Why isn't Manyworlds obviously correct?

  • Thread starter GofG
  • Start date
In summary: Huh? I don't see how this "approach" (taking the math at face value) says that bodies should interact instantaneously. Can you give me an example?
  • #1
GofG
22
0
First, Schrodinger's Cat:

Photon emitter, pointed at a half-silvered mirror, such that 50% of the wave hits a sensor that activates a gaseous poison emitter inside a box that has a cat in it.

Standardly, we think about it this way: the photon hits the halfsilvered mirror and decoheres into a superposition of "straight" and "reflected", then the sensor decoheres into a superposition of "hit" or "not hit", then the poison emitter decoheres into a superposition of "activated" or "not activated", then the cat decoheres into a superposition of "dead" or "alive"... so the cat is both dead and alive, etc.

Isn't it obvious that upon opening the box, the human decoheres into a superposition of "sees an alive cat" and "sees a dead cat"?

Isn't that blindingly obvious? If the cat can decohere, why can't the human?

And that's all Manyworlds is, is assuming that decoherence doesn't suddenly "stop" at macroscopic levels.

Can someone explain to me why this isn't selfevident?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
GofG said:
Can someone explain to me why this isn't selfevident?

Because none of it is observable. There is no experiment which will prove/disprove "Many Worlds".

PS: Shroedinger invented his cat puzzle because it was ridiculous. It was never intended as a serious problem for QM. Rather it is taking simple ideas to ridiculous extremes.
 
  • #3
UltrafastPED said:
Because none of it is observable. There is no experiment which will prove/disprove "Many Worlds".

PS: Shroedinger invented his cat puzzle because it was ridiculous. It was never intended as a serious problem for QM. Rather it is taking simple ideas to ridiculous extremes.

We've observed decoherence up to ridiculously large systems (I believe 45nm was confirmed recently?), why on Earth should we assume it doesn't apply all the way up?

Why would decoherence suddenly "end" just because a system gets large enough?

I feel like we should assume macroscopic decoherence until we see a counterexample. The math doesn't describe a point where decoherence stops happening; if we take schrodinger's equation at face value, then waves of amplitude *is* reality. Why postulate, on TOP of S's equation, that huge chunks of the wave get pruned away by an unknown, nonlocal, faster-than-light process?

Or are you going to wait for macroscopic decoherence to get verified at the 1mm level? The 1cm level?

What if your theory is right, but decoherence actually stops at, say, the 1km level, so we aren't actually large enough to collapse the wavefunction? Doesn't it seem suspicious to you that, in all three of these scenarios (macroscopic decoherence, decoherence stops at some point between an atom and a human, decoherence stops at some point larger than a human) we observe the same experimental outcome?

I guess my question is: what reason do scientists have for believing that, against the math, at some point of size decoherence no longer applies?
 
  • #5
The only real complaint I see listed on that page is that MWI doesn't explain the Born probabilities. This is true, but the Born probabilities are a mystery, not just for manyworlds, but for all interpretations, including Collapse interpretations. That is, the fact that we experience a given state by the squared modulus of that state's thickness in the wave is not *evidence against* manyworld.

In fact, that page pretty well defined my own stance: manyworlds are simply a part of Schrodinger's equation, period.

Are there any objections to macroscopic decoherence, other than the fact that it doesn't explain the Born probabilities?
 
Last edited:
  • #6
  • #7
The math doesn't describe a point where decoherence stops happening; if we take schrodinger's equation at face value, then waves of amplitude *is* reality.

Using this approach, bodies should interact instantaneously too, which contradicts electromagnetic theory and experience. To insist that every math concept of the theory has counterpart in the real world is unreasonable.
 
  • #8
Jano L. said:
Using this approach, bodies should interact instantaneously too, which contradicts electromagnetic theory and experience. To insist that every math concept of the theory has counterpart in the real world is unreasonable.

Huh? I don't see how this "approach" (taking the math at face value) says that bodies should interact instantaneously. Can you give me an example?

atyy said:
Decoherence is not an exact thing, so the branches of the many-worlds are not exact things (see eg. http://arxiv.org/abs/1111.2187 p12).

I just finished reading that paper... I don't quite understand what you're saying. QM as described by Schrodinger's Equation is deterministic; we know exactly how thick each slice is. This doesn't suggest that each Everette branch is clearly distinct from each other Everette branch; if this were the case, a single photon wouldn't be able to interfere with itself. I don't think I'm claiming that the branches are distinct, but when you get up to the macroscopic level of humans, there isn't really any interference from one branch to another (ie, the slice-of-the-wavefunction which is you-seeing-the-dead-cat doesn't causally affect the slice-of-the-wavefunction which is you-seeing-the-live-cat).

My question stands. In order to reject manyworlds, you must posit one of:
1) Once a system is large enough, where 'large' is defined as having a certain number of interacting particles, the system stops undergoing decoherence
1a) and usually we posit that "large enough" is somewhere between an atom and a human, so that we can cleanly state that we aren't constantly being split into multiple copies of ourselves
2) Observation/measurement acausally, faster-than-light, nonlocally, nonrelatively 'collapses' the wavefunction down to a single point.

