I What is the current perspective on quantum interpretation?

  • #51
vanhees71 said:
The problem with the debates about interpretation, which is usually a rather philosophical topic
vanhees71 said:
Well, I think interpretation of QT is much more religion than philosophy
So which is it?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
Well, I guess both ;-)).
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #53
vanhees71 said:
Well, I guess both ;-)).
Your answer is neither philosophy nor religion. It's politics. :oldbiggrin:
 
  • Haha
Likes DennisN, bhobba and vanhees71
  • #54
So it's far from being science. SCNR.
 
  • #55
MathematicalPhysicist said:
if you have someone arguing for A and the other one for ~A (negation of A), how can you have a third option?!

Because arguments are rarely the A, not A type. They are something like I believe everyone needs a guaranteed income of at least $20,000 a year (statement A). The opposition is nobody should have a guaranteed income. The not A position is a guaranteed income of less than $20,000, or no guaranteed income. A compromise position could be a guaranteed income of $10,000 py which satisfies neither position, but both sides may be able to live with it.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Buzz Bloom
  • #56
bhobba said:
Because arguments are rarely the A, not A type. They are something like I believe everyone needs a guaranteed income of at least $20,000 a year (statement A). The opposition is nobody should have a guaranteed income. The not A position is a guaranteed income of less than $20,000, or no guaranteed income. A compromise position could be a guaranteed income of $10,000 py which satisfies neither position, but both sides may be able to live with it.

Thanks
Bill
Well, how do you know that those type of arguments are rare? you just gave one example of an argument which this is not the case.
 
  • #57
MathematicalPhysicist said:
Well, how do you know that those type of arguments are rare? you just gave one example of an argument which this is not the case.

You got me there. Just from everyday experience, but we all know how that often collapses when looked at carefully. Actually that is just experience as well - caught in a logical loop.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #58
bhobba said:
You got me there. Just from everyday experience, but we all know how that often collapses when looked at carefully. Actually that is just experience as well - caught in a logical loop.

Thanks
Bill
You've caught in a LOOP, and you can't get out of it...

LOOP QG. (used to be my username, but I got outside the LOOP, into another loop).
 
  • Haha
Likes bhobba
  • #59
vanhees71 said:
The problem with the debates about interpretation, ..., is that philosophers tend to use fuzzy definitions of their words, particularly the ones we discuss here (locality and reality among them).
I can fullly share the frustration over the many pointless debates involving the word "reality" provoked both by philosophers (for example Yuval Noah Harari, officially an historician) and physicists alike. There are languages with different words for different aspects of it, for example German has Realität (from res=thing/stuff), Wirklichkeit (from wirken=effect), and Gegebenheit (from gegeben=given). But even those different words won't help much in the end.

Not sure whether it is the fault of philosophers that quantum physics is local and nonlocal at the same time, and that capturing the sense in which it is nonlocal is even more challenging than capturing the sense in which it is local. I think that the word "local" has a sufficiently specific meaning (which is the same in different laguages). Still, it can apply to many different things and situations with meaning slightly adapted to the different contexts.

Thanks for repeating and expanding on the microcausality principle. I have now read a bit about it. Looks like properties of the vacuum state are important too for the consequences related to locality that you gave. Well, I guess this is just related to the fact that the background (like a solid crystal, or a curved spacetime) can affect locality too.

Have you seen my request to be more specific about in which paper exactly Einstein introduced the notion of "inseparability"?
 
  • #60
I'd not use the word "reality" in these debates anymore, because it has practically no clear meaning anymore. For me what's "real" is what physicists measure in the lab, and all I need to provide as a theoretical physicist is to explain how the formalism (Hilbert space, observable algebras, statstical operators,...) describes what can be measured and what one expects to find in the lab.

Concerning locality it's clear that local relativistic QFTs are local (that's why they are called local), and this has a clear mathematical meaning within the formalism: local field operators that describe observables must commute at space like distances with the Hamiltonian density (which itself is also a local field operator, i.e., built out of the field operators and their derivatives at one space-time point). That's also known as the microcausality condition, because it guaranties causality in the sense of the Minkowski space-time structure, particularly that there cannot be within such a theory any causal connection between space-like separated measurements. This principle is pretty strong and leads, together with the boundedness of the Hamiltonian from below, to pretty general conclusions like the spin-statistics connection (half-integer spin fields describe fermions; integer-spin fields bosons), the CPT symmetry, and the linked-cluster principle and unitarity of the S-matrix.

The paper I have in mind is Einstein's own writing about the EPR paradox. In contradistinction to this unfortunately very famous EPR paper it's a masterpiece in scientific prose, as everything Einstein wrote. Recently somebody posted a link to an English translation somewhere here on Physics Forums, but I cannot find it anymore. Here's the original citation:

A. Einstein, Quantenmechanik und Wirklichkeit, Dialectica 2,
320 (1948),
https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1746-8361.1948.tb00704.x

I'm not sure, whether Einstein called it "inseparability" explicitly in this work, but that's what he describes in detail, namely the strong correlations of far-distant properties of an extended quantum system, like two photons which may be registered at very far distant places, being completely unpolarized but still showing 100% correlations of their polarization states.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #61
vanhees71 said:
It is utmost important to keep in mind that correlations and causal connections are two different things (not only in the context of quantum theory).

