I would like to argue about .999

  • Thread starter Curd
  • Start date
In summary: Basically, the proof is showing that the infinite sum of .9 repeating (or .999...) can be written as a fraction in the form of 1/9 (or 1/10). And we know that 1/9 (or 1/10) is equal to .111... (or .10000...), so that means the infinite sum of .9 repeating is equal to .111... (or .10000...). And since .111... (or .10000...) is equal to 1, that means .999... is equal to 1.I hope that makes sense. It's a pretty complex proof, so it might take some time to fully understand. In summary, the conversation
  • #1
Curd
78
1
In response to the below quote I have written this. The idea that arguing is "spreading misinformation" is ridiculous as argument is the prime mover behind the evolution of the general intelligence of humanity as a whole. If that's the sort of attitude this forum carries with it though, fine, I'll leave. I came here to become educated, not merely indoctrinated. (education being something highly dependent on the dialogue created by argument and indoctrination being something highly dependent on the lack of dialogue created by argument). So, I submit the below in an attempt to meet out my expectations of education. Whether I get such education by means of knowing more about the world or more about the current subject, .999... will depend on the reaction I get.

So, here goes...


Hurkyl said:
(moderator's note: I've removed someone asserting that 0.999... is not equal to one, along with the followups)



decimals of fractions never accurately equal those fractions. for example .111111111111111...never fully equals 1/9 (which applies directly to a certain proof) but for practical purposes you can assume it does.

.999999... never equals one. (i still find it hard to believe that saying that warrants an infraction). as the decimal points increase onto infinity the space between 1 and .9999... becomes smaller, but the two never do connect to equal the exact same number. there is an infinite number of spaces to which decimals can extend (as noted by pie), so there is no reason for .999999999... ever to change to one.

you can argue that .9999999 REPRESENTS one in the language system you happen to be using, but .99999... will never actually equal one in real life.

let's say you want to count all of the entities (particles, doodads, whatever) in the universe in relation to the whole. we will represent the whole with 1. once you have accounted for every item within the universe, let's represent each such item with a 9 after the decimal point, you have counted the whole of it and achieved accounting for 1 universe. since the universe expands on forever, the actual ability to do such a thing does not exist. therefore you can continue on counting 9's in .99999... without ever actually achieving 1.

If you were to say otherwise you would have to also say that infinity is impossible, and ergo pie would be impossible (along with other things). as it is a fact that the 9's after the decimal point can go on into infinity it is also a fact that .999... never equals one except for practical purposes in which such fine details are not important.

and as for that argument by Hurkyl that I'm "spreading misinformation"

and spreading misinformation? so, you're saying that the losing party to any argument is "spreading misinformation"? how ever is one to have conversations on topics if one is to always be correct (i'm not saying I'm wrong by arguing this by the way), when being incorrect is "spreading misinformation"?

who is the owner of this forum? i would very much like to take this up with them.
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Here's a proof that .999...=1.

.999... can be written as the infinite sum as follows:

[tex].9 + .09 + .009 + .0009 + .00009 + ... = .9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n[/tex]

Now, evaluating the sum on the right, we use the fact (proven below) that...

[tex]\sum_{n=0}^\infty r^n = \frac{1}{1-r}[/tex]

for all r with a magnitude less than 1. Using this fact, we find that...

[tex].9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n = .9 \frac{1}{1-.1} = \frac{.9}{.9}=1[/tex]

Now, to prove that fact that we used, note the proof below:

[tex]S = \sum_{k=0}^{n-1} a r^k = a + a r + a r^2 + a r^3 + a r^4 + ... + a r^{n-1}[/tex]

[tex]rS = a r + a r^2 + a r^3 + a r^4 + a r^5 + ... + a r^n[/tex]

[tex]S - rS = a - a r^n = a (1 - r^n)[/tex]

[tex]S(1-r) = a (1 - r^n)[/tex]

[tex]S = \frac{a (1-r^n)}{1-r}[/tex]

Now let n go to infinity. For r with a magnitude less than 1, r^n tends to 0 as n tends to infinity. Thus...

[tex]\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} S = \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \frac{a (1-r^n)}{1-r} = \frac{a}{1-r}[/tex]

Q E D
 
Last edited:
  • #3
More correctly, that holds as long as [itex]|r|<1[/itex].

Might also help to add the step [tex]S = \sum_{k = 0}^{n-1} ar^k[/tex] or similar...
 
  • #4
Char. Limit said:
Here's a proof that .999...=1.

.999... can be written as the infinite sum as follows:

[tex].9 + .09 + .009 + .0009 + .00009 + ... = .9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n[/tex]

Now, evaluating the sum on the right, we use the fact (proven below) that...

