Difficulty with "Exists" & "Let" or "Arbitrary"

  • Thread starter Thread starter CGandC
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Difficulty
CGandC
Messages
326
Reaction score
34
1. when writing a proof, I stumbled upon cases where I wondered if the following two are equivalent?:
a. " There exists ## n \in N ## such that ___ "
b. " Let ## n \in N ## be arbitrary such that ___"

Are these statements the same? Is ## n ## in both of them the same?

2. Suppose I have the following set
1604320047390.png

And I want to prove that there exists a real number ## m ## such that for all ## a \in C ## it is satisfied that ## a \leq m ##.
So writing of the proof goes as follows:
We'll take ## 2 \in R ##. Let ## b \in C ## , meaning there exists ## n \in N ## such that ## b = \frac{n+1}{2^n} ## . So we'll prove that ## \frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2 ## .

I saw in the answers that the proof of ## \frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2 ## is done with induction on ## n ##.

The question is: how is it possible to do proof by induction on ## n ## here if in the writing of the proof I said " there exists ## n \in N ## " and not " arbitrary ## n \in N ## " or " Let ## n \in N ## "?
I know that I do proof by induction if I have a claim such as ## \forall n \in N. P(n) ##. But here in the writing of the proof I have a claim of ## \exists n \in N. P(n) ## which I have to prove, which isn't the same as the previous claim.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
CGandC said:
1. when writing a proof, I stumbled upon cases where I wondered if the following two are equivalent?:
a. " There exists ## n \in N ## such that ___ "
b. " Let ## n \in N ## be arbitrary such that ___"

Are these statements the same? Is ## n ## in both of them the same?
No. T´hey are not.

The existence quantor means: there is one instance, as in "there exists a natural number which is divisible by 3 and 1 only.

Let there be (an arbitrary) is the all quantor. It means e.g.: Given an arbitrary natural number ##n##, there is another natural number ##n+1## following ##n##. Since we haven't assumed any restrictions on ##n## other than being a natural number, this implies that it is true for all natural numbers. ##n## here is a place holder for any, or all. In the previous example, only ##n=3## satisfied the condition.
2. Suppose I have the following set View attachment 272036
And I want to prove that there exists a real number ## m ## such that for all ## a \in C ## it is satisfied that ## a \leq m ##.
So writing of the proof goes as follows:
We'll take ## 2 \in R ##. Let ## b \in C ## , meaning there exists ## n \in N ## such that ## b = \frac{n+1}{2^n} ## . So we'll prove that ## \frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2 ## .
You should have highlighted meaning! We have given any ##b\in C##. This means we do not pose any restrictions on ##b##. Nevertheless, and all we know is, that it is contained in ##C##. This means that ##b## is of the form ##\dfrac{n+1}{2^n}## for some ##n\in \mathbb{N}##, since all members of ##C## look this way. We have not determined which one in ##C##, except that we've arbitrarily chosen one of them to work with, which we called ##b##.
I saw in the answers that the proof of ## \frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2 ## is done with induction on ## n ##.

The question is: how is it possible to do proof by induction on ## n ## here if in the writing of the proof I said " there exists ## n \in N ## "
and not " arbitrary ## n \in N ## " or " Let ## n \in N ## "?
There exists an ##n## refers to the shape of the elements we are talking about, not a specific one. This makes ##n## arbitrary in the induction proof, and specified if we talk about ##b##. It would had been better to write ##b(n)= \dfrac{n+1}{2^n}\in C## to demonstrate that ##b## is parametrized or labelled by ##n##. However, ##b(n)## and therewith ##n## were arbitrary. Only the shape was specified. The same was true in my examples under point ##1)##. ##3## is also divisible by ##-3## and ##-1## but we were talking about natural numbers only. The same happens here: we are talking about ##C## only, which makes ##b=b(n)## arbitrary except for its shape. The label ##b## is only given in order that we can address those elements, as we address natural numbers by ##n##.
I know that I do proof by induction if I have a claim such as ## \forall n \in N. P(n) ##. But here in the writing of the proof I have a claim of ## \exists n \in N. P(n) ## which I have to prove, which isn't the same as the previous claim.
I'm a little afraid that this explanation might have confused you a bit. If so, please ask. And btw., you are right: it would have been better if we used logical symbols:
$$
\forall \,b\in C\, : \, b<2\in \mathbb{R} \Longleftrightarrow \forall\, b(n)\in C\, : \,b<2\Longleftrightarrow \forall \, n\in \mathbb{N}\, : \,P(n) \Longleftrightarrow \forall \,n\in \mathbb{N} \, : \, \dfrac{n+1}{2^n}<2
$$
 
  • Like
Likes CGandC
CGandC said:
1. when writing a proof, I stumbled upon cases where I wondered if the following two are equivalent?:
a. " There exists n∈N such that ___ "
b. " Let n∈N be arbitrary such that ___"
Are these statements the same?
As already stated, no they are not the same. In the first, it is asserted that there is a specific number n that satisfies the given condition, and possibly others as well.
In the second, any integer n will satisfy the given condition.
 