The microcausality principle says ... That implies that there are no faster-than light interactions and thus no faster-than light causal effects.
But microcausality is simply a bad, misleading name. It is defined as the non-existence of correlations. Once QT (and QFT as well) in the minimal interpretation do not make claims about causality at all, to name this property "microcausality" is simply the wrong word.
vanhees71 said:
The cause for the correlations in all such cases is not due to the one or the other measurements, which can be space-like separated and thus cannot causally influence one another within local relativistic QFT, and still you observe the correlations due to entanglement predicted by this theory. ... Within this theory it's also clear that the correlations between the measured polarization observables is due to the preperation of the photon pairs [emph. mine]
And such reasoning is the result of such misleading names. You simply cannot know if the measurements can causally influence the other measurements because the minimal interpretation makes no claims about causality.
vanhees71 said:
With this "minimal interpretation" of the quantum state, i.e., that it describes (and only describes!) the statistical properties of measurement outcomes when measuring observables of the prepared the system, there is no contradiction between microcausality and the observed correlations between space-like separated measurements on an entangled system.
No. If you introduce notions of causality into the minimal interpretation, you introduce something which in itself is sufficient to prove the Bell inequalities. Essentially Reichenbach's principle of common cause is sufficient for this. But in your argument above (my emphasis) you use causality in a form which presupposes the common cause principle.
 
  • #62
Sunil said:
But microcausality is simply a bad, misleading name. It is defined as the non-existence of correlations. Once QT (and QFT as well) in the minimal interpretation do not make claims about causality at all, to name this property "microcausality" is simply the wrong word.

Microcausality is usually defined to be spacelike observables commuting (field operators commuting or anti-commuting), and it is consistent with the existence of correlations that violate the Bell inequality. So it may be the misleadingly named, but it isn't the non-existence of correlations.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #63
Why is "microcausality" a misnomer? To the contrary, it precisely names the principle by its purpose, and of course as any physical theory also relativistic QFT assumes causality. If there were no causality there'd be no natural laws and natural science wouldn't exist. You have to distinguish between causal effects and correlations. Entanglement describes correlations, and it's of course fully consistent with the causality built into local relativistic QFT.
 
  • #64
atyy said:
Microcausality is usually defined to be spacelike observables commuting (field operators commuting or anti-commuting), and it is consistent with the existence of correlations that violate the Bell inequality. So it may be the misleadingly named, but it isn't the non-existence of correlations.
It is the non-existence of all correlations which would allow to send signals.
vanhees71 said:
Why is "microcausality" a misnomer? To the contrary, it precisely names the principle by its purpose,
This would be not yet a contradiction, given that the purpose could have been to mislead too.
vanhees71 said:
and of course as any physical theory also relativistic QFT assumes causality.
No. If it would assume causality in its classical meaning, including Reichenbach's common cause principle, then it would allow to prove Bell's theorem.
vanhees71 said:
If there were no causality there'd be no natural laws and natural science wouldn't exist.
Wrong. Natural laws could exist without causality, and correlations can exist without causality too. Of course, it does not make any sense to reject such fundamental principles like realism and causality. Even more logic (don't forget that there have been even proposals for some "quantum logic"). But that does not mean that doing such nonsense would be impossible. It is, instead, what the mainstream is doing right now.
vanhees71 said:
You have to distinguish between causal effects and correlations. Entanglement describes correlations, and it's of course fully consistent with the causality built into local relativistic QFT.
No. Causality is sufficient to prove the Bell inequality. So either you live without causality, or you reduce it to something which can be named "causality" only by positivists (signal "causality"), which does not even have a common cause principle.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #65
Due to the validity of the microcausality constraint in local relativistic QFTs the correlations described by entanglement without such a theory cannot be due to faster-than-light and thus acausal signaling. The correlations are inherent the state and the state has been prepared including these correlations. It's clear that these correlations are not describable by a deterministic local hidden-variable theory and in that sense not classical.
 
  • #66
vanhees71 said:
It's clear that these correlations are not describable by a deterministic local hidden-variable theory and in that sense not classical.
A nice example of how misleading the wording today is. There is, first, the "local", which means "Einstein-causal". A local (in the usual sense) theory with a limiting speed faster than light would have to be named "nonlocal".

But that's not the only funny thing. The other one is that "in that sense" Newtonian gravity would be not classical too.

Both don't seem accidental. They have a similar consequence - a quite classical, common sense compatible interpretation of modern physics (say, dBB combined with a preferred frame) would have to be named "non-local" and "non-classical".
vanhees71 said:
Due to the validity of the microcausality constraint in local relativistic QFTs the correlations described by entanglement without such a theory cannot be due to faster-than-light and thus acausal signaling.
The logic of this justification is reversed. If some condition forbids some "acausal" (non-Einstein causal) influence (FTL signaling), but does not forbid another "acausal" (non-Einstein-causal) influence (BI violations), it cannot be named "causality".