Both of these points seem absurd to me (the first position seems isomorphic to the second in that it's magic, except dressed up in sciency-sounding terms), so what I'm asking is: are there any other reasons why one might disbelieve in macroscopic decoherence (ie manyworlds)?
 
Last edited:
  • #9
I don't understand why you equate decoherence and manyworlds!

p.s. From your first post I see that you use the word decoherence in a unorthodox way. Quantum mechanical systems do not decohere into superpositions.
 
  • #10
martinbn said:
I don't understand why you equate decoherence and manyworlds!

p.s. From your first post I see that you use the word decoherence in a unorthodox way. Quantum mechanical systems do not decohere into superpositions.

Decoherence is when two blobs of amplitude get separated from each other enough that their interaction approaches zero, correct? So if we have two particles whose positions are highly correlative of each other (either the particles are "both on the right" or "both on the left"), then they've decohered into two states: (Particle A - Left + Particle B - Left) * (Particle A - Right + Particle B - Right).

Now, there's still a very small 'probability' (a very very thin blob of amplitude) linking the two, such that we might end up observing Particle A going left and Particle B going right, but if the two blobs of amplitude are separated by enough space then the chance of us observing that is very slim, because the two blobs are decohered.

Now, if you add a human into the mix, a human observing the two particles, then the system becomes even *more* decohered, because the human brain's final state depends heavily on the state of the particles. So the new system is (Particle A Left + Particle B Left + Human Sees Left) * (Particle A Right + Particle B Right + Human Sees Right).

If the amplitude blobs that are what we think of as the particles can decohere, why can't the amplitude blobs that are what we think of as the two particles plus the human decohere?

In which case, Schrodinger's equation tells us that the particles have entered a superposition of L+L and R+R, and the human has entered a superposition of L and R, with some extremely thin/wispy/light-grey blobs of amplitude left over for stuff like R+L,R or R+R,L.

Edit: For clarification, the reason I am equating manyworlds with decoherence is that, when the 'possible state' of two particles (left and left, or, right and right) decoheres, anything that depends on the value of the state ends up on one side of the fence, or the other. Both possibilities, R+R and L+L, happen; the blobs of amplitude in configuration-space look exactly the same, there's no way to use math to figure out which one of them is "real" and which one of them "isn't real". In exactly the same way, if a human observes this system, then the human's final state is heavily dependent on the state of (R+R * L+L), because the two different states are no longer causally interacting with each other. If they were still causally interacting with each other (as in the dual slit experiment), then we would see both (as we do in the dual slit experiment). But they're not; they're decohered. Which means that the *new* state, instead of being (Particle A Left + Particle B Left) * (Particle A Right + Particle B Right), is (Particle A Left + Particle B Left + Human Observes Left) + (Particle A Right + Particle B Right + Human Observes Right).

There are two humans in that system! One of the humans observes the particles on the left, one of the humans observes the particles on the right, but Schrodinger's equation describes both humans equally well! and says nothing about which one is real. If the human in question believes in the collapse interpretation, then the Human in the amplitude-blob (Particle A Left + Particle B Left + Human Observes Left) thinks to himself, "Oh, so I collapsed the particles to the left and made that outcome 'real'." while the Human in the amplitude-blob (Particle A Right + Particle B Right + Human Observes Right) thinks to himself "Oh, so I collapsed the particles to the right and made that outcome 'real'."
 
Last edited:
  • #11
GofG said:
My question stands. In order to reject manyworlds, you must posit one of:
1) Once a system is large enough, where 'large' is defined as having a certain number of interacting particles, the system stops undergoing decoherence
1a) and usually we posit that "large enough" is somewhere between an atom and a human, so that we can cleanly state that we aren't constantly being split into multiple copies of ourselves
2) Observation/measurement acausally, faster-than-light, nonlocally, nonrelatively 'collapses' the wavefunction down to a single point.

That was not your question. Your question was why isn't many-worlds obviously correct. So the question was not about rejecting many-worlds, but about accepting many-worlds. There is no certainty that many-worlds us technically correct, even by proponents as shown in the above links by Sean Carroll and David Wallace.
 
  • #12
atyy said:
That was not your question. Your question was why isn't many-worlds obviously correct. So the question was not about rejecting many-worlds, but about accepting many-worlds. There is no certainty that many-worlds us technically correct, even by proponents as shown in the above links by Sean Carroll and David Wallace.

Sean Carroll says, in the page you linked:

Our only assumption was that the apparatus obeys the Rules of Quantum Mechanics just as much as the particle does, which seems to be an extremely mild assumption if we think quantum mechanics is the correct theory of reality. Given that, we know that the particle can be in “spin-up” or “spin-down” states, and we also know that the apparatus can be in “ready” or “measured spin-up” or “measured spin-down” states. And if that’s true, the quantum state has the built-in ability to describe superpositions of non-interacting worlds. Not only did we not need to add anything to make it possible, we had no choice in the matter. The potential for multiple worlds is always there in the quantum state, whether you like it or not.

