What is the physics behind GR's diffeomorphism invariance?

In summary: down to the following question: is there any physical reason why the laws of physics should be invariant under a certain transformation group?...the answer is that there is a certain natural reason, which is that the transformation group should be the group of isometries of the space-time metric.
  • #1
itssilva
55
0
Hi. This is my first post here in PF ( :) ). I've been reading some threads on "passive" versus "active" diffeomorphisms, and I wondered: what is the physical motivation for having GR be diffeomorphic invariant? Sure, this allows us to have solutions to Einstein's equations (EFE) up to diffeomorphism (pick one and obtain another by "pushing forward" along the morphism), but, as far as I know (and may be incorrect, please feel free to comment on inadequacies), relativistic equations are only required to be invariant under some representation of the Poincaré group P, which is, itself, a subset of GL(4, R), the set of matrix representations of all possible real linear transformations in 4-space; why not simply restrict ourselves to morphisms associated to P?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Hi itssilva, and welcome to PF!

itssilva said:
relativistic equations are only required to be invariant under some representation of the Poincaré group P

This is true in special relativity, where spacetime is flat; but in GR, spacetime is curved, and this restriction doesn't apply. Basically, this is because in flat spacetime, the Poincare group is always the isometry group of the spacetime; but a general curved spacetime may not have an isometry group at all. So the only way to write laws of physics that are invariant in a general curved spacetime is to make them invariant under general diffeomorphisms.
 
  • Like
Likes bcrowell
  • #3
"physical motivation for having GR be diffeomorphic invariant"

This comes from the physical picture that "laws" of physics should be written in a form that all observers agree on it. Now observers or reference frames in physics is defined by a set of coordinate systems and clocks. GR first assumes that spacetime (or curved spacetime but I think the adjective curved is redundant) is a (pseudo)Riemannian manifold. As you know very well, changing reference frames or observers then means simply changing the labels of spacetime coordinates i.e. relabeling of the points on the manifold (or in math lingo going from one coordinate patch to another one which overlap at the points being relabelled). Einstein argued that since under the relabelings (aka diffeomorphisms) the manifold does not change, so should the laws of physics as well. This is how he promoted diffeomorphism covariance or general covariance to a principle. However this does not mean anything more than the fact the laws of physics should be of the form, "Some tensor field =0" and nothing more. How gravity comes into the picture is a whole different and interesting part of the story and there we need something called the equivalence principle.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #4
Roy_1981 said:
However this does not mean anything more than the fact the laws of physics should be of the form, "Some tensor field =0" and nothing more.

In fact the real content of diffeomorphism invariance comes about when one makes the metric tensor dynamical. This makes it more than just a mere statement about general covariance which is a rather trivial statement by itself.
 
  • Like
Likes wabbit
  • #5
"In fact the real content of diffeomorphism invariance comes about when one makes the metric tensor dynamical."

This statement is akin to putting horse before the cart. A pseudo-Riemannian manifold in general would have a metric (tensor) components to be time-dependent. Stationary spacetimes are special cases where metric is without time-dependence, aka non-dynamical. General covariance is content free when it comes to linking metric tensor to gravitation. In fact, one can write down a general covariant version of Newton's scalar theory of gravitation as was done by Cartan which is unfortuantely not covered in a GR course or most texts. But the encyclodepic treatise of Misner, Thorne & Wheeler has a nice description of Cartan's theory. Bottomline is one needs the principle of equivalence to link the metric tensor to gravitation. General covariance alone gives you nothing, I won't use the belittling adjective "trivial" but instead would use the adjective "natural or expected".
 
  • #6
The following is approximately how Einstein argues in his original paper:

In pre-general relativistic physics, the differences in coordinates had a natural interpretation in terms of measuring rods and clocks. To apply the equivalence principle, we assume that the freely falling frame, in which there is no gravitational field, is the truly inertial one, and special relativity applies only in the freely falling frame. This implies that the 'stationary frame' in which there is a gravitational field, has a metric tensor that is different from the Minkowski one, and for example the rate of clocks depend on their position, and light rays do not move in straight lines, so this coordinate system cannot be interpreted in the customary way as we did in special relativity.