The logic "faster than light and thus acausal" is wrong too, it ignores classical causality which allows faster than light causal influences as long as they don't causally influence the past (in preferred absolute time).

Given that an essential part of quantum interpretations require a preferred frame in a relativistic context (dBB, Nelson, Caticha, all the collapse interpretations), I would recommend to use a language which does not exclude such interpretations at least in this subforum.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #67
Again: Local relativistic QFTs are a QT (afaik the only type we have) which is consistent with Einstein causality by implementing the microcausality constraints between any local observable with the Hamiltonian density. As a QT it's of course not a local deterministic theory but implies, as any QT, the probabilistic (and only probabilistic) meaning of quantum states, and thus there is no contradiction between long-ranged correlations described by entanglement and Einstein causality though of course it is incompatible with the predictions of local deterministic HV theories, as shown by Bell.
 
  • #68
vanhees71 said:
Again: Local relativistic QFTs are a QT (afaik the only type we have) which is consistent with Einstein causality by implementing the microcausality constraints between any local observable with the Hamiltonian density. As a QT it's of course not a local deterministic theory but implies, as any QT, the probabilistic (and only probabilistic) meaning of quantum states, and thus there is no contradiction between long-ranged correlations described by entanglement and Einstein causality though of course it is incompatible with the predictions of local deterministic HV theories, as shown by Bell.

To define your terms - if we interpret the quantum state as real, and state reduction or collapse to be physical, is that consistent with what you call "Einstein causality"?
 
  • #69
I don't know, what real means.

The state, described by the statistical operator, provides probalities and nothing else than probabilities. There's no other nebulous meaning than predicting the probabilities for the outcome of measurements.

There cannot be a collapse as a physical process in local relativistic QFT, because this contradicts the impossibility for faster-than-light signals, implied by the validity of the microcausality property of the theory. That's why I think the collapse assumption has to be abandoned, and it is not necessary, because what's the state after a measurement has been done cannot be stated as a general principle anyway but depends on the specific setup of the experiment.
 
  • #70
vanhees71 said:
I don't know, what real means.

The state, described by the statistical operator, provides probalities and nothing else than probabilities. There's no other nebulous meaning than predicting the probabilities for the outcome of measurements.

There cannot be a collapse as a physical process in local relativistic QFT, because this contradicts the impossibility for faster-than-light signals, implied by the validity of the microcausality property of the theory. That's why I think the collapse assumption has to be abandoned, and it is not necessary, because what's the state after a measurement has been done cannot be stated as a general principle anyway but depends on the specific setup of the experiment.

Then your statement is false.

Whether or not collapse is physical, no predictions are changed.

So if relativistic QT is consistent with Einstein causality, then collapse, interpreted physically, is also consistent with Einstein causality.

If collapse, interpreted physically is not consistent with Einstein causality, then relativistic QT is not consistent with Einstein causality.
 
  • #71
vanhees71 said:
Again: Local relativistic QFTs are a QT (afaik the only type we have) which is consistent with Einstein causality by implementing the microcausality constraints between any local observable with the Hamiltonian density. As a QT it's of course not a local deterministic theory but implies, as any QT, the probabilistic (and only probabilistic) meaning of quantum states, and thus there is no contradiction between long-ranged correlations described by entanglement and Einstein causality though of course it is incompatible with the predictions of local deterministic HV theories, as shown by Bell.
The disagreement remains to be one about causality but now shifts toward "Einstein causality".

I insist that to name something "causality" which does not have a principle of common cause is misleading.

Signal "causality" is that weaker notion of causality which is compatible with QFT, but it is not a variant of causality, it is something much weaker, it is only about correlations between what can be produced at some "source" and what can be measured at some "receiver". Instead, a notion of full causality, including a common cause principle, would be sufficient to prove the BI. Thus, to be compatible with QT/QFT, one needs a preferred frame with return to classical causality.
 
  • #72
I don't understand what you mean by causality then. We are talking about relativistic causality, where causal connections cannot be between spacelike separated events. In non-relativistic physics there's no such constraint, and you have usually actions at a distance anyway. So here's also no tension between the collapse postulate and causality.

A causal connection is not the same as correlations of course. Causal connections are always due to a signal in relativistic physics (at least in our standard realizations as local (classical or quantum) field theories). There can be correlations between local observables measured at space-like separated spacetime points due to the state of the system (particularly in the case where a quantum system has entangled far-distantly measured subsystems).
 
  • #73
vanhees71 said:
the probabilistic (and only probabilistic) meaning of quantum states
If the interpretation was probabilistic and only probabilistic, then collapse would be interpreted as update and only update. Denying collapse (by the argument that it violates locality or Schrodinger equation) makes sense only if quantum state is not probabilistic and only probabilistic.
 
  • #74
I think we argue in circles again...

I don't understand, for what I'd need a collapse assumption, which cannot be made in the fundamental formulation of the theory, because what happens with the system in the measurement process depends on the used measurment apparatus and if you need to determine a state after a measurement you have to think about how to get this new state case by case.