Quantum mechanics *is* manyworlds. If you want to believe something other than many worlds, you have to add something to quantum mechanics, like a "collapse postulate".

So what I'm saying is, what evidence is there for adding something like a collapse postulate? Why should we add something to a theory that already perfectly describes our observations and experiences?

The "technical problems" for MWI that Sean Carroll describes are:

Sean Carroll said:
Why does the quantum state branch into certain kinds of worlds (e.g., ones where cats are awake or ones where cats are asleep) and not others (where cats are in superpositions of both)? Why are the probabilities that we actually observe given by the Born Rule, which states that the probability equals the wave function squared? In what sense are there probabilities at all, if the theory is completely deterministic?

He then goes on to say that the "Why certain kinds of worlds and not others" question is solved by pointer states, essentially by the fact that macroscopic systems are robust. The Born probability problem is tied closely with the "why probabilities at all" problem, and neither are solved by MWI, but adding stuff to MWI, like a collapse postulate, does not fix the problem. It's like saying "little angels come in and erase all of the worlds that aren't real in a manner consistent with the Born probabilities." It doesn't explain why the Born probabilities are what they are; from a Kolmogorov complexity standpoint, you've only made the theory more complicated without adding any additional predictive or explanatory power.
 
Last edited:
  • #13
GofG said:
Quantum mechanics *is* manyworlds. If you want to believe something other than many worlds, you have to add something to quantum mechanics, like a "collapse postulate".

So what I'm saying is, what evidence is there for adding something like a collapse postulate? Why should we add something to a theory that already perfectly describes our observations and experiences?

No, that's rubbish. Something equivalent to a collapse postulate is needed. That is standard Copenhagen. That is problematic, but a cheap claim that many-worlds obviously solves the problems does many-worlds a disfavour, considering the hard and serious work that people like Deutsch and Wallace have put in.
 
  • #14
What "problems" are you talking about? The Born probabilities? The Collapse postulate does not solve those either. By postulating collapse, you've added something new onto Schrodinger's equation that makes it strictly more complicated without increasing its predictive or explanatory value.

In order to explain the Born probabilities, we need to add something on which explains why the probability of experiencing a slice of the wavefunction is equal to the squared modulus of the thickness of that slice. It seems like our probability of experiencing a slice should just be equal to the thickness; that's what MWI predicts.

But adding on a collapse postulate that reads "when a system gets large enough, all of the blobs of amplitude except one are destroyed, in accordance with the Born probabilities" doesn't solve that problem. It doesn't explain why the Born probabilities are used, instead of something else. That's what I mean when I say it makes the theory strictly more complicated. The theory "Schrodinger's Equation + Born Probabilities" is the strictly simplest theory we have right now, and it implies manyworlds. If you want to *explain* the Born probabilities, and why they're different from what we'd expect them to be, then you can't do it by saying "Something does something, as per the Born probabilities" instead of just saying "The Born probabilities".

I'm not saying it's a complete theory, I'm just saying that basically everything postulated up until this point has been isomorphic to saying 'Little angels come along and destroy every blob of amplitude, selecting one blob to be the 'real' blob, based on the squared modulus of that blob's density'. Nothing has explained why the Born probabilities are used, instead of something else, like the straight thickness instead of squared thickness, or something completely ridiculous like "assign each distinct blob of amplitude a number based on its density, divide each blob's number by the total number of leaves on every tree in the universe, pick the third blob of amplitude whose density, when represented by a real number 0-10, has the third digit after the decimal point being 5."

There's a lot of possibilities for what the probabilities might be; the real question is why pick the squared modulus? And you're never going to solve that by tacking on a mechanism that uses the squared modulus, but could use some other criteria.
 
Last edited:
  • #15
GofG said:
And that's all Manyworlds is, is assuming that decoherence doesn't suddenly "stop" at macroscopic levels.

No, that's not the difference between Manyworlds and other interpretations. Other interpretations include decoherence too: they have to, because they have to explain why only certain alternatives are available for the wave function to collapse into. The difference with Manyworlds is that there is no collapse.
 
  • #16
Decoherence is part of the QM formalism. It is just good old fashioned physics. No one doubts the validity of decoherence as it is just a framework of calculations derived from standard QM. MWI is an interpretation of QM that uses decoherence but it is not the only interpretation that does so. MWI makes assumptions that are not derivable from QM in order to attempt an explanation of the measurement problem (but not the preferred basis problem). You seem to be conflating the two. MWI is no more valid than any other interpretation of QM that reproduces the predictions of QM and it is certainly not "self-evident" that MWI is the end all be all of the measurement problem.