[tex]\sum_{n=0}^\infty r^n = \frac{1}{1-r}[/tex]

for all r with a magnitude less than 1. Using this fact, we find that...

[tex].9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n = .9 \frac{1}{1-.1} = \frac{.9}{.9}=1[/tex]

Now, to prove that fact that we used, note the proof below:

[tex]S = \sum{k=0}^{n-1} a r^k = a + a r + a r^2 + a r^3 + a r^4 + ... + a r^{n-1}[/tex]

[tex]rS = a r + a r^2 + a r^3 + a r^4 + a r^5 + ... + a r^n[/tex]

[tex]S - rS = a - a r^n = a (1 - r^n)[/tex]

[tex]S(1-r) = a (1 - r^n)[/tex]

[tex]S = \frac{a (1-r^n)}{1-r}[/tex]

Now let n go to infinity. For r with a magnitude less than 1, r^n tends to 0 as n tends to infinity. Thus...

[tex]\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} S = \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \frac{a (1-r^n)}{1-r} = \frac{a}{1-r}[/tex]

Q E D


could you explain the above in layman's terms (i haven't seen anything like that in several years)?

and does it account for the possibility of an infinity of something in a finite space?
 
  • #5
jhae2.718 said:
More correctly, that holds as long as [itex]|r|<1[/itex].

Might also help to add the step [tex]S = \sum_{k = 0}^{n-1} ar^k[/tex] or similar...

Edited those in. Thanks!
 
  • #6
Curd said:
could you explain the above in layman's terms (i haven't seen anything like that in several years)?

and does it account for the possibility of an infinity of something in a finite space?

Actually, you often get a sum of infinite elements giving a finite number. Well, I'm assuming that's what you mean. And as for layman's terms, I'll try, but I'm not very good at explaining stuff like this, so bear with me.

Basically, I just converted our number .999... into an infinite sum. Then I proved, using the fact that this sum was a geometric series, that such a sum is equal to 1. Therefore, .999 is equal to 1.
 
  • #7
Here's an explanation of the proof:
Char. Limit said:
Here's a proof that .999...=1.

.999... can be written as the infinite sum as follows:

[tex].9 + .09 + .009 + .0009 + .00009 + \dots = .9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n[/tex]

We can write 0.999... as a geometric series. A geometric series is a series of the form [tex]\sum_{k=0}^N ar^k[/tex], where a is a constant and r is a constant ratio.

Char. Limit said:
Now, evaluating the sum on the right, we use the fact (proven below) that...

[tex]\sum_{n=0}^\infty r^n = \frac{1}{1-r}[/tex]

for all r with a magnitude less than 1. Using this fact, we find that...

[tex].9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n = .9 \frac{1}{1-.1} = \frac{.9}{.9}=1[/tex]

The sum of a geometric series is given by [tex]\frac{a}{1-r}[/tex], where [itex]|r|<1[/tex]. So, this series sum to exactly 1. (I.e., the infinitude of partial sums is one.)

Char. Limit said:
Now, to prove that fact that we used, note the proof below:

[tex]S = \sum_{k=0}^{n-1} a r^k = a + a r + a r^2 + a r^3 + a r^4 + ... + a r^{n-1}[/tex]
We begin by examining a more general case of a geometric series which takes the sum of [itex]n-1[/tex] terms.

Char. Limit said:
[tex]rS = a r + a r^2 + a r^3 + a r^4 + a r^5 + ... + a r^n[/tex]
We can multiply by the constant ratio r to get an expression that will allow us to get rid of most of the terms, shown below:
Char. Limit said:
[tex]S - rS = a - a r^n = a (1 - r^n)[/tex]

[tex]S(1-r) = a (1 - r^n)[/tex]

[tex]S = \frac{a (1-r^n)}{1-r}[/tex]
Factoring and solving for S, we get the expression for the sum of an arbitrary geometric series.
Char. Limit said:
Now let n go to infinity. For r with a magnitude less than 1, r^n tends to 0 as n tends to infinity. Thus...
For our case, we want the special case where [itex]n \to \infty[/itex]. To ensure this limit exists, we need to make the [itex]r^n[/itex] term go to zero. We do this by saying that [itex]|r|<1[/itex].

Consider a fraction [tex]\frac{a^n}{b^n}[/tex]. If [tex]\frac{a^n}{b^n} < 1 \Rightarrow a^n < b^n[/tex].
If we take the limit as [itex]n \to \infty[/itex] of this, bn grows faster than an, which implies the limit goes to zero.

Char. Limit said:
[tex]\lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} S = \lim_{n \rightarrow \infty} \frac{a (1-r^n)}{1-r} = \frac{a}{1-r}[/tex]

Q E D
We then take the limit and end up with the sum for an infinite geometric series, which we used to find [tex].9 \sum_{n=0}^\infty \left(\frac{1}{10}\right)^n[/tex]

As for the concept of a sum of an infinite amount of terms converging to a finite number, a lot of people have difficulty accepting this.

