a given throughout most of human evolution.
 
  • #194


ConradDJ said:
But Apeiron says “language clearly objectifies the subject, the doer”... I would rather say, written language does this. In purely oral cultures there is much less of a sense of things as “objects” just existing in themselves with certain characteristics. There is much more of a sense of things as “agents”, “doers” that behave in certain ways.

I certainly agree about that. Luria classic study of Uzbeks in transition from an oral to literary culture illustrates your point. Also Walter Ong's more recent work - http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Orality
 
  • #195


ConradDJ said:
No. I think the most important thing to understand about authenticity (in Heidegger's sense) is that it can't do without inauthenticity. The point is not to get rid of inauthenticity.

I understand both are required here, so then the response to Whitehead’s matrix of interpenetration of the two perhaps was about the "from outside" view being considered too priviledged?

ConradDJ said:
To my mind, though, these attempts don’t really take the “standpoint of the individual” seriously enough. They end up talking about “mind” or “apperception” as something going on out there in the real world of objects. That is, these philosophies all live in that abstract mental space in which we envision the world “from outside”, as if we weren’t actually there.
...The thing is, it can be very difficult for us to find our way back into a point of view that's truly our own.

Rather, the idea called for here may instead privilege subjectivity or authenticity?

ConradDJ said:
I would rather say, written language does this.

Derrida disagrees with the "devaluation of writing".

"In the application of this ensemble of rules and historical perspective, one observation about the "devaluation of writing," proved crucial for all of Derrida works: the devaluation of writing is an ancestral bias that was born with Western civilization itself, and remains crucial in modern culture, including science.[5] "


http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Deconstruction

Derrida’s arguments against the devaluation of writing includes the idea that writing makes processes more apparent. Amongst things he mentions, too, is the division of self during inner dialogue, into speaker and listener.

He “interiorly” considers the structure of such concepts and “exteriorly” writes of uncovering historic dissimulation.
‘In a 1972 he remarked the historical aspect of deconstruction:[4]
To "deconstruct" philosophy [...] would be to think – in the most faithful, interior way – the structured genealogy of philosophy's concepts, but at the same time to determine – from a certain exterior [...] – what this history has been able to dissimulate or forbid [...] By means of this simultaneously faithful and violent circulation between the inside and the outside of philosophy [...a] putting into question the meaning of Being as presence.’It is also this sort of approach to things like subjectivity and the time of “presence” that I think is quite balanced. I enjoy considerations of boundaries and "trace".
 
Last edited:
  • #196


fuzzyfelt said:
I understand both are required here, so then the response to Whitehead’s matrix of interpenetration of the two perhaps was about the "from outside" view being considered too privileged?

...Rather, the idea called for here may instead privilege subjectivity or authenticity?


Well, yes... but both the authentic and inauthentic viewpoints can be “privileged”, in very different ways. On the inauthentic side there’s everything from bigoted dogmatism to the open, self-critical objectivity of science, which deserves to be privileged. Authenticity can’t make the same kind of claim to being right about things. It’s “privileged” only in that it’s the point of view we all start from and end with.

The key point is that both are required, as you say, but the value of both can only be appreciated from the authentic viewpoint. Objectivity wants to move beyond “subjective appearances” to uncover the reality of things. All well and good. But I think when we take that distanced mental perspective that envisions the world as Whitehead does, what’s most important about our connectedness becomes invisible. We get abstract notions about how things connect. Whitehead’s “apperception” is modeled on sense-perception. Tam refers to Ken Wilbur’s metaphysics based on the notion of things being parts of other things. We can probably all agree that “interdependence” is a basic aspect of the world. Apeiron looks to theoretical biology and general systems theory as a guide to describing what this means.

But I think it’s only when we take seriously our own personal point of view on the world, as we live it moment to moment, that we can begin to see what it means to be in relationships, always in the context of other relationships. This was the main point of Being and Time, that the environing structure of “being-here” is different from any objective description of “what’s there” in the world. The “here and now” in which existence happens is very different from the space and time of world-history seen “from outside”. And the basic failing of the inauthentic view is that it doesn’t see this difference at all.

So authentically, we can appreciate what we learn from an objective standpoint about our shared reality. But the kind of philosophy that imagines the world from no point of view in particular misses what’s fundamental. It describes the world of connections “from outside” and talks about the relationships between things from the standpoint of a third party. It can’t see the side of the world that consists in points of view communicating with other points of view, each in its own context... even though that’s all any of us have ever actually experienced.
 