So before you go about discussing MWI, you should first understand the difference between MWI (an interpretation) and decoherence (just physics of QM). A good place to start would be: http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0312059v4.pdf
 
  • #17
GofG said:
It seems like our probability of experiencing a slice should just be equal to the thickness; that's what MWI predicts.

I don't think MWI "predicts" this; I think MWI *assumes* this, without proof. But I don't see how the concept of "our probability of experiencing a slice" even makes sense in MWI, because in MWI, by definition, there is a copy of "us" that experiences each possible outcome of any quantum interaction. A particular copy, experiencing a particular outcome, has no way of testing, experimentally, what the relative "weight" of that outcome is, because there is no way of testing what other copies exist and "how much" of each copy exists.
 
  • #18
WannabeNewton said:
Decoherence is part of the QM formalism. It is just good old fashioned physics. No one doubts the validity of decoherence as it is just a derivation from standard QM. MWI is an interpretation of QM that uses decoherence but it is not the only interpretation that does so. MWI makes assumptions that are not derivable from QM in order to attempt an explanation of the measurement problem (but not the preferred basis problem). You seem to be conflating the two. MWI is no more valid than any other interpretation of QM that reproduces the predictions of QM and it is certainly not "self-evident" that MWI is the end all be all of the measurement problem. So before you go about discussing MWI, you should first understand the difference between MWI and decoherence.

Alright, I admit that decoherence does not equal manyworlds, but that's not what I'm saying.

I don't see how MWI makes any assumptions. It seems to cleanly solve the measurement problem (by saying that there is no collapse, and that there is a version of you who sees all possible outcomes) without postulating any additional assumptions. That is, if you take the state of a setup with a photon, a half-silvered mirror, a sensor, and a human observing the whole thing, then if you are only using Schrodingers Equation, then you end up with a description of two separate human brains, one in the state of observing the photon get reflected and one in the state of observing the photon go through the mirror. If you could input into Schrodinger's Equation the entire state of such an apparatus, including all of the particles in the brain, before the experiment, then it would output the total state of two brains. It is an additional assumption on top of this to assume that one of these brains is real, and the other isn't real.

Can you point me to where my assumption is?

PeterDonis said:
I don't think MWI "predicts" this; I think MWI *assumes* this, without proof. But I don't see how the concept of "our probability of experiencing a slice" even makes sense in MWI, because in MWI, by definition, there is a copy of "us" that experiences each possible outcome of any quantum interaction. A particular copy, experiencing a particular outcome, has no way of testing, experimentally, what the relative "weight" of that outcome is, because there is no way of testing what other copies exist and "how much" of each copy exists.

Even though different versions of you will experience every possible outcome of a given experiment, you can only experience one of those outcomes. This is simply due to the fact that our brains are built on macroscopic physics, and do not function as superpositions of themselves. I think you are confused about the meaning of the word "probability". If I am set up with a half-silvered mirror, a photon emitter, and two sensors, then I have specific rules as to how much I anticipate seeing the photon go left as opposed to go right. I call these differently-weighted anticipations "probabilities", and they are proportional to the density of the amplitude-blobs which describe those states.

PeterDonis said:
No, that's not the difference between Manyworlds and other interpretations. Other interpretations include decoherence too: they have to, because they have to explain why only certain alternatives are available for the wave function to collapse into. The difference with Manyworlds is that there is no collapse.

I am not saying that other interpretations don't have decoherence; I am saying that, for the most part, they describe some additional postulate whereby the various decohered blobs of amplitude collapse, such that one is made real (and that's the one you actually experience) and the rest are made unreal. Manyworlds simply says that you experience all of the amplitude blobs; that there is no level-of-complexity-or-largeness where collapse happens.
 
  • #19
GofG said:
Huh? I don't see how this "approach" (taking the math at face value) says that bodies should interact instantaneously. Can you give me an example?

Consider the Schroedinger equation for hydrogen atom

$$
\partial_t \Psi (\mathbf r_1, \mathbf r_2, t) = \frac{1}{i\hbar} \left(- \frac{\hbar^2}{2m_1}\Delta_1-\frac{\hbar^2}{2m_2}\Delta_2 - \frac{e^2}{4\pi \epsilon_0} \frac{1}{|\mathbf r_1 - \mathbf r_2|} \right) \Psi (\mathbf r_1,\mathbf r_2,t).
$$

Interaction of the electron with the proton is described by the last term in the bracket. If we wrote down similar equation for large many-particle system, there would be many such terms, but they are always functions of positions ##\mathbf r_1,...## only - there is no delay and no corresponding speed of interaction propagation, no matter how far the particles are.

Projecting this mathematical property of the equation onto the world one would claim that the interaction *is* instantaneous. But in fact, we know that electromagnetic interaction propagates with the speed of light. The electrostatic interaction term is just an approximation.

So be careful about applying mathematical theory in physics - not every mathematical property of the theory is physically valid.
 
  • #20
GofG said:
Even though different versions of you will experience every possible outcome of a given experiment, you can only experience one of those outcomes.

Well, sure; but that's not the problem. See below.