The "collapse" is a FAPP description for a very limited type of "measurements", namely von Neumann filter measurements.
 
  • #75
vanhees71 said:
The "collapse" is a FAPP description for a very limited type of "measurements", namely von Neumann filter measurements.
No. Even for general POVM measurements there is a generalized collapse rule
$$|\psi\rangle\to\frac{M_k|\psi\rangle}{|M_k|\psi\rangle|}$$
where ##M_k## are Kraus operators for the POVM
$$\sum_k M_k^{\dagger}M_k=1$$
Recall https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/difference-between-collapse-and-projection.998545/post-6445457 for photon measurement.

The projective "filter" measurements are a special case in which ##M_k## are projectors satisfying ##M_k M_{k'}=M_k\delta_{kk'}##.
 
  • #76
vanhees71 said:
I think we argue in circles again...

I don't understand, for what I'd need a collapse assumption, which cannot be made in the fundamental formulation of the theory, because what happens with the system in the measurement process depends on the used measurment apparatus and if you need to determine a state after a measurement you have to think about how to get this new state case by case.

The "collapse" is a FAPP description for a very limited type of "measurements", namely von Neumann filter measurements.

It's a useful tool to understand what you mean by Einstein causality, ie. to understand whether you mean "classical relativistic causality" or "no superluminal signaling". Quantum theory is not consistent with classical relativistic causality, but it is consistent with no superluminal signaling.

It seems that although you reject classical relativistic causality because of the Bell inequality violations, it seems that you also accept it because of your rejection of physical collapse.

It doesn't make sense to reject collapse as inconsistent with no superluminal signaling, since interpreting the state update as physical collapse is consistent with no superluminal signaling.
 
  • #77
atyy said:
It's a useful tool to understand what you mean by Einstein causality, ie. to understand whether you mean "classical relativistic causality" or "no superluminal signaling". Quantum theory is not consistent with classical relativistic causality, but it is consistent with no superluminal signaling.

It seems that although you reject classical relativistic causality because of the Bell inequality violations, it seems that you also accept it because of your rejection of physical collapse.

It doesn't make sense to reject collapse as inconsistent with no superluminal signaling, since interpreting the state update as physical collapse is consistent with no superluminal signaling.
Can you tell us what "classical relativistic causality" is?
 
  • #78
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand what you mean by causality then. We are talking about relativistic causality, where causal connections cannot be between spacelike separated events.
Of course, causality was part of physics even before 1905, so that it makes no sense to incorporate relativity into the very definition of causality. My understanding of classical causality necessarily includes a principle of common cause: Observed correlations require a causal explanation. Which can be a direct causal connection as well as a correlation caused by some common cause.
In non-relativistic physics there's no such constraint, and you have usually actions at a distance anyway. So here's also no tension between the collapse postulate and causality.
vanhees71 said:
A causal connection is not the same as correlations of course. Causal connections are always due to a signal in relativistic physics (at least in our standard realizations as local (classical or quantum) field theories). There can be correlations between local observables measured at space-like separated spacetime points due to the state of the system (particularly in the case where a quantum system has entangled far-distantly measured subsystems).
So, your "there can be correlations ..." is followed by a "due to", showing that in your notion of causality a correlation also requires some causal explanation. A notion of causality which would say "some correlations can happen without any causal connection" is simply not worth to be named causality.

But if something is sufficient as an explanation of a correlation has a well-defined mathematical meaning. It means that if we control for the common cause C, then A and B become independent again: ##P(A\land B|C) = P(A|C)P(B|C)##. And this is enough to prove the Bell inequalities. And therefore a theory with relativistic causality cannot make the predictions of QT. You have to give up Einstein causality, to replace it by some non-causality misnamed "signal causality".
 
  • #79
atyy said:
It's a useful tool to understand what you mean by Einstein causality, ie. to understand whether you mean "classical relativistic causality" or "no superluminal signaling". Quantum theory is not consistent with classical relativistic causality, but it is consistent with no superluminal signaling.

It seems that although you reject classical relativistic causality because of the Bell inequality violations, it seems that you also accept it because of your rejection of physical collapse.

It doesn't make sense to reject collapse as inconsistent with no superluminal signaling, since interpreting the state update as physical collapse is consistent with no superluminal signaling.
What do you mean by "classical relativistic causality" then? For me causality simply means that two space-like separated events cannot be causally connected and that implies that signals can propagate maximally at the speed of light (i.e., such signals that are mediated by a massless field as the em. field).

Bell inequalities describe however constraints on correlations, and correlations can exist across spacelike separated parts of a system, e.g., the entangled photon pairs used in Bell experiments. Here measurements on far-distant parts show correlations violating Bell's inequalities showing that QT is incompatible with any local determinstic HV theory. The correlations are found also when the registration events of the two photons are spacelike separated. As you admit that local relativistic QFTs exclude faster-than light signalling this implies that within these QFTs it's impossible that the correlations are due to causal effects of one measurement on the other, and this excludes at least a naive collapse assumption: All that changes causally when A registers her photon can only be within the future light cone of this measurment event and thus there cannot be any causal influence on B's measurement result from A's measurement. So there cannot be any collapse in the sense of a dynamical causal physical process.