Let's consider the geometric series [tex]\sum_{k=0}^{\infty} \left(\frac{1}{2}\right)^n[/tex]. If we use the formula to find the sum, we get:
[tex]\sum_{k=0}^{\infty} \left(\frac{1}{2}\right)^n = \frac{1}{1-\frac{1}{2}}=\frac{1}{\frac{1}{2}} = 2[/tex]

To visualize this, consider an empty rectangle. We add a square that is half of the rectangle. We then add another rectangle that is half of the remaining empty rectangle, and so on...
350px-Geometric_progression_convergence_diagram.svg.png

Image from Wikipedia
As you can see, although there are an infinite number of terms, they never get outside the bounds of the first rectangle.
 
Last edited:
  • #8
Char. Limit said:
Actually, you often get a sum of infinite elements giving a finite number. Well, I'm assuming that's what you mean. And as for layman's terms, I'll try, but I'm not very good at explaining stuff like this, so bear with me.

Basically, I just converted our number .999... into an infinite sum. Then I proved, using the fact that this sum was a geometric series, that such a sum is equal to 1. Therefore, .999 is equal to 1.

layman as in a man who hasn't done calculus in over 5 years, took college algebra in a 20 day course 7 years ago (and therefore never had a solid foundation in it), and is now about a third of the way through going through his college algebra book again.
 
  • #9
Char. Limit said:
Actually, you often get a sum of infinite elements giving a finite number. Well, I'm assuming that's what you mean. And as for layman's terms, I'll try, but I'm not very good at explaining stuff like this, so bear with me.

Basically, I just converted our number .999... into an infinite sum. Then I proved, using the fact that this sum was a geometric series, that such a sum is equal to 1. Therefore, .999 is equal to 1.
Correction: What Char. Limit proved was that .999... is equal to 1. He inadvertently omitted the ellipsis (...).

Curd said:
layman as in a man who hasn't done calculus in over 5 years, took college algebra in a 20 day course 7 years ago (and therefore never had a solid foundation in it), and is now about a third of the way through going through his college algebra book again.
 
  • #10
Curd said:
layman as in a man who hasn't done calculus in over 5 years, took college algebra in a 20 day course 7 years ago (and therefore never had a solid foundation in it), and is now about a third of the way through going through his college algebra book again.

Are you familiar with sequences and series?
 
  • #11
jhae2.718 said:
Are you familiar with sequences and series?

And limits. Don't forget limits.
 
  • #12
Char. Limit said:
And limits. Don't forget limits.

not any longer. the only one that i remember vaguely is limits.
 
  • #13
".999999... never equals one. (i still find it hard to believe that saying that warrants an infraction). as the decimal points increase onto infinity the space between 1 and .9999... becomes smaller"

Yes: each time you stop at a finite number of decimals you define another number, and the differences between those numbers and 1 gets smaller.

, but the two never do connect to equal the exact same number. there is an infinite number of spaces to which decimals can extend (as noted by pie), so there is no reason for .999999999... ever to change to one.

"you can argue that .9999999 REPRESENTS one"

I'm reasonably sure you made a typing error here and really mean ".999999..." instead of "0.999999" BUT, in case you didn't, nobody is saying 0.9999999 represents one.


"in the language system you happen to be using, but .99999... will never actually equal one in real life."

You are stuck in the idea (whether you realize it or not) of thinking in finite blocks of 9s. The notation [itex] 0.999 \cdots [/itex] is a single object: the [itex] \cdots [/itex] informs us that the 9s march on forever.

I think your problem is based in your (admitted) lack of familiarity with these topics as much as it is skepticism of the usefulness and applicability of infinite decimal expansions.
 
  • #14
Curd said:
In response to the below quote I have written this. The idea that arguing is "spreading misinformation" is ridiculous as argument is the prime mover behind the evolution of the general intelligence of humanity as a whole. If that's the sort of attitude this forum carries with it though, fine, I'll leave. I came here to become educated, not merely indoctrinated. (education being something highly dependent on the dialogue created by argument and indoctrination being something highly dependent on the lack of dialogue created by argument). So, I submit the below in an attempt to meet out my expectations of education. Whether I get such education by means of knowing more about the world or more about the current subject, .999... will depend on the reaction I get.

So, here goes...


decimals of fractions never accurately equal those fractions. for example .111111111111111...never fully equals 1/9 (which applies directly to a certain proof) but for practical purposes you can assume it does.
Since you are asserting that .11111... is not the same as 1/9, please tell me how far apart they are.