GofG said:
If I am set up with a half-silvered mirror, a photon emitter, and two sensors, then I have specific rules as to how much I anticipate seeing the photon go left as opposed to go right.

Yes, and in actual experiments, these anticipations, which are based on the Born rules, are borne out (pun sort of intended :wink:). But I don't see how to get them from the MWI, without *assuming* the Born rules. It seems to me that the MWI predicts that there are copies of me who experience *every possible sequence of outcomes* of, say, the half-silvered mirror experiment you describe; there should be some copy of me, for example, that experiences every single photon going left, even if the underlying amplitudes are equal for left and right.

In other words, if I use the MWI, I can't actually justify deducing amplitudes from observed frequencies, *unless* I add the Born rules as a postulate. Without the Born rules, if I see half the photons going left and half going right, the only thing I can deduce is that the underlying amplitude has *some* nonzero coefficient for both the left and the right state (because if either one were zero, I would only observe the other). But any pair of nonzero coefficients is consistent with what I observe, because any pair of nonzero coefficients will give rise to a "world" in which I observe half the photons going left and half going right. And, conversely, even if I see all the photons going left, I can't deduce that the underlying amplitude has a zero coefficient for the right state, because a state with, say, equal coefficients for both left and right would still give rise to a "world" in which I observed all the photons going left (as above).
 
  • #21
GofG said:
I don't see how MWI makes any assumptions...That is, if you take the state of a setup with a photon, a half-silvered mirror, a sensor, and a human observing the whole thing, then if you are only using Schrodingers Equation, then you end up with a description of two separate human brains, one in the state of observing the photon get reflected and one in the state of observing the photon go through the mirror.

How would you derive this from the basic formalism of QM? How would you experimentally verify it? You can't, so these are additional assumptions on top of the QM framework. As such, going back to the title of your OP, there is no way to verify if MWI is "obviously correct". What one can do is attempt to prove it wrong on a fundamental, theoretical level.

This has been established already but let me just reiterate that macroscopic decoherence is a prediction of QM that can be experimentally verified and is in fact fundamental in explaining why classical systems have a preferred set of bases and projection operators, why position and momentum are their main characterizations, and why they do not observationally exist in superpositions of these observables.
 
  • #22
Jano L. said:
Consider the Schroedinger equation for hydrogen atom

$$
\partial_t \Psi (\mathbf r_1, \mathbf r_2, t) = \frac{1}{i\hbar} \left(- \frac{\hbar^2}{2m_1}\Delta_1-\frac{\hbar^2}{2m_2}\Delta_2 - \frac{e^2}{4\pi \epsilon_0} \frac{1}{|\mathbf r_1 - \mathbf r_2|} \right) \Psi (\mathbf r_1,\mathbf r_2,t).
$$

Interaction of the electron with the proton is described by the last term in the bracket. If we wrote down similar equation for large many-particle system, there would be many such terms, but they are always functions of positions ##\mathbf r_1,...## only - there is no delay and no corresponding speed of interaction propagation, no matter how far the particles are.

Projecting this mathematical property of the equation onto the world one would claim that the interaction *is* instantaneous. But in fact, we know that electromagnetic interaction propagates with the speed of light. The electrostatic interaction term is just an approximation.

So be careful about applying mathematical theory in physics - not every mathematical property of the theory is physically valid.

That problem goes away in manyworlds, because the interactions aren't happening in real-time; when you interact with one of a pair of thusly-entangled particles, you aren't learning information about the other particle at a faster-than-light speed, and you aren't learning about any kind of "hidden variables" embedded in the particles which tell them, for instance, to what angle they are polarized.

Let's take two entangled photons, oppositely polarized. That is, we don't know how they're polarized, but we know that if Photon A goes through a 90deg filter then Photon B will go through a 0deg filter.

So we say: Photon A is (1 ; 0) and Photon B is (0 ; 1)

But it could also be the other way around; we just know they're entangled and opposite. We write that thusly:

[itex]\sqrt{1/2} * ( [ A=(1 ; 0) \wedge B=(0 ; 1) ] - [ A=(0 ; 1) \wedge B=(1 ; 0) ] )[/itex]

Now, if you measure Photon A's polarization, it decoheres the entanglement between the [0 ; 1] and [1 ; 0] blobs for A, because you can only experience one or the other. So if you find that A's polarization is [1 ; 0], then you know you're in the [itex][ A=(1 ; 0) \wedge B=(0 ; 1) ][/itex] blob of amplitude. This doesn't communicate information outside of your light cone, because you already knew that SOMEONE would be in the [1; 0] blob; it tells you which blob you're in. Similarly, it doesn't tell you anything about Photon B, because you already knew that SOMEONE would be in the B=[0 ; 1] blob. You couldn't use this to, say, make a one-time-pad with someone on the other end of a long stream of polarized entangled photons, because you're only finding out which blob you're in, not which blob they're in. If that isn't enough of an explanation, I can start talking about 30/60/90 polarization and how particular vectors of a photon are absorbed by the polarized film, but that would require a lot more knowledge of TeX than I have.
 