Note that there arise no contradictions when you assume a kind of "local collapse", i.e., if you just interpret "collapse" as an update of the state description by one of the observers. Say A has measured the polarization of her photon (prepared as one of the usual Bell states of a photon pair) being ##H##. Then she knows that with certainty B must find his photon to be ##V## polarized (i.e., no matter when B measures his photon, i.e., before A's measurement or after A's measurement or even simultaneously or if his measurement event is space-like separated). Of course then ##A## may update her description of the pair to ##|HV \rangle## without changing any of her predictions what B has measured/will measure as compared to the predictions by using the original entangled state. So indeed, within local relativistic QFTs, there's no way to use entanglement for faster-than-light signalling.
 
  • #80
Sunil said:
Of course, causality was part of physics even before 1905, so that it makes no sense to incorporate relativity into the very definition of causality. My understanding of classical causality necessarily includes a principle of common cause: Observed correlations require a causal explanation. Which can be a direct causal connection as well as a correlation caused by some common cause.
In non-relativistic physics there's no such constraint, and you have usually actions at a distance anyway. So here's also no tension between the collapse postulate and causality.

So, your "there can be correlations ..." is followed by a "due to", showing that in your notion of causality a correlation also requires some causal explanation. A notion of causality which would say "some correlations can happen without any causal connection" is simply not worth to be named causality.

But if something is sufficient as an explanation of a correlation has a well-defined mathematical meaning. It means that if we control for the common cause C, then A and B become independent again: ##P(A\land B|C) = P(A|C)P(B|C)##. And this is enough to prove the Bell inequalities. And therefore a theory with relativistic causality cannot make the predictions of QT. You have to give up Einstein causality, to replace it by some non-causality misnamed "signal causality".
The point to argue within relativistic physics is of course that there is no tension between causality and the collapse postulate within non-relativistic physics. In Galilean spacetime instantaneous actions at a distance are not excluded but rather usually what's used (e.g., in Newton's theory of the gravitational interaction). So there's simply nothing to argue about within non-relativistic QM.

The correlations described by entangled states are of course due to the fact that the system is prepared in such a state in the beginning. In that sense the correlations have a cause, but the cause is the preparation in an entangled state at the very beginning and not due to the measurement at part A of the system which may be very far distant from part B.

I don't understand your last paragraph: Most of the Bell tests are done with photon pairs, which are correctly described within standard QED, which is a local relativistic QFT leading to the very prediction of the violation of Bell's inequality. For me Einstein causality simply is that there are no causal connections between space-like separated events, and that's what's implied by the very construnction of local relativistic QFTs (microcausality condition).
 
  • #81
vanhees71 said:
What do you mean by "classical relativistic causality" then? For me causality simply means that two space-like separated events cannot be causally connected and that implies that signals can propagate maximally at the speed of light (i.e., such signals that are mediated by a massless field as the em. field).

Bell inequalities describe however constraints on correlations, and correlations can exist across spacelike separated parts of a system, e.g., the entangled photon pairs used in Bell experiments. Here measurements on far-distant parts show correlations violating Bell's inequalities showing that QT is incompatible with any local determinstic HV theory. The correlations are found also when the registration events of the two photons are spacelike separated. As you admit that local relativistic QFTs exclude faster-than light signalling this implies that within these QFTs it's impossible that the correlations are due to causal effects of one measurement on the other, and this excludes at least a naive collapse assumption: All that changes causally when A registers her photon can only be within the future light cone of this measurment event and thus there cannot be any causal influence on B's measurement result from A's measurement. So there cannot be any collapse in the sense of a dynamical causal physical process.

Note that there arise no contradictions when you assume a kind of "local collapse", i.e., if you just interpret "collapse" as an update of the state description by one of the observers. Say A has measured the polarization of her photon (prepared as one of the usual Bell states of a photon pair) being H. Then she knows that with certainty B must find his photon to be V polarized (i.e., no matter when B measures his photon, i.e., before A's measurement or after A's measurement or even simultaneously or if his measurement event is space-like separated). Of course then A may update her description of the pair to |HV⟩ without changing any of her predictions what B has measured/will measure as compared to the predictions by using the original entangled state. So indeed, within local relativistic QFTs, there's no way to use entanglement for faster-than-light signalling.

The problem with your argument is that no prediction is changed by physical collapse. So whether the collapse is physical or just a state update, all predictions of the theory are the same.
 
  • #82
atyy said:
The problem with your argument is that no prediction is changed by physical collapse. So whether the collapse is physical or just a state update, all predictions of the theory are the same.
To me this is an argument against physical collapse. If all the experiments, even in principle, cannot tell the difference, then what does it mean to say that it was physical!

ps What is "classical relativistic causality" and what is its relation to "no faster than light signalling"?
 
  • #83
atyy said:
The problem with your argument is that no prediction is changed by physical collapse. So whether the collapse is physical or just a state update, all predictions of the theory are the same.
The important difference is that the interpretation as state update is not in contradiction with the mathematical foundation, but the collapse is!
 