If we want to base a theory of gravitation on these ideas, we must therefore regard any system of coordinates as equally good from the point of view of the laws, i.e. the equations must be generally covariant.

There is more to this issue, which ultimately boils down to what exactly the coordinates mean in physics. Einstein calls it his "struggle with the meaning of the coordinates." Check out the 'hole argument' for example.
 
  • #8
PeterDonis said:
This is true in special relativity, where spacetime is flat; but in GR, spacetime is curved, and this restriction doesn't apply. Basically, this is because in flat spacetime, the Poincare group is always the isometry group of the spacetime; but a general curved spacetime may not have an isometry group at all. So the only way to write laws of physics that are invariant in a general curved spacetime is to make them invariant under general diffeomorphisms.

I agree; but my question is kinda indirectly tied to the equivalence principle, which I understand physically but haven't been able to translate to math, because, roughly speaking, I imagine GR ought to 'localize' SR, in possibly one of two ways:
1) Suppose you have a tensor field T and a diffeomorphism f, that induces a change in the original T (let's call it *T); then, for every point of spacetime, we could say that the theory is 'diffeomorphic invariant' but restrict ourselves to those f such that the pullback of *T is T transformed by a Poincaré rep; or
2) In a Yang-Mills-like way; in QED, you have global U(1) symmetry, and, if you want that to be local, you add a gauge field A with field strength (curvature) F (all of these geometrical objects defined in a principal bundle), and, for kicks, that introduces interactions in the Lagrangian; I think it suggestive to make the analogy P=U(1), affine connection=A, Riemmann tensor=F and spacetime=some global section after gauge fixing. In fact, there's a line of research, gauge theory gravity, that seems to do something like this, although they don't use the P, for some reason.
As of 'general covariance', I see people using this term in different contexts, but what I understand by that is that means simply writing equations in tensor form, so they are coordinate-independent (and also spacetime-independent, if you use the minimal-prescription of derivatives go to covariant derivatives, etc); thus, even if you Poincaré-transform a coordinate patch, your equations remain the same.
 
  • #9
itssilva said:
Suppose you have a tensor field T and a diffeomorphism f, that induces a change in the original T (let's call it *T); then, for every point of spacetime, we could say that the theory is 'diffeomorphic invariant' but restrict ourselves to those f such that the pullback of *T is T transformed by a Poincaré rep

This amounts to limiting consideration to local inertial coordinates. The problem with that is that there are a lot of things we would like to do in GR that are a lot easier if we aren't limited to local inertial coordinates.

itssilva said:
As of 'general covariance', I see people using this term in different contexts, but what I understand by that is that means simply writing equations in tensor form, so they are coordinate-independent (and also spacetime-independent, if you use the minimal-prescription of derivatives go to covariant derivatives, etc); thus, even if you Poincaré-transform a coordinate patch, your equations remain the same.

But a Poincare transformation only works in local inertial coordinates on a sufficiently small patch of spacetime, because it assumes that the region of spacetime on which it is operating is flat. Again, if we want to allow general coordinate charts on larger regions of spacetime, we can't limit ourselves this way.
 
  • #10
itssilva said:
I agree; but my question is kinda indirectly tied to the equivalence principle, which I understand physically but haven't been able to translate to math, because, roughly speaking, I imagine GR ought to 'localize' SR, in possibly one of two ways:
1) Suppose you have a tensor field T and a diffeomorphism f, that induces a change in the original T (let's call it *T); then, for every point of spacetime, we could say that the theory is 'diffeomorphic invariant' but restrict ourselves to those f such that the pullback of *T is T transformed by a Poincaré rep; or
2) In a Yang-Mills-like way; in QED, you have global U(1) symmetry, and, if you want that to be local, you add a gauge field A with field strength (curvature) F (all of these geometrical objects defined in a principal bundle), and, for kicks, that introduces interactions in the Lagrangian; I think it suggestive to make the analogy P=U(1), affine connection=A, Riemmann tensor=F and spacetime=some global section after gauge fixing. In fact, there's a line of research, gauge theory gravity, that seems to do something like this, although they don't use the P, for some reason.

