audioloop said:
"Our second observation has to do with the quantum measurement problem. As is known,
during such a measurement, the quantum system makes a transition from being in a superposition of eigenstates of the measured observable, to being in one of the eigenstates, and the probability of any given outcome is proportional to the square of the amplitude for the wave function to be in that state. If we assume that this transition happens within the framework of standard linear quantum mechanics, then it is explained by the phenomenon of decoherence, in conjunction with the Everett many worlds interpretation. Decoherence destroys interference amongst the various superposed alternatives, while still preserving their superposition. However, since we observe only one of the alternatives in an outcome, we must invoke also the branching of the Universe into many worlds, at the time of a measurement, so that the quantum system, apparatus, and observer, all split into dierent branches, one branch for every alternative."
There is a prevalent language problem exemplified by this author which seeps into ones attempt to understand the issues. Let me key specifically on
"the quantum system makes a transition from being in a superposition of eigenstates of the measured observable, to being in one of the eigenstates"
This transition is not physical --in and of itself-- in that the qualities of "being in a superposition of eigenstates" vs "being in one eigenstate" are not observable properties of the system. Of course "being in a specific eigenstate" is exactly the statement that the system has been observed but the comparison between "spooky superposition" vs "sensible objective non-superposition" is not a physical distinction. To say a system is in superposition of states of one observable one must specify effectively that the system is in a specific "sensible objective non-superposition" eigen-state of another (complementary) observable.
The system is always in in the eigen-state of some observable when we are describing it with wave-functions or more generally Hilbert space vectors.
Everyone contemplating quantum mechanics should focus and meditate on this one point until it is clear, superposition is not a physical property of a system, it is a relationship between observables, the fact that they are not compatible but rather complementary.
Get this clear and then re-parse the Schrodinger Cat experiment, asking yourselves a question at the point in the narrative where the cat is hypothesized to be in a superposition.
Of what complementary observable is the cat then in an eigenstate?
To attempt to answer this question we must and may go back and describe the observable for which the original decaying atom was in an eigenstate when asserted to be in a superposition of whole and decayed. It is out there just not easy to describe in terms of laboratory procedures. One would then take the dynamics and evolve this complementary observable forward in time to find its future equivalent. But in expanding the system to describe atom plus cat you are left with the impossibility of describing a living cat in a sharp initial state. The very concept of "alive" precludes the absolute zero temperature and zero entropy assumption when using a sharp description.
We must thus invoke a density operator format.
Now as to density operators and decoherence... let me point out that at one end you have a density operator constructed (mathematically) using classical probabilities. It thus has the same semantic status as a classical probability distribution in that it is not describing/modeling the system's state of reality but rather potential behavior when subject to an act of observation. I can speak of the outcome of a coin flip (before the flip!) as a 50%-50% "classical superposition" of heads vs tails and we all know the coin is not physically in a "cloud of probability" but rather that --languagewise-- I am speaking in the hypothetical mode. Now understanding that as the
semantic meaning of the density operator at the end of the decoherence process, it is improper for us to change that semantic meaning along the described dynamic evolution. We must for the purposes of being consistent and clear, maintain that semantic interpretation of the density operator at the beginning when it is e.g. equivalently (to a hilbert space vector) expressing a system in a sharp "state". (Hence a better word is "sharp mode" as in mode of system production.)
Note that this does not argue that the sharp modes cannot be given alternative, metaphysical interpretation (though I assert this with other facts does imply such) it does however tell us that this is not the interpretation, the semantic meaning of the density operator and hence the quantum mechanics of the Schodinger's cat experiment and parallel thought experiments. And that my dears, plus the above hinted at assertion that no additional metaphysical interpretation is meaningful, is Copenhagen in a (moderately large) nutshell.
With CI there is no "measurement problem" or "Schrodinger's Cat" problem. Decoherence is de-coherence as in it is not iterpretationally distinct from classical "decorrelation". No other (metaphysical) interpretation can resolve the Schrodinger's Cat scenario any better than does CI. CI's explanation is the only explanation because no explanation can properly ignore this need for consistent unchanging meaning of the density operator when it is invoked in this instance nor deny the classical meaning of probabilities as limiting relative frequencies for non-actualized potential outcomes. One is committed to remaining in the hypothetical mode for the duration of the exposition.*
"IF we measure A, we see a1 with probablity p1 and ..."
(* or one must present a very explicit and very rigorous treatment of the transition to actual mode. I think this is best done by using a wholly distinct set of words/symbols. Something like \hat{\psi} for a "metaphysical" wave function and \tilde{\psi} for a "statistical" wave function, if these are what you want to invoke.)