  • #84
In my opinion, as I said in another thread about interpretations, the interpretation of collapse as state update is nonsensical, while the interpretation of collapse as physical is wrong.

Why do I say it's nonsensical to interpret collapse as state update? State update makes sense in classical probability, because the probability distribution is assumed to reflect the observer's lack of information about the actual state of affairs. When you learn something new, then you update the probability distribution to reflect that new information. That's sensible, but the underlying assumption is that probabilities are subjective. But in QM, the probabilities that come from the wave function cannot be interpreted as subjective. That would be a hidden-variables theory, not pure QM.

Let's consider the case of an anti-correlated twin-pair EPR experiment. For now, let's assume that it's agreed that Alice and Bob will measure the spin of their particle along the z-axis. Then when Alice measures her particle to have spin-up, she knows immediately that Bob will measure spin-down. To interpret this as just a "state update" means that the result of Bob's measurement was determined before Alice performed her measurement, and her measurement simply revealed this pre-existing value. That's a hidden variable theory.
 
  • #85
vanhees71 said:
The important difference is that the interpretation as state update is not in contradiction with the mathematical foundation, but the collapse is!

But no equation changes between state update and physical collapse, so how can physical collapse be in contradiction to the mathematical foundation?
 
  • #86
atyy said:
But no equation changes between state update and physical collapse, so how can physical collapse be in contradiction to the mathematical foundation?

I think you're right, that collapse or no collapse makes no difference to the mathematical foundation. However, I think the distinction is this: A collapse interpretation (along with other interpretations such as Bohmian mechanics) would mean that relativity is wrong. Relativity would still be recoverable as an effective, approximate theory, valid in certain circumstances.
 
  • #87
atyy said:
But no equation changes between state update and physical collapse, so how can physical collapse be in contradiction to the mathematical foundation?
Well collapse means that instantaneously to a measurement the entire state changes to an eigenstate of the measured observable with the corresponding eigenstate, namely to the projection of the state before measurement to that corresponding eigenspace. If you take this as a physical process there's a contradiction in the case of relativistic microcausal QFTs, because the measurement is local and thus all interactions cannot leads to causal changes over space-like separated space-time points. So there's nothing in the formalism that allows for a collapse as a dynamical physical process.

On the other hand, why are you then so keen to keep the collapse in the interpretation, if it doesn't make any difference anyway? I agree with that, and because of these contradictions with the formalism I just don't use the collapse assumption without loosing anything in the application of the formalism to the description of experiments in the lab.
 
  • #88
vanhees71 said:
Well collapse means that instantaneously to a measurement the entire state changes to an eigenstate of the measured observable with the corresponding eigenstate, namely to the projection of the state before measurement to that corresponding eigenspace. If you take this as a physical process there's a contradiction in the case of relativistic microcausal QFTs, because the measurement is local and thus all interactions cannot leads to causal changes over space-like separated space-time points. So there's nothing in the formalism that allows for a collapse as a dynamical physical process.

But this argument is not correct. Microcausality imposes no superluminal signaling, Collapse interpreted as physical is also consistent with no superluminal signaling. So it doesn't make sense to say that collapse is inconsistent with microcausality.

vanhees71 said:
On the other hand, why are you then so keen to keep the collapse in the interpretation, if it doesn't make any difference anyway? I agree with that, and because of these contradictions with the formalism I just don't use the collapse assumption without loosing anything in the application of the formalism to the description of experiments in the lab.

I prefer the state update interpretation, but I think it's important to get the understanding of microcausality correct. Microcausality is about there being no superluminal signaling, so it is consistent with collapse interpreted physically. By rejecting physical collapse on the basis of "microcausality", you are using a different intuition that is like classical relativistic causality to apply to microcausality. But it isn't correct to think of "microcausality" like classical relativistic causality.
 
  • #89
vanhees71 said:
The point to argue within relativistic physics is of course that there is no tension between causality and the collapse postulate within non-relativistic physics.
Ok, but that does not mean that you can simply invent some new notion of "relativistic causality" which has nothing to do with the original notion of causality which becomes even stronger once we restrict the allowed causal connections to the lightcone.
vanhees71 said:
The correlations described by entangled states are of course due to the fact that the system is prepared in such a state in the beginning. In that sense the correlations have a cause, but the cause is the preparation in an entangled state at the very beginning and not due to the measurement at part A of the system which may be very far distant from part B.
And once you identify the common cause with this preparation, you can apply ##P(AB|C) = P(A|C)P(B|C)##. Apply it to the measurement in the same direction, with 100% correlation, and you get that the preparation gives either P(A|C)=1 or P(A|C)=0, thus, the measurement result is predefined by the state. With this assumption, the remaining proof of the BI becomes trivial.
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand your last paragraph: Most of the Bell tests are done with photon pairs, which are correctly described within standard QED, which is a local relativistic QFT leading to the very prediction of the violation of Bell's inequality. For me Einstein causality simply is that there are no causal connections between space-like separated events, and that's what's implied by the very construnction of local relativistic QFTs (microcausality condition).
For me, Einstein causality is classical causality strengthened by the additional restriction that causal connections are allowed only inside the light cones. That means, if we have Einstein causality, we can prove the BI. Once the BI are violated, QED is not an Einstein-causal theory.