Your statement "decimals of fractions never accurately equal those fractions" doesn't match your example. The decimal fractions .1, .11, .111 are successively closer to 1/9, but as you point out, none of them is equal to 1/9. The notation .111..., means an infinitely repeating pattern of 1's, and this shorthand notation does equal 1/9.
Curd said:
.999999... never equals one. (i still find it hard to believe that saying that warrants an infraction). as the decimal points increase onto infinity the space between 1 and .9999... becomes smaller, but the two never do connect to equal the exact same number.
They aren't equal at any finite decimal place, true, but we're talking about 9's extending infinitely far to the right of the decimal point.
If they aren't equal, their difference must be nonzero. Care to do the subtraction for me?
Curd said:
there is an infinite number of spaces to which decimals can extend (as noted by pie), so there is no reason for .999999999... ever to change to one.

you can argue that .9999999 REPRESENTS one in the language system you happen to be using, but .99999... will never actually equal one in real life.
You're being sloppy here. No one is arguing that .9999999 is equal to 1. We are saying however, that .9999999.. is exactly equal to 1. Note the ellipsis.
Curd said:
let's say you want to count all of the entities (particles, doodads, whatever) in the universe in relation to the whole. we will represent the whole with 1. once you have accounted for every item within the universe, let's represent each such item with a 9 after the decimal point, you have counted the whole of it and achieved accounting for 1 universe. since the universe expands on forever, the actual ability to do such a thing does not exist. therefore you can continue on counting 9's in .99999... without ever actually achieving 1.

If you were to say otherwise you would have to also say that infinity is impossible, and ergo pie would be impossible (along with other things). as it is a fact that the 9's after the decimal point can go on into infinity it is also a fact that .999... never equals one except for practical purposes in which such fine details are not important.

and as for that argument by Hurkyl that I'm "spreading misinformation"

and spreading misinformation? so, you're saying that the losing party to any argument is "spreading misinformation"?
It is a fairly common occurrence around here that someone asks whether .999... is different from 1. It is easy to prove that the two are equal.
Curd said:
how ever is one to have conversations on topics if one is to always be correct (i'm not saying I'm wrong by arguing this by the way), when being incorrect is "spreading misinformation"?

who is the owner of this forum? i would very much like to take this up with them.
 
  • #15
Curd said:
not any longer. the only one that i remember vaguely is limits.

Ok, I'm going to start with sequences.

A sequence is basically a list of numbers. We usually write sequences in the form [tex]\left\{a_n\right\}_{n=b}^{c}[/tex].

What this means is that for some term [itex]a_n[/itex], we plug in some number b, add it to our list, then plug in some number b+1, add it to our list, and do that until we reach c.

So, for example:
[tex]\left\{n\right\}_{n=1}^5 = \{1,2,3,4,5\}[/tex]
A more complicated example:
[tex]\text{Find }\left\{n^2-n\right\}_{n=2}^6[/tex]
The first term, [itex]a_2[/tex], is:
[tex]a_2 = 2^2-2 = 2[/tex]
We do this for 2-6, to yield:
[tex]\left\{n^2-n\right\}_{n=2}^6 = \{2,6,12,20,30\}[/tex]

Then we have infinite sequence; a general infinite sequence is given by:
[tex]\left\{a_n\right\}_{n=0}^\infty = \{a_0, a_1, a_2, \dots\}[/tex]

This goes on forever. Now that we have the concept of an infinite sequence, we need to introduce convergence. When we say something converges we mean than, as [itex]n \to \infty[/itex], each sequence term gets closer to a finite number. If each term gets bigger or terms don't approach the same number, we say the sequence diverges.

Since you said you vaguely remember limits, we can define a convergent sequence as any sequence for which [tex]\lim_{n \to \infty} a_n = L[/tex] holds, where L is a finite number. Otherwise, a series is divergent.

With me so far?
 
Last edited:
  • #16
OK, the 0.999... question... again

Question for the moderators: isn't it a good idea to put an FAQ in the math forums where such things are explained? So that people who want to post on the issue, have at least heard what we think of it? If you want, I'm willing to write such an FAQ, containing basic questions like 0.999... and division by zero.


Curd said:
you can argue that .9999999 REPRESENTS one in the language system you happen to be using, but .99999... will never actually equal one in real life.

Then the question obviosuly becomes: what is 0.9999... in real life? Can you give me an example what it is?

Here's an easy proof that 1=0.999...
Let x=0.999...
Then 10x=9.999...
Then 10x-x=9.999... - 0.999...=9
Then 9x=9
Then x=1

Of course, this isn't really a proof, it's merely an indication why this should be true. The real proof that 1=0.999... can only be given with the explicit construction of the real numbers, i.e. when working with Dedekind sets or Cauchy fundamental sequences.