Last edited:
  • #23
PeterDonis said:
But I don't see how to get them from the MWI, without *assuming* the Born rules. It seems to me that the MWI predicts that there are copies of me who experience *every possible sequence of outcomes* of, say, the half-silvered mirror experiment you describe; there should be some copy of me, for example, that experiences every single photon going left, even if the underlying amplitudes are equal for left and right.

In other words, if I use the MWI, I can't actually justify deducing amplitudes from observed frequencies, *unless* I add the Born rules as a postulate. Without the Born rules, if I see half the photons going left and half going right, the only thing I can deduce is that the underlying amplitude has *some* nonzero coefficient for both the left and the right state (because if either one were zero, I would only observe the other). But any pair of nonzero coefficients is consistent with what I observe, because any pair of nonzero coefficients will give rise to a "world" in which I observe half the photons going left and half going right. And, conversely, even if I see all the photons going left, I can't deduce that the underlying amplitude has a zero coefficient for the right state, because a state with, say, equal coefficients for both left and right would still give rise to a "world" in which I observed all the photons going left (as above).

Huh? There is no blob of amplitude which represents a brain that perceives a single photon going both left and right; that's what decoherence means. If the two states of the photon, the two blobs of amplitude (one at RIGHT and one at LEFT) are decohered, then the two brains that observe the two states are also decohered. Manyworlds simply says that both of those brains exist, not that there is some brain which experiences both.

WannabeNewton said:
How would you derive this from the basic formalism of QM? How would you experimentally verify it? You can't, so these are additional assumptions on top of the QM framework. As such, going back to the title of your OP, there is no way to verify if MWI is "obviously correct". What one can do is attempt to prove it wrong on a fundamental, theoretical level.

This has been established already but let me just reiterate that macroscopic decoherence is a prediction of QM that can be experimentally verified and is in fact fundamental in explaining why classical systems have a preferred set of bases and projection operators, why position and momentum are their main characterizations, and why they do not observationally exist in superpositions of these observables.

You cannot derive the Born probabilities from Schrodinger's equation; this is a legitimate problem. Schrodinger's equation implies manyworlds, but does not imply the Born probabilities. I have never argued against this. However, none of the other interpretations imply the Born probabilities either. My current hypothesis is "Schrodinger's Equation + Born Probabilities". The Collapse interpretation is "Schrodinger's Equation + Mechanism that deletes blobs of amplitude according to Born probabilities".

I am certainly not saying that MWI demonstrates how the Born probabilities came to be; what I am saying is that this is not a flaw of MWI but a flaw of quantum mechanics in general, and there are no interpretations which get rid of it. That is, adding a collapse postulate doesn't do any better job of explaining the Born probabilities than just plain old MWI does.

Now, at some point we will discover the reason for the Born probabilities. Whatever the reason is, I seriously doubt it will be some mechanism which deletes blobs of amplitude from consideration which is, for some reason, biased towards using Born probabilities. If we can find some mechanism for which it would make sense to use the Born probabilities instead of other possible alternatives, then such might be a candidate for an explanation. But a collapse postulate that declares the Born probabilities explicitly, instead of implicitly, isn't an explanation.
 
  • #24
GofG said:
There is no blob of amplitude which represents a brain that perceives a single photon going both left and right

I didn't say there was. I'm talking about repeated runs of the experiment. Say we run the experiment ten times; then there is a blob of amplitude representing ten photons all going left, and a brain perceiving that ten photons have gone left. And that's true regardless of what the underlying coefficients for the left and right states are, as long as the coefficient of the left state is nonzero. Also, if we run the experiment ten times, there will be a blob of amplitude where five photons go left and five go right, and a brain perceives that five have gone left and five have gone right, for *any* combination of coefficients of the underlying left and right states as long as both are nonzero.

GofG said:
My current hypothesis is "Schrodinger's Equation + Born Probabilities". The Collapse interpretation is "Schrodinger's Equation + Mechanism that deletes blobs of amplitude according to Born probabilities".

First of all, if this is your position, then it's not correct to say "QM just is manyworlds", when you're defining "QM" as the Schrodinger equation (which you have to, since the Schrodinger equation is the only common feature of all the different interpretations). You're adding a postulate to "QM" to get MWI, just as the collapse interpretation adds a postulate to "QM".

Second, I think you've mis-stated your hypothesis: I would state it as "Schrodinger's equation + Born rules for interpreting amplitudes". You can't call them "probabilities" because all the possible outcomes happen, so there are no "probabilities" of one outcome happening rather than the other.
 
