vanesch
Staff Emeritus
Science Advisor
Gold Member
- 5,109
- 20
Terra Incognita said:The books give a partial solution to construct the Hamiltonian operator (the specific time evolution) starting from a classical Hamiltonian. These are the following equations you gave in the post # 38:
a) {A’,B’}_classical= [A,B]_quantum/i hbar.
b) replace the scalar A’ by the operator A, the scalar B’ by the operator B in the scalar Hamiltonian of classical mechanics.
This is just a method to construct the hamiltonian of QM (specific to QM) and not the way to define the Liouville operator of CSM (specific to CSM).
I can understand one wants to mold classical statistical mechanics into a framework using a hilbert space. But that, to me, is not a quantum theory per se. The classical link between momentum, position and energy (h(p,q)) on one hand, and the link between energy and time evolution (Schroedinger equation) on the other hand, are, I think, fundamental. So I don't know if you learn much from this mimickry, even if formally (by forcing the liouville equation to work out) you can make things work. I mean: it is not because we were able to map a classical phase space dynamics, given by the liouville equation, onto a hilbert state mechanism, that we have anything like a quantum theory, do we ? I'm sure that with some effort I'm able to map hydrodynamical problems also on a Hilbert space formulation. But does that give my quantum hydrodynamics then ? Or maybe I'm missing the whole point of this exercise then...
Your error: you assume that the time evolution of the state is given by the hamiltonian obtained by the process to get the quantum hamiltonian starting from the classical hamiltonian. The time evolution operators evolutions are specific to the theories.
I would take that as very very fundamental in a quantum theory... That there is a quantity (energy) which is measurable (and hence a classical function of q and p), and which corresponds to the time evolution.
Of course you can impose just ANY time evolution in a hilbert space, by just any mechanism, and then call the derivative to time the action of an operator, which is called a "hamiltonian". But are we still doing quantum theory here, or just defining mathematical operators in a hilbert space setting ?
In that case, what is this formal game going to learn us about an interpretative issue in quantum theory ?
I am applying quantum probabilities (an observable and a state define a probability law) and not the specificities of the time evolution that are theory dependant.
I have in both theories, expressed with quantum probabilities, the problem of the eingenbasis selection. This is why I think we can use them to understand better decoherence and the preferred basis problems (separation of general problems for theory dependant problems).
I don't understand this. The (p,q) basis is clearly preferred, no ? You have set up everything so that 1) |psi|^2 in that basis is the phase space density and 2) that this density evolves according to the Liouville equation. In what other basis would you ever like to work then ? What does it even MEAN, to be in a |p1,q1> + |p2,q2> state ? To what does this state correspond ?
Do you really think we need a classical “human” (or a machine) to acknowledge the measurement results?
Yes, exactly for the reason you asked in the beginning of this thread. You can consider ALL interactions as given by unitary evolution. So your voltmeter and everything just ends up entangled with whatever it was measuring (that's given by the interaction hamiltonian).
For instance, consider a computer that is counting photoelectric pulses and calculates a correlation. Well, the computer will end up entangled in several terms, and in each of the terms, it will have calculated a different correlation. You will end up with something like:
|computercorr=0.8>|++>|-->|-->|-+>|++> + |computercorr=0.6>|++>|-->|-->|+->|-+> +
|computercorr=0.8>|-->|-+>|++>|-->|++> +
...
That's what you get out of all the interaction hamiltonians between the photonstates and the photodetectors, the counting modules, and the electronics of the computer. The computer has no need to be in only ONE of these states. But clearly, when you LOOK and OBSERVE the computer screen, you only see one answer. That means that the bodystate YOU are consciously aware of, must be in a product state with only ONE state of the computer screen. But as long as you do not look, that computer, its screen and everything else can happily be in an entangled state as above. And to do that, you don't need any preferred basis. The hamiltonians, specifying a unitary evolution operator, are sufficient, and their action is of course independent of the basis in which you apply them.
Computers not being aware of a classical world, they don't mind being in entangled states, so from the point of view of a computer, there's no problem for it to have at the same time a result which is corr = 0.8, corr = 0.2 and 0.1 in different terms. It's just when YOU look at it that you only see one of those results. But that's more something about YOU than about the computer. So the Born rule only applies to YOUR experiences.
(in the sense a voltmeter give a voltage if we, human, are look or not at this voltmeter).
Well, that's not true in a MWI. The voltmeter does not give one voltage on its reading. It gives all possible results, in entangled states. We only seem to observe one of them. But only when we look. Crazy, no ? :-)
This is a matter of words. What is important for the measurement, to acknowledge it or to know if one place a detector (or a question) after the plate, one will see the results implied by the plate (in this case the “measurement”)?
Well, we say that the detector will see the result implied by the plate in one term, and will see another result in another term.
You seem to assume that you need interaction with the environment in order to get a measurement. I do not see why we need such interaction (hence the double slit example with the reflecting plate).
In other words, I can imagine a measurement without any interaction (in the sense negligible during the considered time), just by saying that the detector records the results. The fact that someone may or may not read the results of the detector (now, 10 years later or never) does not change the results.
Well, that's the big difference between a collapse model and a relative state interpretation. In a relative state interpretation, the detector has obtained all the possible results at the same time. In some terms, the detector has clicked, and in other terms, that same detector, at the same time and place, didn't click. It is only when you look at it that you know in what term you are (and not even what "really happened to the detector"). That's the whole point of relative state views.
In a collapse model of course, there IS - as you say - an outcome, whether you look at it or not. And then there needs to be a transistion, through a Born rule. And there needs to be an objective choice of basis. And then, indeed, you have the problem of whatever is an observer, or not, and what is an environment, or not. As long as there is no clear physical dynamics that gives an answer to that, I find these problems so unsurmountable that I prefer a relative-state view in which EVERYTHING HAPPENS, and in which I only consciously experience ONE alternative. And then of course you see the crucial role of me as an observer, and the naturalness of dividing the universe into "my body" and "the rest". This implies (and allows) quantum theory to be valid "all the way up" until I have to make my personal choice as to what term to pick.
And *as long as you do that* and apply the unitary evolution to all interactions, there is no basis problem to be solved (but there is also no definite result obtained) for any interaction that is not a subjective observation by myself. And for THOSE subjective observations, I'd think that using splits that are based upon myself versus the rest of the universe are allowed and rather natural.
Now, I know that this sounds crazy - and probably it is. But it is A POSSIBILITY. And we don't have any clear physical indication of where this unitary evolution fails. Maybe gravity will do so. Maybe not. As long as there is no clear model of how it does so, I take it that what we know of our fundamental laws (unitary evolution) is valid everywhere.
cheers,
Patrick.