You have only that "signal causality", which follows from that "microcausality", both being essentially weaker than real causality with common cause principle.
 
  • #90
atyy said:
But this argument is not correct. Microcausality imposes no superluminal signaling, Collapse interpreted as physical is also consistent with no superluminal signaling. So it doesn't make sense to say that collapse is inconsistent with microcausality.
I prefer the state update interpretation, but I think it's important to get the understanding of microcausality correct. Microcausality is about there being no superluminal signaling, so it is consistent with collapse interpreted physically. By rejecting physical collapse on the basis of "microcausality", you are using a different intuition that is like classical relativistic causality to apply to microcausality. But it isn't correct to think of "microcausality" like classical relativistic causality.
How can microcausality (implying the impossibility of superluminal signaling) be consistent with collapse as a physical process since the collapse clearly predicts superluminal signaling. Take the standard entangled photon pair. If you consider collapse a physical process, then when A finds her photon being H-polarized, the state instantaneously collapses to ##|HV \rangle \langle HV|##, i.e., instaneously Bob's photon gets into the state ##|V \rangle \langle V|##, while before its state clearly was different, namely ##\hat{1}/2## even Bob may be light-years away from Alice. That's clearly inconsistent with the impossibility of superluminal signaling.

The way out is also clear: You interpret the quantum state simply as what it is, namely providing probabilities for the outcome of measurements, including the correlations described by entanglement. Then you don't need any collapse to understand the 100% correlation between the polarizations of the photons, because it's already there from the very beginning when the photon pairs are prepared in this entangled state. It's not A's measurement causing a collapse, including B's photon that is registered maybe lightyears away at the same time as A's (in their common rest frame, for simplicity of the argument), that causes the correlation but the preparation of the photons in the very beginning before any measurment has been performed, and in this way everything is consistent with the impossibility of faster-than-light signalling and thus the microcausality property of QED.

I still don't get what you mean by "classical relativistic causality" in contradistinction to "microcausality". For me microcausality simply is a way to guarantee that the oucome of measurements must obey "relativistic causility". I don't know what you mean by "classical causality". Causality has the same meaning in all of physics.
 
  • #91
Sunil said:
You have only that "signal causality", which follows from that "microcausality", both being essentially weaker than real causality with common cause principle.
This makes no sense since QED IS a theory obeying Einstein causality by the imposing the microcausality constraint on local observables. I don't understand what you mean by "real causality with common cause principle" and why you think "signal causality" is in some sense weaker.
 
  • #92
I am still waiting for someone to explain the terms "Einstein causality", "classical relativistic causality", and "no faster than light signaling". Aren't they the same?
 
  • #93
vanhees71 said:
This makes no sense since QED IS a theory obeying Einstein causality by the imposing the microcausality constraint on local observables.
No, it is not. What you can derive using that misnamed "microcausality" condition is only that (also misnamed) "signal causality", that you cannot send signals FTL. That's all. You don't have a common cause principle for that "microcausality".
vanhees71 said:
I don't understand what you mean by "real causality with common cause principle" and why you think "signal causality" is in some sense weaker.
For the common cause principle, see https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/physics-Rpcc/. Some people are critical of it, in particular Arntzenius, but I have not found that criticism impressing. For example, one can formulate stochastic theories in such a way that the common cause does not appear in the theoretical formalism. So what? The principle is simple, if there is a correlation between A and B, it requires an explanation, which may be a direct causal influence ##A\to B## or ##B\to A## or some common cause ##C\to A, C\to B##. The common cause is sufficient as an explanation if after controlling it the correlation disappears, ##P(AB|C)=P(A|C)P(B|C)##, else the remaining correlation requires more explanation.

Once "signal causality" does not contain the common cause principle, it is much weaker and misnamed.
martinbn said:
I am still waiting for someone to explain the terms "Einstein causality", "classical relativistic causality", and "no faster than light signaling". Aren't they the same?
Einstein causality is classical causality, inclusive the common cause principle, with the additional restriction that causal influences can exist only inside the light cone. "Signal causality" is the impossibility to send signals with FTL. It follows from Einstein causality but does not contain the common cause principle. That means, there may be arbitrary correlations between space-like separated events, but a request to explain them somehow will be ignored - correlations do not require causal explanations in signal causality.

So, assume you have two dices. If thrown at approximately the same time in the CMBR frame, they give always the same number. You obviously cannot use them to send signals. So, signal causality is not violated. It holds, and those dices give no reason to doubt that it holds.

Instead, in Einstein causality, these dices are surprising, and create an open scientific problem: To explain in a causal way why they give always the same number when thrown at the same time, even if that is done space-like separated.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and gentzen
  • #94
So when you say Einstein causality, you mean causality plus common cause principle. Who came up with this name? And what about all the objections to the common cause princple? Last time i asked you, you shruged it off. But why do you elevate it to a univarsal principle?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #95
martinbn said:
I am still waiting for someone to explain the terms "Einstein causality", "classical relativistic causality", and "no faster than light signaling". Aren't they the same?
I'm waiting too. For me they are all the same. I don't know what "classical" has to do with it. A theory is causal or not, no matter whether it's a classical (field) or a quantum (field) theory.
 