The truth is actually that we've CHOSEN 1 to be equal to 0.999... If you want, you can choose it another way, but then there's a lot of arithmetic that won't hold. So in order to keep the nice laws of arithmetic, we have to define 1=0.999... You may not like it, but it's much more beautiful this way.
This paragraph is actually personal opinion, you may find many mathematicians who disagree. But you won't find any mathematician who says that 1=0.999... isn't true.
 
  • #17
A couple of fine points...
jhae2.718 said:
Ok, I'm going to start with sequences.

A sequence is basically a list of numbers. We usually write sequences in the form [tex]\left\{a_n\right\}_{n=b}^{c}[/tex].

What this means is that for some term [itex]a_n[/itex], we plug in some number b, add it to our list, then plug in some number b+1, add it to our list, and do that until we reach c.

So, for example:
[tex]\left\{n\right\}_{n=1}^5 = \{1,2,3,4,5\}[/tex]
A more complicated example:
[tex]\text{Find }\left\{n^2-n\right\}_{n=2}^6[/tex]
The first term, [itex]a_2[/tex], is:
[tex]a_2 = 2^2-2 = 2[/tex]
We do this for 2-6, to yield:
[tex]\left\{n^2-n\right\}_{n=2}^6 = \{2,6,12,20,30\}[/tex]

Then we have infinite sequence; a general infinite sequence is given by:
[tex]\left\{a_n\right\}_{n=0}^\infty = \{a_0, a_1, a_2, \dots\}[/tex]

This goes on forever. Now that we have the concept of an infinite series,
infinite sequence
jhae2.718 said:
we need to introduce convergence. When we say something converges we mean than, as [itex]n \to \infty[/itex], each sequence term gets closer to a finite number. If each term gets bigger, we say the sequence diverges.

Since you said you vaguely remember limits, we can define a convergent sequence as any sequence for which [tex]\lim_{n \to \infty} a_n = L[/tex] holds, where L is a finite number.

Then, a sequence is divergent if: [tex]\lim_{n \to \infty} a_n = \infty[/tex]
True, but a sequence can be divergent without being unbounded; e.g., {(-1)n}.
jhae2.718 said:
With me so far?
 
  • #18
Mark44 said:
A couple of fine points...infinite sequence

Oops...typo'd. Thanks for catching that.

Mark44 said:
True, but a sequence can be divergent without being unbounded; e.g., {(-1)n}.

Very true. I forgot to include those cases; I think I've worded it better now.
 
Last edited:
  • #19
Curd said:
So, I submit the below in an attempt to meet out my expectations of education. Whether I get such education by means of knowing more about the world or more about the current subject, .999... will depend on the reaction I get.

So, here goes...






decimals of fractions never accurately equal those fractions. for example .111111111111111...never fully equals 1/9 (which applies directly to a certain proof) but for practical purposes you can assume it does. [snip]

.999999... never equals one. [snip] as the decimal points increase onto infinity the space between 1 and .9999... becomes smaller, but the two never do connect to equal the exact same number. there is an infinite number of spaces to which decimals can extend (as noted by pie), so there is no reason for .999999999... ever to change to one.

you can argue that .9999999 REPRESENTS one in the language system you happen to be using, but .99999... will never actually equal one in real life.

.
You people who assert that .999... and .111... can never reach 1 or 1/9 th etc. are simply stuck with the idea that you can consider the term without the ellipses. You can't it is the ellipses that make the term complete and it is impossible to speak of the term apart from the ellipses. It is trival to speak of the term without the ellipses and say that you will never have the complete number. There is no argument about that. It also is true that the ellipses mean that the term goes ont into infinity and has more decimal places than the total number of particles in the universe (no matter how small the particle), but that of course doesn't mean that the term can not equal a real or rational number. We mathematicians have already proven that it does. See for instance the post of Char Limit. Anyone who says that there must be an error in such proofs are simply not serious mathematicians.
 
  • #20
Here's an interesting proof, based on knowledge from 4th grade:

I'll pose it as questions, so as to allow the reader to reach their own conclusion.

Are there real numbers between any two unequal real numbers?
What is a number between .999... and 1?

You learn in 4th grade, in simpler terms, that the reals are dense. In any dense set, there are infinitely many members between any two members. All real numbers have a decimal expansion. There is no decimal expansion between .999... and 1, therefore there is no number between them. There is no number between them, therefore they are equal.
 