  • #25
Jano L. said:
Consider the Schroedinger equation for hydrogen atom

$$
\partial_t \Psi (\mathbf r_1, \mathbf r_2, t) = \frac{1}{i\hbar} \left(- \frac{\hbar^2}{2m_1}\Delta_1-\frac{\hbar^2}{2m_2}\Delta_2 - \frac{e^2}{4\pi \epsilon_0} \frac{1}{|\mathbf r_1 - \mathbf r_2|} \right) \Psi (\mathbf r_1,\mathbf r_2,t).
$$

Interaction of the electron with the proton is described by the last term in the bracket. If we wrote down similar equation for large many-particle system, there would be many such terms, but they are always functions of positions ##\mathbf r_1,...## only - there is no delay and no corresponding speed of interaction propagation, no matter how far the particles are.

Projecting this mathematical property of the equation onto the world one would claim that the interaction *is* instantaneous. But in fact, we know that electromagnetic interaction propagates with the speed of light. The electrostatic interaction term is just an approximation.

So be careful about applying mathematical theory in physics - not every mathematical property of the theory is physically valid.

I just realized that you're not talking about the usual Bell's Theorem-style problem. You're simply talking about regular old particle interactions.

The thing is, for Schrodinger's equation to describe p1 and p2 (the proton and the electron), then they have to already be entangled. If they're already entangled, then there's no faster-than-light causality; the interactions which affect the pair happened in the past.

Suppose two photon-waves are approaching each other in space. As time moves forward, they get closer (ignoring relativity for now). At some point, they start interacting. This point happens when the outmost-reaching part of Photon A's wave touches the outmost-reaching part of Photon B's wave. Up until that point, the two particles are not entangled, but at that point, they are. But nothing in this situation implies FTL signaling; nothing is nonlocal. The two particles can't affect each other until their waves are actually touching.
 
  • #26
PeterDonis said:
I didn't say there was. I'm talking about repeated runs of the experiment. Say we run the experiment ten times; then there is a blob of amplitude representing ten photons all going left, and a brain perceiving that ten photons have gone left. And that's true regardless of what the underlying coefficients for the left and right states are, as long as the coefficient of the left state is nonzero.

Then what exactly was your complaint?


First of all, if this is your position, then it's not correct to say "QM just is manyworlds", when you're defining "QM" as the Schrodinger equation (which you have to, since the Schrodinger equation is the only common feature of all the different interpretations). You're adding a postulate to "QM" to get MWI, just as the collapse interpretation adds a postulate to "QM".

What is that postulate?

Second, I think you've mis-stated your hypothesis: I would state it as "Schrodinger's equation + Born rules for interpreting amplitudes". You can't call them "probabilities" because all the possible outcomes happen, so there are no "probabilities" of one outcome happening rather than the other.

This comes from a disagreement over the definition of the word "probability". I'm a Bayesian, not a frequentist, so I use the word "probability" to describe my uncertainty as to what I'm going to experience, not the behavior of some object as time approaches infinity. That said, regardless of what definitions we're using, we're not disagreeing about anything that's happening out there in the universe. If I'm going to be put into an artificial coma, and then they'll flip a quantum coin, and if it's heads they'll wake me up in a room with red walls, while tails means green walls, then I'll attribute a 50% "probability" to seeing red walls when I wake up, and a 50% "probability" to seeing green walls; but really, since I experience both, what I am doing is *dividing up my uncertainty as to what I should anticipate*. This "uncertainty about anticipation" thing works very similarly to probability, so similarly that all of the rules about how to manipulate it are exactly the same as the rules you use to manipulate probability, so I'm going to go ahead and keep referring to it as probability, even though it isn't (since MWI is deterministic).
 
  • #27
GofG said:
First, Schrodinger's Cat:

Photon emitter, pointed at a half-silvered mirror, such that 50% of the wave hits a sensor that activates a gaseous poison emitter inside a box that has a cat in it.

Standardly, we think about it this way: the photon hits the halfsilvered mirror and decoheres into a superposition of "straight" and "reflected", then the sensor decoheres into a superposition of "hit" or "not hit", then the poison emitter decoheres into a superposition of "activated" or "not activated", then the cat decoheres into a superposition of "dead" or "alive"... so the cat is both dead and alive, etc.

Isn't it obvious that upon opening the box, the human decoheres into a superposition of "sees an alive cat" and "sees a dead cat"?

Isn't that blindingly obvious? If the cat can decohere, why can't the human?

And that's all Manyworlds is, is assuming that decoherence doesn't suddenly "stop" at macroscopic levels.

Can someone explain to me why this isn't selfevident?

As already mentioned, we don't see any other worlds. So that is one explanation.

Now, you preface by saying "First, Schrodinger's Cat". So this point may not be fair. But MWI does not explain certain elements of entanglement, namely entanglement swapping where the particles are entangled AFTER detection. In MWI, the worlds would have already split into the results (showing entanglement) BEFORE they have even interacted. So how is that supposed to occur?

(And I know MWIers will hand-wave it, but I think it is a legitimate question.)
 
  • #28
DrChinese said:
But MWI does not explain certain elements of entanglement, namely entanglement swapping where the particles are entangled AFTER detection.

What do you mean by this? Can you give me an example in terms of, say, polarized photons?
 
