Missing(?) rigor in proof involving countable union of countable sets

In summary: I won't bore you with the details other than to say that the result is a function from U_n(A_n) into a subset of N x N.Since the correspondence between (m,n) and N is given as a formula in the proof, this establishes that the function f_n : A_n —> N can be written in functional notation as f_n(a) = (m,n-1)(m+n-1) + n, where m and n are the corresponding elements of A_m and A_n, respectively.Therefore, by definition, the correspondence between U_n(A_n) and a subset of
  • #1
Uncanny
36
1
TL;DR Summary
I posted earlier regarding a corollary (regarding the rational numbers) of the theorem in question here. Upon reviewing the chapter and putting pen to paper, however, I have come across a deeper question concerning the proof presented of the theorem that a countable union of countable sets is itself countable. A photo of the theorem statement and proof in question is, again, attached below.
My question concerns the portion of the proof stating, “...we set up a correspondence between the elements of U(A_n), for n in N, and a subset of S by making the element a correspond to (m, n) if A_m is the first set in which a appears, and a is the nth element of A_m.”

In particular, I am wondering whether a more precise, or rigorous/symbolic formulation of the quoted portion of the proof above can be made? In other words, how can a statement of the correspondence be formally mathematically expressed (i.e., explicitly in functional form)?

It seems (to me, at least) this would be a function mapping from U(A_n) into a subset of N x N, since, in turn, the correspondence between (m,n) and N is priorly given as a formula in the proof: (1/2)(m+n-2)(m+n-1) + n.

*Update: I’ve done a bit of research into the matter since initially posting, and it seems the solution may involve the axiom of choice (which I should, regardless, brush up on) as well as the particular correspondences denumerating each A_n. I’ll post any tentative solution I reach, should I arrive at one before any helpful or suggestive responses!
 

Attachments

  • CAAB11C9-EB7D-4281-88C0-47D7799C7C27.png
    CAAB11C9-EB7D-4281-88C0-47D7799C7C27.png
    60 KB · Views: 363
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Uncanny said:
Summary: I posted earlier regarding a corollary (regarding the rational numbers) of the theorem in question here. Upon reviewing the chapter and putting pen to paper, however, I have come across a deeper question concerning the proof presented of the theorem that a countable union of countable sets is itself countable. A photo of the theorem statement and proof in question is, again, attached below.

My question concerns the portion of the proof stating, “...we set up a correspondence between the elements of U(A_n), for n in N, and a subset of S by making the element a correspond to (m, n) if A_m is the first set in which a appears, and a is the nth element of A_m.”

In particular, I am wondering whether a more precise, or rigorous/symbolic formulation of the quoted portion of the proof above can be made? In other words, how can a statement of the correspondence be formally mathematically expressed (i.e., explicitly in functional form)?

It seems (to me, at least) this would be a function mapping from U(A_n) into a subset of N x N, since, in turn, the correspondence between (m,n) and N is priorly given as a formula in the proof: (1/2)(m+n-2)(m+n-1) + n.

I'm not sure I understand your question. There's a difference between "rigour" and producing an explicit formula.
 
  • #3
PeroK said:
I'm not sure I understand your question. There's a difference between "rigour" and producing an explicit formula.

I’m looking for an explicit formula. Also, check my update, please, incase it elucidates the matter- I may have edited the original post while or after you replied.
 
  • #4
Uncanny said:
I’m looking for an explicit formula. Also, check my update, please, incase it elucidates the matter- I may have edited the original post while or after you replied.

In my opinion it's a good opportunity to get away from the idea that you need an explicit formula. There are many results in mathematics where you can show that something exists without being able to produce a formulaic description of the object.

I can only see that the axiom of choice might be relevant if you want to justify that the countable union of sets is itself a well-defined set. But, that's going in the "opposite" direction towards the foundations of mathematics.
 
  • #5
My tentative solution is such:

By hypothesis, the A_n are denumerable, or countable, so there exist functions, say f_n(a) : A_n —> N which are 1-1 correspondences between the sets A_n and (subsets of) the natural numbers, N. To show that the union of a denumerable number (which is the case here since the A_n are indexed by n in N, hence enumerating them) of denumerable sets (the A_n, again, denumerable by hypothesis) is denumerable, consider the 1-1 correspondences, g_n, from U(A_n) into N x N given by: g_n(a) = (n, f_n(a)).

I still need to figure out a way to account for the potential “overlap” or pairwise (non-empty) intersections between the A_n so that any element(s) is(are) not doubly counted.
 
  • #6
Uncanny said:
I still need to figure out a way to account for the potential “overlap” or pairwise (non-empty) intersections between the A_n so that any element(s) is(are) not doubly counted.

So if you have a surjection ##f## from ##N## into ##U(A_n)##, then can't you just delete the repeats to get a bijection? (Assuming that ##U(A_n)## is infinite?)
 