CGandC said:
1. when writing a proof, I stumbled upon cases where I wondered if the following two are equivalent?:
a. " There exists ## n \in N ## such that ___ "
b. " Let ## n \in N ## be arbitrary such that ___"

Are these statements the same? Is ## n ## in both of them the same?
They're not the same ##-##

the statement

##\exists n [(n \in \mathbb N) \wedge Pn]##

means that there is at least one natural number ##n## that has property P,

while the statement

##\forall n [(n \in \mathbb N) \Rightarrow Pn]##

means that every natural number ##n## has property P.
2. Suppose I have the following set

1604338094775.png


And I want to prove that there exists a real number ## m ## such that for all ## a \in C ## it is satisfied that ## a \leq m ##.
Symbolizing what you posit as to be proven:

##\exists m [(m \in \mathbb R) \wedge (\forall a [(a\in C) \Rightarrow (a \leq m)]##,

then, noting that in the expression defining membership in ##C##, the numbers generating the values for ##a \in C## are the natural numbers ## n \in \mathbb N##, and as we ascend through the natural numbers, beginning with ##n=1## we get:

## \frac {(1+1)^2} {2^1} = \frac {2^2} {2^1} = \frac 4 2 = 2##,

and:

##(n=2) \rightarrow (a =\frac {3^2} {2^2} = \frac 9 4 = 2.25)##,

but after ##n=2##, the divisor grows faster than the dividend, so the quotient decreases for every natural number greater than 2:

##(n = 3) \rightarrow (a= \frac {16} 8 = 2)##,

##(n=4) \rightarrow (a= \frac {25} {16} = 1.5625)##,

##(n = 5) \rightarrow (a= \frac {36} {32} = 1.125)##,

(at ##n=6## the fraction is no longer top-heavy:)

##(n = 6) \rightarrow (a= \frac {49} {64} = 0.756625)##,

##(n = 7) \rightarrow (a= \frac {64} {128} = \frac 1 2 = 0.5)##,

##(n = 8) \rightarrow (a= \frac {81} {256} = 0.31640625)##,

##(n=9) \rightarrow (a= \frac {100} {512} = 0.1953125)##,

##(n=10) \rightarrow (a=\frac {121} {1024} = 0.1181640625##

So it's clear that for greater values than ##2##, with the divisor continuing to double, while the dividend continues to be a ##1##-greater number squared, the ##2.25## value of ##a## when ##n=2## can only diminish for ##n>2##, and that's the mathematical induction step (informally stated) that justifies the conclusion that

##\exists m [(m \in \mathbb R) \wedge (\forall a [(a\in C) \Rightarrow (a \leq m)]##;

however, if we take the problem as it is here stated, then because the problem statement calls for a real number ##m##, and the highest value we can get for ##a## that is generated by a natural number ##n## is 2.25 , which occurs when ##n=2##, the correct answer cannot be ##m=2##; instead, the correct answer would be ##m=2.25##,.
So writing of the proof goes as follows:
We'll take ## 2 \in R ##. Let ## b \in C ## , meaning there exists ## n \in N ## such that ## b = \frac{n+1}{2^n} ## . So we'll prove that ## \frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2 ## .
Your prior statement of the problem clearly calls for the universal quantifier for ##n## here; not for the existential quantifier:
And I want to prove that there exists a real number ## m ## such that for all ## a \in C ## it is satisfied that ## a \leq m ##.
(emphasis added)

All members ##a \in C## are produced, respectively, by all members ##n \in \mathbb N.
I saw in the answers that the proof of ## \frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2 ## is done with induction on ## n ##.
That statement is true if and only if ##n## is not equal to ##2##, i.e. when ##n=1##, ##a=2##; when ##n=2##, ##a=2.25##; as ##n## increases after that, ##a## decreases ##-## when ##n=3##, ##a=2##, with further diminution of ##a## for all further incrementations of ##n##.

So:

##((n \in \mathbb N) \wedge (\frac{n+1}{2^n} \leq 2)) \iff \neg(n=2)##

I think that there may be some confusion regarding whether the quarry is ##m=n=2##, i.e ##m## is equal to the natural number ##n## by which the greatest number ##a \in C## is generated, i.e. ##m=2## or rather is, as the problem as statement appears to call for, the real number ##m## to which the greatest ##a \in C## is less than or equal, i.e. ##m=2.25##, which is generated when ##n=2##.
The question is: how is it possible to do proof by induction on ## n ## here if in the writing of the proof I said " there exists ## n \in N ## " and not " arbitrary ## n \in N ## " or " Let ## n \in N ## "?
The problem statement uses both types of quantifier: there exists a real number ##m## such that for all ##a \in C##, ##a \le m##.
I know that I do proof by induction if I have a claim such as ## \forall n \in N. P(n) ##. But here in the writing of the proof I have a claim of ## \exists n \in N. P(n) ## which I have to prove, which isn't the same as the previous claim.
Please post the problem and answer exactly as you encountered it.
 
The major difference between 1. and 2. is that 1. is a sentence (with some truth value), while 2) is not.

When we say: "Let n be [something] satisfying P(n)" for some proposition P, we are not positing anything.

In a proof by induction, the goal is to prove A: P(1) and B: P(n) \Rightarrow P(n+1). For B, one usually starts out with "Let n be [something] satisfying P(n)". Note that in your example (the one with "let b \in C, there exists n \in N [...]"), you're not formulating the beginning of the proof of the inductive step. The inductive step is as follows:

Let n \in N be some positive integer satisfying \frac{(n+1)^2}{2^n} \leq 2. We are not positing that something is true (in fact, it's not meaningful to assign any truth value to it when n is indeterminate). We are rather supposing it to be true for an indeterminate n for the sake of proving P(n) \Rightarrow P(n+1). To complete the proof of the inductive step, prove that \frac{((n+1)+1)^2}{2^{n+1}} \leq 2.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes CGandC
I believe there is a significant gap in the availability of resources that emphasize the underlying logic of abstract mathematical concepts. While tools such as Desmos and GeoGebra are valuable for graphical visualization, they often fall short in fostering a deeper, intuitive understanding. Visualisation, in this sense, should go beyond plotting functions and instead aim to reveal the reasoning and common-sense foundations of the concept. For example, on YouTube one can find an excellent...

Similar threads

Replies
10
Views
3K
Replies
1
Views
3K
Replies
23
Views
3K
Replies
6
Views
3K
Replies
8
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
2K
Replies
0
Views
2K
Back
Top