  • #21
Curd said:
could you explain the above in layman's terms (i haven't seen anything like that in several years)?

and does it account for the possibility of an infinity of something in a finite space?
Yes with the ellipses, i.e. considering the number of terms as infinite, for instance the 1 by 2 rectangle posted by jhar2.718 and repeatedly dividing the rectangles in half. The sum of the infinite parts is indeed 2 and not something less and this can be proven mathematically. Also, try googling Zeno's Paradox.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
Curd, the ellipses imply the limit of SUM (.9/10^n) as n --> infinity, so if you are arguing that .9 repeating does not equal 1, then you are arguing, in principle, against limits, and suggesting that all of Calculus is "wrong."

Would you also, for instance, argue that 1/999.972 (999.972 kg. being the mass of water contained inside a 1 meter cube box at ~3.98 degrees Centigrade) is not equal to lim n --> infinity .001*SUM (28^(1*n)/10^(6*n))?

In the real physical world, if we are talking about the mass of water (at maximum density under one atmospheric pressure), you could make a very rational case that those numbers up above are approximations (even as scientists toy with the idea of making the kilogram an SI derived unit of measurement...). After all, the original ratio back in the late 1700's was 1/1000 (units: m/kg).

But in the idealized mathematical world, which is what we are dealing with here, then the fraction representing the ratio of the edge length of a 1 meter cube containing water to the mass of the water contained in that cube, 1/999.972 is precisely equal to lim n --> infinity .001*SUM (28^(n)/10^(6*n)). That which the fraction represents may be inaccurate, but the infinite sum representation of that fraction is 100% accurate.

Seems to me that you have a problem with infinite sums in general and are only willing to accept partial sums as mathematically valid. If so, then that should be the focus of your argument (good luck), not does .9 recurring equal 1. Because .9 recurring DOES equal one (as the sum of an infinite series), even if the way it "gets there" and the constituent (infinite) parts from which it is constructed are different from, say, n - (n-1) = 1

P.S. Or, just think of it this way: If you draw a circle of diameter 1 meter inside a square of edge length 1 meter, then is there an exact area inside the circle and also an exact area outside the circle but inside the square? If so, is that area any less exact simply because one could never, in an infinite amount of time, write out that area in decimal notation form?
 
Last edited:
  • #23
well Curd, I think I have a way you can understand this plainly. First I'll give a simple formal proof and then a more informal one which seems to follow your thinking strategy against the idea that 0.99999... = 1.

Formal but simple proof:

(1/3) = (0.333333333...)
(1/3)*3 = (0.999999999...)
3/3 = 0.99999999...
1 = 0.999999999

Then a more informal proof which seems to be following the way you are thinking against the 0.999... = 1 idea.

You seem to think that because adding another 0.09 and a 0.009 and a 0.0009 and so in is never enough for the expression to finally equal 1. Once we get up to 0.99999, it is still 0.000001 short of equaling 1. Remember that we are saying 0.999999... with an INFINITE number of 9s is equal to 1. If you still think that there will never come a nine which is exactly enough to make the expression equal 1, you are right. Because if a nine does come to make it equal, it truly isn't an infinite decimal and another 0.00000000000000001 difference still exists.

We are saying that the number of nines is infinite. So, the difference between 0.999... and 1 is equal to:

0.000000000000...1

with an infinite number of zeros, the number is never quite ready to add on the extra one. The one essentially doesn't exist, the number of zeroes will carry on forever and ever and the one will never show up. I hope you see the connection between the idea that there will never be a 9 in the infinite decimal 0.999999... which will make it equal to 1 and the idea that there isn't ever going to be enough zeroes to make the number ready to add the 0.000000...1



I hope this helps ease your confusion.


Zac
 
  • #24
I don't know if this argument has been given on this particular thread, but this is how I like to show that .9999...=1.

Let n = .999...
multiply both sides by 10:

10n = 9.999...

Subtract n from both sides:

9n = 9

Divide both sides by 9:

n=1

but by assumption, .99...=n. Thus, .99...=n=1

EDIT: My calc prof. taught us this one just before we started with series.
 
Last edited:
  • #25
micromass said:
OK, the 0.999... question... again

Question for the moderators: isn't it a good idea to put an FAQ in the math forums where such things are explained? So that people who want to post on the issue, have at least heard what we think of it? If you want, I'm willing to write such an FAQ, containing basic questions like 0.999... and division by zero.




Then the question obviosuly becomes: what is 0.9999... in real life? Can you give me an example what it is?

Here's an easy proof that 1=0.999...
Let x=0.999...
Then 10x=9.999...
Then 10x-x=9.999... - 0.999...=9
Then 9x=9
Then x=1

Of course, this isn't really a proof, it's merely an indication why this should be true. The real proof that 1=0.999... can only be given with the explicit construction of the real numbers, i.e. when working with Dedekind sets or Cauchy fundamental sequences.