  • #7
I got it! Essentially, the modifications and remainder of the proof I have written for the theorem are as follow:

I worked backwards to arrive at this concept, but in presenting the proof it seems more logically appropriate to begin with it; I first show that:

U_n(A_n) = U_n[A_n\U_k=1,k=n-1(A_k)], k ranging the prescribed natural numbers (namely, 1 through n-1, inclusive).

This result turns out fairy simple to prove after first proving a very helpful lemma. That is, {A_n\U_k=1,k=n-1(A_k)}_n are (pairwise) disjoint. This proof, in turn, amounts to considering the intersections of the A_n\U_k=1,k=n-1(A_k) for two exhaustive (and contradictory) cases: j<m and m<j, where j and m are arbitrary (but fixed) natural numbers such that j is not equal to m.

Now, we are naturally left with a family of functions, {g_n: A_n\U_k=1,k=n-1(A_k) —> N x N; g_n(a) = (n, f_n(a))}_n. If we can show that the union of this family of functions is itself a function, then the proof will (at least, to my level of rigor and formality) be complete!

Fortunately here, {A_n\U_k=1,k=n-1(A_k)}_n constitute an exhaustive sequence of sets on their union; that union is equal to U_n(A_n), which was proven above. Furthermore, the restriction of the mapping g_i+1 to A_i\U_k=1,k=i-1(A_k) is equal to g_i. As such, it follows that the union of the set of functions G = {g_n}_n is, indeed, a (well-defined) function.

Thus, a well-formulated proof for the theorem results, with G(a): U_n{A_n\U_k=1,k=n-1(A_k)} = U_n(A_n) —> N x N given by G(a) = g_n(a). The resulting set of ordered pairs, of course, has already been shown to be in 1-1 correspondence with N. Hence, the theorem is proven.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes stevendaryl
  • #8
Also... I felt I should include the demonstration that the functions {g_n} are each well-defined, but the “proof” seems trivial based on the construction of the {g_n}.
 
  • #9
As it turns out, the second-to-last paragraph in my post (#7) isn’t, in general, true (for consider if we simply partition N into two sets: evens and odds; whichever set you call A_1, it is never the case that A_1 is a subset of A_2).

The conclusion of the paragraph, however, remains true by a simpler argument; namely, that for a set of functions, {f_i}_i, where f_i: A_i —> C for each i in N and {A_i}_i are disjoint, f = U_i(f_i) is a function. This is a fairly simple proof usually included in most chapters on functions in set theory (or related) books. The proof for the case i=2 is ordinarily presented therein, but incase it’s of interest to anyone, I wrote my own proof for the generalized case (i.e. for countable unions of functions), and can post it. I doubt this to be the case though. 😅
 
  • #10
I also just realized that most of the work for proving this theorem can be stated compactly by an operation called “disjoint union.” But surely most of these steps are included in proving the underpinnings of that operation?
 
  • #11
Uncanny said:
I also just realized that most of the work for proving this theorem can be stated compactly by an operation called “disjoint union.” But surely most of these steps are included in proving the underpinnings of that operation?

I don't understand why it needs to be made complicated. You have a countable union of countable sets. All the elements of the union can be counted by a diagonal argument; or, by the argument given in the link you posted.
 

What is meant by "missing rigor" in a proof involving countable union of countable sets?

Missing rigor refers to a lack of precision or completeness in the logical steps used to prove a statement involving countable unions of countable sets. This means that there may be gaps or assumptions made in the proof that are not explicitly stated or justified.

Why is it important to have rigor in a proof involving countable union of countable sets?

Rigor is important in any mathematical proof because it ensures that the statement being proved is true and that the logical steps used to prove it are valid. In the case of countable unions of countable sets, rigor is especially important because these sets can be complex and require careful reasoning to prove statements about them.

What are some common mistakes or errors that can lead to missing rigor in a proof involving countable union of countable sets?

Some common mistakes include using circular reasoning, making unjustified assumptions, and omitting important details or steps in the proof. Additionally, not carefully considering edge cases or exceptions can also lead to missing rigor in a proof.

How can one ensure rigor in a proof involving countable union of countable sets?

To ensure rigor, one should carefully define all terms and concepts used in the proof, clearly state all assumptions and justify them, and provide a complete and logical sequence of steps to prove the statement. It is also helpful to have the proof reviewed by others for any potential errors or gaps.

What are some strategies for improving the rigor in a proof involving countable union of countable sets?

Some strategies include breaking down the proof into smaller, more manageable steps, using counterexamples to test the validity of the proof, and double-checking all assumptions and logical steps. It can also be helpful to consult other sources or seek guidance from more experienced mathematicians.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
700
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
4K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
1
Views
491
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
922
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
8
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
5
Views
2K
Back
Top