The "equivalence principle" is related to the "gauge principle" of field theory. Both are "minimal coupling" principles.

itssilva said:
As of 'general covariance', I see people using this term in different contexts, but what I understand by that is that means simply writing equations in tensor form, so they are coordinate-independent (and also spacetime-independent, if you use the minimal-prescription of derivatives go to covariant derivatives, etc); thus, even if you Poincaré-transform a coordinate patch, your equations remain the same.

As WannabeNewton said above, general covariance is trivial. Special relativity is generally covariant also, since it just means that the physics is formulated on a manifold, and we can use any coordinates we want to describe the same physics. The physical content of general relativity is that matter curves spacetime, and spacetime tells matter how to move. (Alternatively, it can be argued to be spin 2, but whatever it is, there is hardly any physics in general covariance. However, terminology varies, and Weinberg's textbook uses "General Covariance" to mean the equivalence principle, which is a non-trivial principle.)

Since general covariance is a kind of gauge equivalence (more than one description of the same physics), one sees that the "gauge principle" is also badly named since it is possible to use non-minimal couplings that also (at least classically) retain gauge invariance.
 
Last edited:
  • #11
It is true that general covariance interpreted as a requirement that the laws should be covariant with respect to arbitrary changes of coordinates is in a sense 'trivial.' However the idea of general convariance in Einstein's mind was a little different, and is not exactly a mathematical requirement, and is in his words also a kind of 'heuristic' principle.

Newton's laws for example, prefer particular coordinate systems in the sense that they are simplest when they refer to inertial frames. The law of inertia that a body free from forces moves in a straight line for example is not generally covariant, although a more complicated formulation (Cartan) can be generally covariant.

Einstein's idea was that the the simplest and most natural formulation of gravity theory must not prefer any particular coordinate systems, i.e. the simplest description must be applicable in arbitrary coordinates without change.

The preference for particular coordinate choices arises as a description of particular situations, and cannot therefore be part of the most natural formulation. Einstein compares this to the following situation: on the Earth's surface, there is a preferred direction, the vertical, connected to the uniform gravitational field near the surface. If we were to formulate the theory in such a way that this direction was embedded in the foundation of the theory, it would make things very difficult when we consider more general situations, because the preferred direction which has been embedded into the foundations completely complicates things when we are no longer on the surface of the earth. The preference given to inertial frames is kind of analogous to this, and the the most natural description is one where such preferred systems are not embedded in the foundations.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes atyy, martinbn and PeterDonis
  • #12
dx said:
It is true that general covariance interpreted as a requirement that the laws should be covariant with respect to arbitrary changes of coordinates is in a sense 'trivial.' However the idea of general convariance in Einstein's mind was a little different, and is not exactly a mathematical requirement, and is in his words also a kind of 'heuristic' principle.

Newton's laws for example, prefer particular coordinate systems in the sense that they are simplest when they refer to inertial frames. The law of inertia that a body free from forces moves in a straight line for example is not generally covariant, although a more complicated formulation (Cartan) can be generally covariant.

Einstein's idea was that the the simplest and most natural formulation of gravity theory must not prefer any particular coordinate systems, i.e. the simplest description must be applicable in arbitrary coordinates without change.

The preference for particular coordinate choices arises as a description of particular situations, and cannot therefore be part of the most natural formulation. Einstein compares this to the following situation: on the Earth's surface, there is a preferred direction, the vertical, connected to the uniform gravitational field near the surface. If we were to formulate the theory in such a way that this direction was embedded in the foundation of the theory, it would make things very difficult when we consider more general situations, because the preferred direction which has been embedded into the foundations completely complicates things when we are no longer on the surface of the earth. The preference given to inertial frames is kind of analogous to this, and the the most natural description is one where such preferred systems are not embedded in the foundations.

Is the argument here simply that there is no global inertial frame, because spacetime is curved? If so, does it require a cosmological solution, or some circumstances like a non-zero cosmological constant under which the gravity cannot be written as spin 2 on flat spacetime? If that is the case, it would be funny that Einstein first tried to make the universe static - but at least he had to the good sense to use the cosmological constant to do that?
 