  • #197


fuzzyfelt said:
Derrida disagrees with the "devaluation of writing"...

Derrida’s arguments against the devaluation of writing includes the idea that writing makes processes more apparent. Amongst things he mentions, too, is the division of self during inner dialogue, into speaker and listener.


This links to the part of the Wikipedia page that’s most relevant –
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Deconstruction#Of_Grammatology

Thanks for pointing this out. I find Derrida’s language hard to tolerate, so I haven’t spent much time on his work. It seems that Heidegger’s main influence, in French philosophy at least, was to encourage a rhetorical style that feels to me deliberately obscure. But this is very relevant to the discussion...

I’m sorry, though, I have to be at work early this AM, so I’ll have to respond tomorrow.
 
  • #198


From http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Deconstruction#Of_Grammatology"

Derrida argues that people have historically understood speech as the primary mode of language and understood writing as an inferior derivative of speech.​

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Orality" is that on the contrary, in our literate culture it’s difficult to appreciate the nature of speech, since our ways of imagining the world have been formed over the centuries in writing. And it’s oral culture that’s often dismissed as primitive and inferior.

Derrida argues that speech is historically equated with logos, meaning thought, and associated with the presence of the speaker to the listener. It is as if the speaker thinks out loud and the listener hears what the speaker is thinking and if there is any confusion then the speaker's presence allows them to qualify the meaning of a previous statement. Derrida argues that by understanding speech as thought language "effaces itself." Langauge itself is forgotten. The signified meaning of speech is so immediately understood that it is easy to forget that there are linguistic signifiers involved - but these signifiers are the spoken sounds (phonemes) and written marks (graphemes) that actually comprise language.​

Heidegger often emphasizes the opposite, in relation to “language”. That is, what’s essential in language has to do not with the “signifiers” but with the kind of relationship to the world and to other people that talking makes possible. Everything humans do and feel is bound up in this kind of communicative relationship, which goes far beyond the use of words and sentences.

This thought that something very basic to existence is being taken for granted and “forgotten” is very much in Heidegger’s vein. But for me, this basic thing that’s taken for granted has to do with the nature of human relationships. For Derrida, it seems to be the technology of “signifying”, or “language” in the narrow sense:

The consideration of language as writing leads inescapably to the insight that language is a system of signs. As a system of signs the signifiers are present but the signification can only be inferred. There is effectively an act of translation involved in extracting a signification from the signifiers of language. This act of translation is so habitual to language users that they must step back from their experience of using language in order to fully realize its operation...

The insight that language is a system of signs, most obvious in the consideration of language as writing, leads Derrida to state that "everything [...] gathered under the name of language is beginning to let itself be transferred to [...] the name of writing."​

So Derrida takes “language” in such a narrow sense that it almost excludes talking, as a “naive” derivative of writing. Of course he can’t mean that talking evolved out of writing. But he thinks that only writing brings out what’s essential in language.

This feels to me like an extreme of the Cartesian viewpoint – the intellect enclosed in its own world, recognizing there’s no way of connecting with any world except the one it constructs itself. But at least it can be aware of the technology it uses.

Naturally such a distanced intellectual perspective prefers writing, i.e. objectified language. It takes the representing / signifying function of language as essential, and ignores the function of letting people be in touch with each other, as something merely illusory.

It’s true that the only world we actually experience is the world each of us builds “in our own heads”. It’s true that when we talk, we’re only imagining there’s someone out there who’s listening and understanding. And when we listen, we’re only imagining we understand what another person thinks or feels. But this kind of mutual imagining is what relationships are made of, and it’s what’s basic to the kind of “consciousness” we humans evolve.

I think human language began with the emergence of this kind of relationship, that we all learn to participate in when we’re very young, and from then on take for granted. As compared to this, the aspect of language that appears in writing is highly derivative, very distanced, “inauthentic” – but certainly not “inferior”.

For a great many purposes, including science and philosophy, writing is indispensable. Derrida is right, that written language in particular is what makes self-reflection possible. But self-reflection isn’t all there is to existence. Nearly all of what makes us human had evolved long before writing.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #199


I’m rushing and I’m unlikely to account for Derrida well in a post, and even less likely to at the moment, but I’ll make a quick attempt.
ConradDJ said:
So Derrida takes “language” in such a narrow sense that it almost excludes talking, as a “naive” derivative of writing. Of course he can’t mean that talking evolved out of writing. But he thinks that only writing brings out what’s essential in language...
That is not my understanding. Spivak argued along these lines. Derrida's aim was to treat both writting and speech similarly.