  • #29
If some particle have the probility of be in two place at once its mean he feel hiyer dimension , and feel many world like two world are his reality
 
  • #30
GofG said:
Then what exactly was your complaint?

See below.

GofG said:
What is that postulate?

You are assuming that you can interpret the amplitudes appearing in the Schrodinger equation as "probabilities" (see below for more on that word). But the Schrodinger equation doesn't tell you that by itself. The Schrodinger equation tells you that, for example, if we run the photon experiment ten times, there will be a blob of amplitude where all ten photons go left (and the brain perceives all ten photons going left)--and a blob where all ten photons go right--and a blob for every other possible combination of results of the ten runs (i.e., 1024 blobs in all). It does *not* tell you that there is a 50-50 chance of a given photon going left or right. That requires an extra postulate.

GofG said:
I'm a Bayesian, not a frequentist, so I use the word "probability" to describe my uncertainty as to what I'm going to experience, not the behavior of some object as time approaches infinity.

I tend to be a Bayesian too (and I agree with your description of how a Bayesian would use QM to derive anticipations about future observations), but that doesn't mean Bayesians get to dictate all uses of the word "probability". As that word is used in the phrase "Born probabilities", it refers to predicted relative frequencies, not epistemic uncertainty on the part of observers. That's because comparing predicted relative frequences with actually observed relative frequencies is how we experimentally test QM.
 
  • #31
GofG said:
Why would decoherence suddenly "end" just because a system gets large enough?

It doesn't - it simply happens so quick you never notice it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #32
martinbn said:
I don't understand why you equate decoherence and manyworlds!

Indeed.

Many interpretations such as Consistent Histories and Ignorance ensemble use it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #33
PeterDonis said:
It does *not* tell you that there is a 50-50 chance of a given photon going left or right. That requires an extra postulate.

Yes: that postulate is the Born probabilities, which state that the probability of experiencing a given brain is equal to the squared modulus of the thickness/density of that brain's amplitude blob. I have already admitted to this postulate.

But what is built-in to Schrodinger's equation is the fact that each brain is just as real as each other brain; that is, from within Schrodinger's equation, there is no mechanism for collapsing down into one brain.

Schrodinger's equation gives me the density/thickness of a particular blob, and the Born probabilities tell me how to turn that density/thickness into a subjective anticipation/probability.

I tend to be a Bayesian too (and I agree with your description of how a Bayesian would use QM to derive anticipations about future observations), but that doesn't mean Bayesians get to dictate all uses of the word "probability". As that word is used in the phrase "Born probabilities", it refers to predicted relative frequencies, not epistemic uncertainty on the part of observers. That's because comparing predicted relative frequences with actually observed relative frequencies is how we experimentally test QM.

But my epistemic uncertainty reflects exactly the predicted relative frequencies; it's a 1:1 mapping, they're isomorphic. I am translating the predicted frequencies, as given by Schrodinger and Born, into subjective anticipations, as given by Bayes. I don't think there's anything wrong with this?
 
  • #34
GofG said:
What do you mean by this? Can you give me an example in terms of, say, polarized photons?

Sure, check this article:

http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0201134

Experimental Nonlocality Proof of Quantum Teleportation and Entanglement Swapping
Thomas Jennewein, Gregor Weihs, Jian-Wei Pan, Anton Zeilinger
(Submitted on 29 Jan 2002)

"Quantum teleportation strikingly underlines the peculiar features of the quantum world. We present an experimental proof of its quantum nature, teleporting an entangled photon with such high quality that the nonlocal quantum correlations with its original partner photon are preserved. This procedure is also known as entanglement swapping. The nonlocality is confirmed by observing a violation of Bell's inequality by 4.5 standard deviations. Thus, by demonstrating quantum nonlocality for photons that never interacted our results directly confirm the quantum nature of teleportation. "

And note on page 5: "Therefore, this result indicate that the time ordering of the detection
events has no influence..." Alice (in this case acting after Bob has seen his results) is in a world and decides to entangle the 2 particles via entanglement swapping using her Bell State Analyzer (BSA). How does that world know to connect the outcomes of these 2 independent (at this point) photons so as to make sense of what Bob already saw? Keep in mind that the angle setting of her BSA need have no relationship to the angles Bob is measuring at, and could be at a 45 degree angle relative to Bob's. So presumably collapse for the 2 photons has already occurred when they arrive at Alice's BSA. Why should anything related to entanglement of Bob's photons even occur?
 
  • #35
bhobba said:
It doesn't - it simply happens so quick you never notice it.

Thanks
Bill

But if the decoherence happens, if it doesn't end, then there are two brains, both experiencing different things. One experiences the photon going left, one experiences the photon going right. Both of those brains are real, both of those brains are actually experiencing the events. That's manyworlds.
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
5
Replies
143
Views
6K
Replies
15
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
47
Views
4K
Replies
51
Views
4K
Replies
6
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
3
Replies
72
Views
6K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
5
Views
665
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
1K
Back
Top