  • #13
Yes, I think so. Not only is there no global inertial frame, but also that as soon as we admit non-linear transformations in order to use the equivalence principle, we lose the interpretation of differences in coordinates as measurable lengths and times using rods and clocks. However we cannot avoid admitting these non-linear transformations if we want to base the theory on the equivalence principle, and there seems to be no natural way to restrict these non-linear coordinates for the reason given before (i.e. their lack of direct connection to metric measurements), so we must admit all possible coordinates on equal footing.

The argument in my previous post about how the preference given to inertial systems is analogous to the preferred vertical direction near the surface of the Earth is given in Einstein's essay "Autobiographical Notes." He goes into these things much more deeply there.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #14
Not only do the coordinates lack a direct connection to metric measurements, the coordinates in fact do not represent anything real. We cannot even say that a particular point (x1, x2, x3, x4) corresponds to a particular event. Such an identification becomes possible only once the gravitational field has been introduced (i.e. one of many possible fields which are related by gauge transformations.) The active diffeomorphisms of the fields defined on the coordinates also changes the location of events relative to the coordinates.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #15
Thanks everyone for your comments, I really appreciate your input; to more or less wrap things up, I'd like to point out that seeing gravity as the gauge theory of the Poincaré group is an old thing - just google it to see -, but I find it really odd that few people pursue this line of research, which is more on line with the modern approach to high-energy physics and it also seems the more parsimonious view; to illustrate this last point, let me use this modified version of the elevator thought experiment: suppose I'm at reference frame S and you are at S', accelerating away from me at acceleration a (S and S' are in a region where gravitational effects are negligible), and I shoot a light signal at angle θ from the direction of motion; you'd see light bend towards or away from you (depending on a), because c has to be constant; the weak PE asserts that gravitational phenomena, such as the bending of light, cannot be distinguished from the effects of acceleration as observed in inertial reference frames, so, if you didn't know about S, you might be inclined to say that there was some mass distribution nearby causing the signal to bend - conversely, you may swap to a non-inertial frame S'', which rotates slightly away from S' in such a way as to always see the signal at angle θ from your direction of motion. Both views, I believe, imply that spacetime is curved, and I only needed local P transformations to arrive at this conclusion; to me, it still feels that these are the only transformations (local or global) with real physical content; otherwise, how do you make sense of some arbitrary transformation of spacetime coordinates or spacetime-valued fields that is not a translation, a rotation or a boost?
 
  • #16
This sounds a little strange to me, probably misreading what you say here - but if you want to exclude non-inertial frames, describing you standing in your lab becomes rather contrived as you would be using a (inertial) frame that accelerates away from the lab.
 
  • #17
", I'd like to point out that seeing gravity as the gauge theory of the Poincaré group is an old thing - just google it to see -, but I find it really odd that few people pursue this line of research"

Actually this line of thought has been pursued since the late 60s thru 70s till mid-80s and followed to a unsuccessful conclusion apart from the case of 2+1 dimensions. The issue is that there is NO gauge theory action which corresponds to GR. Witten demonstrated in 1988 that this only possible in 2+1 dimensions where Einstein-Hilbert action/GR corresponds to a (sum of) Chern-Simons Gauge theory action. Witten's 1988 paper itself has a nice summary of this line of thought, called the Macdowell-Mansouri approach, and why it is ultimately not fruitful (https://inspirehep.net/record/264816?ln=en).

"which is more on line with the modern approach to high-energy physics and it also seems the more parsimonious view"

Actually the modern/high energy theorists approach to GR or Einstein-Hilbert is based on showing that for spin-2 massless particles, a consistent interacting theory can only be constructed without negative norm ghosts if one has linearized diffeomorphisms as a symmetry. Then adding (self)-interactions lead to an infinite series which when summed leads to Einstein field equations. You can find this quantum field theorists approach to GR in Deser (1970), republished as gr-qc/0411023.
 
  • #18
wabbit said:
This sounds a little strange to me, probably misreading what you say here - but if you want to exclude non-inertial frames, describing you standing in your lab becomes rather contrived as you would be using a (inertial) frame that accelerates away from the lab.
The frames look non-inertial globally, but my point is that they can be made to look inertial locally by P transformations-and this is important in the example because the observer makes local observations. Dunno if that helped?
 