The truth is actually that we've CHOSEN 1 to be equal to 0.999... If you want, you can choose it another way, but then there's a lot of arithmetic that won't hold. So in order to keep the nice laws of arithmetic, we have to define 1=0.999... You may not like it, but it's much more beautiful this way.
This paragraph is actually personal opinion, you may find many mathematicians who disagree. But you won't find any mathematician who says that 1=0.999... isn't true.


doesn't matter if it's beautiful or not. if it is not reflective of reality then it's not accurate. what do physicists say? that's what will really count.
 
  • #26
Curd said:
doesn't matter if it's beautiful or not. if it is not reflective of reality then it's not accurate. what do physicists say? that's what will really count.

It is reflective of reality.

Try this experiment:
  1. Mark out a distance on the floor
  2. Stand at one end
  3. Walk halfway across
  4. Walk halfway across the remaining distance
  5. Keep walking halfway across the remaining distances until you reach the end

Now, this is a physical example of the infinite series [tex]\sum_{n=0}^\infty \frac{1}{2}\left(\frac{1}{2}\right)^n[/tex], which converges to 1.

(First you walk 1/2 of the way, then 1/4, then 1/8, then 1/16, etc.)

However, by your argument, since it is an infinite series it will get close to 1, but never get there. The series sums to 1; refer to Char's proof.

What happens when you try the experiment?

(This, by the way, is known as Zeno's Paradox.)
 
  • #27
Curd said:
doesn't matter if it's beautiful or not. if it is not reflective of reality then it's not accurate. what do physicists say? that's what will really count.
What do reality and physicists have to do with it? In mathematics there are lots of structures that have little to do with reality. For just one example, consider vector spaces. We can visualize a space of two dimensions (a plane) or three dimensions (a space with length, breadth, and height), but it is difficult to visualize a space with, say, 10 or 12 or 100 dimensions. Nevertheless, we are able to calculate the distance between two points in such a space.

And those are just finite-dimension vector spaces. There is even the concept of an infinite-dimensional vector space in which a vector is represented by an infinite sequence. This might be difficult to picture, but there is a whole lot of mathematics built up around this idea.

For a different example, see this thread - https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=484140 - in which micromass talks about "exotic spheres" in seven dimensions. As near as I can tell, this doesn't have much to do with reality.
 
Last edited:
  • #28
Curd said:
doesn't matter if it's beautiful or not. if it is not reflective of reality then it's not accurate. what do physicists say? that's what will really count.

I advise you never to take abstract algebra.
 
  • #29
An old one: "An engineer thinks that his equations are an approximation to reality. A physicist thinks reality is an approximation to his equations. A mathematician doesn't care."
 
  • #30
jhae2.718 said:
An old one: "An engineer thinks that his equations are an approximation to reality. A physicist thinks reality is an approximation to his equations. A mathematician doesn't care."
Pretty well sums it up.
 
  • #31
micromass said:
OK, the 0.999... question... again

Question for the moderators: isn't it a good idea to put an FAQ in the math forums where such things are explained? So that people who want to post on the issue, have at least heard what we think of it? If you want, I'm willing to write such an FAQ, containing basic questions like 0.999... and division by zero.




Then the question obviosuly becomes: what is 0.9999... in real life? Can you give me an example what it is?

Here's an easy proof that 1=0.999...
Let x=0.999...
Then 10x=9.999...
Then 10x-x=9.999... - 0.999...=9
Then 9x=9
Then x=1

Of course, this isn't really a proof, it's merely an indication why this should be true. The real proof that 1=0.999... can only be given with the explicit construction of the real numbers, i.e. when working with Dedekind sets or Cauchy fundamental sequences.

The truth is actually that we've CHOSEN 1 to be equal to 0.999... If you want, you can choose it another way, but then there's a lot of arithmetic that won't hold. So in order to keep the nice laws of arithmetic, we have to define 1=0.999... You may not like it, but it's much more beautiful this way.
This paragraph is actually personal opinion, you may find many mathematicians who disagree. But you won't find any mathematician who says that 1=0.999... isn't true.

Ahhh, so someone has taken this approach this thread, my bad.

Anyway, could you explain why the argument you gave isn't really a proof?
 
  • #32
It "isn't really a proof" because it assumes, without proof, that we can extend arithmetic operations to infinite sequences of digits. However, I disagree with the statement "The real proof that 1=0.999... can only be given with the explicit construction of the real numbers, i.e. when working with Dedekind sets or Cauchy fundamental sequences".

The only numbers involved in saying "1= 0.999..." are rational numbers. No need to extend to all real numbers.

A perfectly valid proof is the one using the geometric series that Char. Lim. gave in the very first response to this thread. And, again, only rational numbers are required.
 
  • #33
Curd said:
doesn't matter if it's beautiful or not. if it is not reflective of reality then it's not accurate. what do physicists say? that's what will really count.