  • #96
vanhees71 said:
How can microcausality (implying the impossibility of superluminal signaling) be consistent with collapse as a physical process since the collapse clearly predicts superluminal signaling. Take the standard entangled photon pair. If you consider collapse a physical process, then when A finds her photon being H-polarized, the state instantaneously collapses to ##|HV \rangle \langle HV|##, i.e., instaneously Bob's photon gets into the state ##|V \rangle \langle V|##, while before its state clearly was different, namely ##\hat{1}/2## even Bob may be light-years away from Alice. That's clearly inconsistent with the impossibility of superluminal signaling.

Since collapse interpeted as a physical process doesn't change any predictions from state update, which you say is consistent with microcausality, the "superluminal signaling" you mention above for physical collapse is not observable.

Hence in quantum theory there are two definitions of "no superluminal signaling" - the unobservable definition and the observable definition. Collapse interpreted as a physical process is not consistent with the unobservable definition that you are using, but it is consistent with the observable definition.
 
  • Like
Likes Fra
  • #97
Ok, "collapse" is so unsharply defined that you always can find some intepretation of this phrase that's consistent with the formalism. ;-)).

I don't know, what you mean by "unobservable definition".
 
  • #98
vanhees71 said:
I don't know, what you mean by "unobservable definition".
If we are thinking alike, it means the observable definition means that two observers can communicate at superluminal speeds. Alice and Bob can not do so.

In the case of statistical correlations, no one ever observers a FTL influence.

/Fredrik
 
  • Like
Likes atyy and vanhees71
  • #99
martinbn said:
So when you say Einstein causality, you mean causality plus common cause principle. Who came up with this name?
I'm not a historian, I would naively guess that Reichenbach once it is named after him, but this is something one would have to check.
martinbn said:
And what about all the objections to the common cause princple? Last time i asked you, you shruged it off. But why do you elevate it to a univarsal principle?
I did not found the objections impressive, as I said. If you feel differently for one of the many of those arguments, feel free to present it here and we will see. A forum is certainly not the place to write a complete refutation of all those arguments.

I elevate this to a universal principle because thinking about it I have recognized the central role of it in the scientific method. It is the very point of causality that, one the one hand, causality is something quite restricted, and, on the other hand, an arbitrary correlation requires a causal explanation.

If you give up to think that correlations require causal explanations, you can stop doing science and start astrology instead. Statistical experiments would not make sense. You have observed a correlation, so what?

Last but not least, there are correlations between the positions of stars and human behavior, quite in line with the predictions of astrology. Those who care about causal explanations explain them away mentioning that many people believe in astrology, so that one has to expect a lot of self-fulfilling prophecies. But once you don't think that such causal explanations are necessary, astrology itself will be fine too. Not?
 
  • #100
martinbn said:
So when you say Einstein causality, you mean causality plus common cause principle. Who came up with this name? And what about all the objections to the common cause princple? Last time i asked you, you shruged it off. But why do you elevate it to a univarsal principle?

I don't think it's a matter of it being a universal principle, it's a matter of saying in what sense quantum mechanics is nonlocal. Before quantum mechanics, it was presumed that it was possible within a "patch" of spacetime, if not within the whole universe, to set up an inertial cartesian coordinate system ##x, y, z, t## such that the most complete description of that patch could be given by a state of the patch evolving over time: ##S(t)##. The state would include facts about particles and fields. In terms of such a picture of the world, we can define locality in the following way:

Divide up the world (or the patch we're interested in) into boxes of size ##\Delta x, \Delta y, \Delta z##. Label the boxes so that box ##(i,j,k)## is the region defined by the set of all points ##(x,y,z)## such that ##i \Delta x \leq x \leq (i+1) \Delta x##, ##j \Delta y \leq y \leq (j+1) \Delta y##, ##k \Delta z \leq z \leq (k+1) \Delta x##.

The state ##S(t)## is said to be separable if it is possible to come up with "local states" ##S_{ijk}(t)## such that ##S(t)## is deducible from the values of all the ##S_{ijk}(t)##, and vice-versa.

If the state of the world (or patch) is separable, then we can define locality in terms of the local states. If ##\Delta t## is an interval of time that is short enough that ##c \Delta t \leq \Delta x##, ##c \Delta t \leq \Delta y##, ##c \Delta t \leq \Delta z##, then the evolution of local state ##S_{ijk}(t)## over the time from ##t## to ##t + \Delta t## can depend only on the states of neighboring boxes, (Box ##(i,j,k)## is a neighbor to Box ##(i',j',k')## is ##|i - i'| \leq 1##, ##|j - j'| \leq 1##, ##|k - k'| \leq 1##).
 

Similar threads

Replies
0
Views
6K
Replies
25
Views
5K
Replies
826
Views
85K
Replies
14
Views
2K
Replies
92
Views
19K
Replies
174
Views
13K
Back
Top