  • #19
Roy_1981 said:
"The issue is that there is NO gauge theory action which corresponds to GR.
I don't want to be obtruse, but putting it that way feels a little like a circular argument: for, if you're trying to make a first-principles theory, you get the equations (be the H-E action or whatever) as a result of your physical considerations, as Einstein did starting from PE+general covariance, instead of considering them as a given-that is, any gravitation theory ought to be satisfactory if it satisfies our physical requirements of PE+general covariance plus agree with observation, which GR happens to do; sure, it might well be that it's mathematically impossible to find a gauge theory corresponding to the H-E action, but that doesn't necessarily exclude the possibility that you start with one and, by appropriate gauge fixing and/or other subtleties, you arrive at an action that at least approximates the H-E or its predictions (sorry if I've digressed too much here :confused:)
 
  • #20
itssilva said:
The frames look non-inertial globally, but my point is that they can be made to look inertial locally by P transformations-and this is important in the example because the observer makes local observations. Dunno if that helped?
Hmm no but don't mind me I was just stopping by and this discussion is way over my head - sorry please carry on.
 
  • #21
"I don't want to be obtruse, but putting it that way feels a little like a circular argument:"

Perhaps I was not clear enough. What I meant is that it can be shown that GR/gravity cannot gauge theory of the Poincaré group (except 2+1 dimensions). And by Gauge theory I meant a theory which is invariant under a set local continuous transformations which constitute a group.
 
  • #22
Roy_1981 said:
Actually the modern/high energy theorists approach to GR or Einstein-Hilbert is based on showing that for spin-2 massless particles, a consistent interacting theory can only be constructed without negative norm ghosts if one has linearized diffeomorphisms as a symmetry. Then adding (self)-interactions lead to an infinite series which when summed leads to Einstein field equations. You can find this quantum field theorists approach to GR in Deser (1970), republished as gr-qc/0411023.
True.

This is slight digression, but the summing of a series is not required, as Deser says

We now derive the full Einstein equations, on the basis of the same self-coupling requirement,
but with the advantages that the full theory emerges in closed form with just one added (cubic)
term, rather than as an infinite series,...


Thought it was worth mentioning
 
  • #23
"but the summing of a series is not required,"

Thanks for pointing out. Indeed, the first order correction or first iteration is enough. Evident from the first order form of Fierz-Pauli version used by Deser, the first order change in graviton field changes the connection to logarithmic in total field strength, which is already infinite series/orders.
 
  • #24
Roy_1981 said:
Actually this line of thought has been pursued since the late 60s thru 70s till mid-80s and followed to a unsuccessful conclusion apart from the case of 2+1 dimensions. The issue is that there is NO gauge theory action which corresponds to GR. Witten demonstrated in 1988 that this only possible in 2+1 dimensions where Einstein-Hilbert action/GR corresponds to a (sum of) Chern-Simons Gauge theory action. Witten's 1988 paper itself has a nice summary of this line of thought, called the Macdowell-Mansouri approach, and why it is ultimately not fruitful (https://inspirehep.net/record/264816?ln=en).
This is late, but, thanks for the ref. As a bit of a sidenote, I've seen that in the ref you gave me plus others that worked on the subject, such as (http://ptp.oxfordjournals.org/content/64/3/866.full.pdf), the focus was on gauging GR through tetrad fields; indeed, from the ref I just gave: "The gauge group [...] is the Poincare gauge group, which is the extension of the Poincare group. In this case the gravitational variable is the tetrad field, which is more fundamental than the metric tensor." Yet, I know nothing about people trying to quantize GR in the spirit of example 2) of post #8, i.e., associate the affine connection directly with the generator(s) of the Poincaré group, the Riemmann tensor with the field strength and spacetime with some global section after gauge fixing, à la Yang-Mills; is there a reason (physical and/or mathematical) for not doing this? Am I missing something obvious? I haven't read on why using tetrads in the first place, but, from what you described, that approach doesn't seem fruitful, anyway...
 