An asymmetric reversal, with one side privileged at the expense of the other, would be at odds with Derrida’s anti-totalitarian stance. Derrida’s aim was to destroy the opposition in the relationship, not reverse it. An example of destroying opposition is that both terms “master” and “slave” require the other for their definition, enslaving the term “master” (from ‘The Restricted to General Economy’).

He treated speech and writing similarly, as “writing” in this case is about a signifier for as long as there has been one (including prehistory), which (imperfectly) points back to a signified, and so includes speech. Speech equally requires “reading” and interpretation.

More, this idea of “writing"/iterability/inscription/textuality, not only includes speech but all the philosophical system (Reilly, 2005), or all experience (Coward, 1990). And so, along these lines, Derrida is looking from inside experience's relationships, rewriting categories and concepts.

Metaphorically or not, Derrida reads between these historical dichotomies of reason/philosophy/experience in ever changing con-texts, within the relationships between these oppositions, and in uncovering what is present but unsaid/absent (“a chain of signification becomes the trace of presence-absence”) he, at the same time, reconstructs.

I don’t know how to link to areas on a wiki page, but there is a heading here called Heideggerian Dasein and Derridian Trace.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Trace_(deconstruction )

Thanks for the more specific link before, but perhaps other parts of the page introduce some of the related ideas more simply. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Deconstruction

It may be some time before I can post again.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #200


PhizzicsPhan said:
Conrad, again, you're taken with Heidegger's supposed sweeping away of traditional philosophy. You think "qualia" is some scientistic term to distract from authentic experience.

Qualia ARE authentic experience. Qualia are subjectivity. Qualia are mind.

Everything you do is the flux and flex of qualia. You are qualia. Your wife IS qualia.

These are all terms for exactly the same thing.

Reality, as you have defined it, is a construct of complex collections of qualia - human minds, in this case. Reality is, thus, dependent on the deeper reality of what you have called Existence. So Existence is what needs to be explained in any decent ontology.

Forgive me for barging in and quoting a post from some pages back. Great thread, but I believe you here exhibit most clearly what has been strangely unpalatable to me in much of your argumentation. I believe it is the style of your inquiry. I would characterize is as the style of ontology that wants to go all the way down, that is not ready to grant any thing an irreducible ontic consistency. It needs to be qualia all the way down, or turtles, or objects, or systems. What is strange is that you seem to admire Whitehead. With Whitehead we might think of any theorizing we do here as devising "lures for feelings" that will direct us toward the world once again, on new trajectories towards coming actuality. The engineering of our abstractions matters. When we think in the style of academic ontology we're often dragged down the slopes because for our "systems" to be universally arguable above others we seek out the safe haven of the mythical "smallest" (or biggest, or universal mode of transformation). If I have understood you correctly you wish to argue for the ontic primacy of qualia as congregating into events. Fair enough, but where does that lead us when we wish to interrogate the ontic consistency of human minding for instance? I would argue that there is really not much use to posit a theory of the smallest things when we, in everyday experience AND from what the sciences explicate as being in our world, encounter so many things that have irreducibly different ontic consistencies. The ontic consistency of human minds, the weird self-knowing reality, that all these human shaped bodies seem to carry around should perhaps be first and foremost treated as a unique "element" in the universe. We routinely observe other observers that have an I to talk about and a who (we acknowledge this when we name)t hat may compel our thought. Not only that, the thinking of kinds activated by the talk of "elements" breaks down when we approach observers, because they are never actually regular! Finding a mind in nature might be like finding a gem of which there exists no other instance in the universe. Isn't that enough to have us thinking already, to compel us to inquire into the specificities of these unique realities? Or take any "kind" that the sciences make available for us to think and talk with. Why would we go and reduce them to fit a systematic onto-story when their specificities are already there, excessively compelling thought that doesn't inevitably lead us down to final principles, the final stuff of the universe, mechanisms of becoming etc.

tl;dr. Could we not for every level of organization be ready to accept a certain mode of existence and rather ask what it does in the world, instead of trying to build these reductive onto-stories?
 

Similar threads

Back
Top