Well, besides the fact that physics has nothing to do with this, you will find that any serious physicist will agree that 1=0.999...
But the actual problem is this: why is 1=0.999... not reflective of reality to you?? I.e. where do you ever encounter 0.999... in reality? I've actually never encountered it anywhere, except in these kind of threads.

Robert1986 said:
Ahhh, so someone has taken this approach this thread, my bad.

Anyway, could you explain why the argument you gave isn't really a proof?

Because you still have to prove that 9.999... - 0.999... is 9 and 10*0.999... = 9.999... This still needs to be shown.
And it seems that Halls is correct, you don't really need Dedekind cuts for this. However, working with decimal represtations is quite tricky, so I wouldn't be surprised if there were some subtleties involved...
 
  • #34
HallsofIvy said:
It "isn't really a proof" because it assumes, without proof, that we can extend arithmetic operations to infinite sequences of digits. However, I disagree with the statement "The real proof that 1=0.999... can only be given with the explicit construction of the real numbers, i.e. when working with Dedekind sets or Cauchy fundamental sequences".

The only numbers involved in saying "1= 0.999..." are rational numbers. No need to extend to all real numbers.

A perfectly valid proof is the one using the geometric series that Char. Lim. gave in the very first response to this thread. And, again, only rational numbers are required.

But Char Limit states his identity is proven below where he multiplies an infinite series by r!

Perfectly valid because it gives valid answers in reality as does the fact that 1/[infinity] = 0
and 1/[infinity] is the difference between .9... and 1.
 
  • #35
I haven't read all the posts in this thread, so maybe I have missed something, but I feel that the two most important facts haven't been mentioned. I'll try to explain them here. It's impossible to even attempt to prove that 0.999...=1 or that 0.999...≠1 until we have defined what 0.999... means. (That's the first important fact in this post). The obvious way to define it is

[tex]0.999\dots=\sum_{n=1}^\infty \frac{9}{10^n}.[/tex]

Unfortunately this definition doesn't make sense until we have defined what the right-hand side means. So let's do that. For N=1,2,3,..., define the "Nth partial sum" as

[tex]S_N=\sum_{n=1}^N\frac{9}{10^n}.[/tex]

Now we can define [itex]\sum_{n=1}^\infty 9/10^n[/itex] as the limit of the sequence [itex]S_1,\ S_2,\ S_3,\dots[/itex]. But what does that mean?

Let's consider a particularly simple sequence to illustrate the idea behind the definition of a limit of a sequence: 1/2, 1/3, 1/4,... The terms in this sequence get smaller and smaller. You might think that it's obvious that it goes to 0, or that it's obvious that a smart math guy can prove that it goes to 0, but it's not. It's impossible to even attempt a proof until we have defined what it means for something to go to 0. So we have to define what the statement "1/2, 1/3, 1/4,... goes to 0" means, before we can attempt to prove that it's true.

This is the standard definition: "1/n goes to 0" means that "for every positive real number ε, there's a positive integer N, such that for all integers n such that n≥N, we have |1/n| < ε". With this definition in place, it's quite easy to prove that "1/n goes to 0" is a true statement. What I want you to see here, is that we chose this definition to make sure that this statement would be true. (That's the second point I wanted to make). The first mathematicians who thought about how to define the limit of a sequence might have briefly considered definitions that make the statement "1/n goes to 0" false, but they would have dismissed those definitions as irrelevant, because they fail to capture the idea of a limit that they already understood on an intuitive level.

So the real reason why 1/n goes to 0 is that we wanted it to!. Similar comments hold for the sequence of partial sums that define 0.999... It goes to 1, because we have defined the concepts "0.999...", "sum of infinitely many terms", and "limit of a sequence" in ways that make 0.999...=1.

This makes the question sort of meaningless. Of course, that doesn't mean that it was a bad idea to ask it. If you hadn't, you wouldn't have learned all this.Here's the general definition of a sequence [itex]x_1,\ x_2,\ x_3,\dots[/itex] of real numbers. If there exists a real number x, such that for each [itex]\varepsilon>0[/itex] there's a positive integer N such that

[tex]n\geq N\ \Rightarrow\ |x_n-x|<\varepsilon,[/tex]

then the sequence is said to be convergent, and x is said to be a limit of the sequence. (That arrow should be read as "implies". It means that if the thing on the left is true, then the thing on the right is true).
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes 1 person

Similar threads

Replies
2
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
47
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
1K
Replies
33
Views
5K
Replies
35
Views
5K
  • General Math
Replies
22
Views
3K
  • General Discussion
Replies
4
Views
659
Replies
1
Views
940
Replies
18
Views
7K
Back
Top