  • #25
Without reading this whole topic: diffeomorphism invariance is not a defining property of GR, because a lot of theories can be recasted in general-covariant form (and general covariance is "dual" to diff.invariance), including Newton. From a field point of view one can derive that general covariance is needed for consistency when iterating Fierz-Pauli theories to include higher-order corrections. See e.g. Hinterbilcher's notes on massive gravity.
 
  • #27
The first physical theory that we learn is Newtonian mechanics, and Newtonian mechanics has a certain set of preferred coordinate systems. Diffeomorphism invariance therefore seems strange to us. But it's more natural to put it the other way around. If someone doesn't want to be agnostic about coordinate systems, then the burden is on them to say which coordinate systems are OK. When you think about it with the advantage of modern hindsight, it quickly becomes clear that formulating such a rule is not easy. For example, suppose you're using a cosmological model in which the universe has the spatial topology of a sphere. We can't put a smooth, well-behaved coordinate system on a sphere; we either have to use charts that overlap, or we have to have coordinate singularities.
 
  • #28
There are three related, but subtly different aspects to diffeomorphism invariance that I've had trouble getting a handle.

The first is coordinate-independence. You should be able to use any coordinate system you like, and that shouldn't change the form of your theory. This is almost a vacuous principle, because any theory can be cast into a coordinate-free form, once you identify the scalar fields, vector fields and tensor fields associated with your theory.

The second is something like "no prior geometry", which basically says that there are no nondynamical scalar, vector or tensor fields. (I guess it should be phrased that there are no such fields that are fixed by the theory--there certain can be solutions to the equations of motion that produce fields that are constant everywhere). This is in contrast with Newtonian physics, which has a universal time that is a nondynamic scalar field, and with Special Relativity, which has a metric tensor that is a nondynamic tensor field. A theory with no prior geometry has to be written in a coordinate-independent way (I think), because there is no way to single out a preferred coordinate system without these prior structures.

The third is subtler, and I don't know whether it is equivalent to the second, or not. It's something like "the indistinguishabilty of points". This is the point that Einstein was making with his "hole" argument. Coordinate-independence by itself is just about labeling points on your spacetime manifold. It's sort of obvious that it should make no difference what label you give to points, if you leave the manifold and its fields unchanged. This third principle says that changing the manifold itself doesn't do anything, provided that you adjust all the physical fields accordingly. If your manifold is a sphere, for instance, you can imagine doing violence to it by squashing it into a pancake. But if you adjust all the fields appropriately, then the new manifold will be indistinguishable from the first. You can imagine deciding that you'd like to change the world so that New York City is at longitude 0o, instead of 74o. The wimpy way to do that is to just choose a new coordinate system in which the zero for longitude goes through New York City. But the godlike way of doing it is to physically grab the island of Manhattan, and move it 3000 miles to the east, then move the neighboring boroughs, then the rest of the New York State, then the rest of the US, and then move the rest of the world to make room, and then go and move all the stars in the sky. After you're done with all these physical changes, if you made sure that you nailed down every single detail, you will end up with a universe that looks exactly like the original, except that the longitude labels on the Earth have changed. In other words, a complete transformation of the manifold and all its objects is equivalent to a simple coordinate change. In yet other words, there is no identity to points on the manifold apart from the values of fields at that point that distinguish it from other points.

What I'm not sure about is whether the third principle (which I can't state in a succinct way) is actual implied by the second. I think that it is, because if there were any way to distinguish points on the manifold, then that would imply in some sense a nondynamical field. If every point had a name, that would imply a "name field" that is nondynamical.
 
  • #29
This is a quote from
Symmetry Transformations, the Einstein-Hilbert Action, and Gauge Invariance
(c) 2000, 2002 Edmund Bertschinger.

When gravity is the only force acting on a particle, diffeomorphism-invariance has a purely geometric interpretation in terms of special vector felds known as Killing vectors.

The physical interpretation suggested in this course material ( and other sources I can't track down right now) is energy-momentum conservation.
 
  • #30
stevendaryl said:
There are three related, but subtly different aspects to diffeomorphism invariance that I've had trouble getting a handle.

The first is coordinate-independence.

The second is something like "no prior geometry",

The third is subtler, and I don't know whether it is equivalent to the second, or not. It's something like "the indistinguishabilty of points".
At the risk of introducing confusing notation, since there is some controversy to the actual meaning of the expressions, I think that these are related to the concepts of general covariance, passive and active diffeomorphism invariance: aspect 1 is general covariance; you can make any equation generally covariant by writing its quantities as tensors/spinors (because these do not depend on the coordinate-patches they're defined on), and as a bonus it would be automatically passive diffeomorphism invariant (i.e., transformations on the coordinate-patch leave the equation unchanged because the fields themselves transform accordingly through its 'tensor character').
Which leaves us to the other two; by my present understanding, I believe "indistinguishabilty of points", in the "godlike" way you describe, is equivalent to the active diffeomorphism invariance (change the field, leave the coordinate-patches alone), which, generally, is a non-trivial thing to do (for rotation of a field by a constant angle, for instance, both active and passive transformations obviously give the same thing, but I'm not so sure for your sphere → pancake transition); however, if you're able to enforce both kinds of invariance (by, say, a 'gimmick' of making the metric field change to your convenience), the theory would be manifold/coordinate-patch-independent ("no prior geometry"?), and having this seems to me the ONLY reason to want to make GR diff-invariant; I cannot but wonder, however, that doing this might be kind of an overkill, just so we have a theory that obey the PE.
 
  • #31
stevendaryl said:
The third is subtler, and I don't know whether it is equivalent to the second, or not. It's something like "the indistinguishabilty of points".

I don't understand this well either, but here are some thoughts. It's usually said here that the hole argument says that observables must be relational in gravity. I don't understand this because I think observables must also be relational in special relativity, ie. relative to an inertial frame.

However, what is known is that in pure gravity, there are no gauge invariant local observables. Classically, this problem can be solved if matter is introduced, so that relational aspects of the matter distribution create local observables. There's a discussion of this around Eq 1.1 of http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9404053.

The quantum situation seems trickier, eg. http://arxiv.org/abs/hep-th/0106109, http://arxiv.org/abs/hep-th/0512200.
 

1. What is the concept of diffeomorphism invariance in general relativity?

Diffeomorphism invariance is a fundamental principle of general relativity, which states that the laws of physics should remain unchanged under arbitrary coordinate transformations. This means that the equations of general relativity should have the same form regardless of the choice of coordinates used to describe the spacetime.

2. How does diffeomorphism invariance relate to the geometry of spacetime?

Diffeomorphism invariance is closely related to the geometric nature of spacetime in general relativity. The theory describes gravity as the curvature of spacetime, and diffeomorphism invariance ensures that this curvature is independent of the coordinate system used to describe it.

3. What is the significance of diffeomorphism invariance in the context of general relativity?

Diffeomorphism invariance is a crucial aspect of general relativity, as it allows the theory to be consistent with the principle of general covariance. This principle states that the laws of physics should be the same for all observers, regardless of their relative motion. Diffeomorphism invariance ensures that this principle is satisfied in the context of general relativity.

4. How is diffeomorphism invariance mathematically represented in general relativity?

In general relativity, diffeomorphism invariance is represented by the use of tensor calculus. This mathematical framework allows for the description of physical quantities that are independent of the choice of coordinates. In particular, the metric tensor, which describes the curvature of spacetime, is a diffeomorphism invariant quantity.

5. Are there any physical implications of violating diffeomorphism invariance in general relativity?

There are no known physical implications of violating diffeomorphism invariance in general relativity. However, it is a fundamental principle of the theory and any violations would require a significant revision of our understanding of gravity. Additionally, experimental evidence strongly supports the validity of diffeomorphism invariance in general relativity.

Similar threads

  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
4
Replies
117
Views
13K
  • Other Physics Topics
Replies
1
Views
2K
Replies
28
Views
7K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
4
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
8
Views
7K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
12
Views
3K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
14
Views
5K
  • Other Physics Topics
Replies
1
Views
2K
  • Science and Math Textbooks
Replies
9
Views
3K
Back
Top