More on the thermal interpretation

In summary, the conversation discusses the fourth part of a series of papers on the thermal interpretation of quantum physics. It summarizes the main features and adds intuitive explanations and new technical developments, showing how spectral features and classical dynamics can arise under appropriate conditions. The conversation also delves into the differences between the thermal interpretation and traditional interpretations, specifically in regards to measurement errors. It also explores standard experiments from the perspective of the thermal interpretation. The conversation ends with a discussion on non-locality and how it is utilized in the thermal interpretation. There is a mention of a potential issue with non-demolition spin measurements in the TI.
  • #1
A. Neumaier
Science Advisor
Insights Author
8,595
4,620
TL;DR Summary
This thread continues the discussion of the thermal interpretation of
quantum physics, announcing Part IV of my series of papers on the subject.
I just finished a 4th part of my series of papers on the thermal interpretation:
This paper continues the discussion of the thermal interpretation of quantum physics. While Part II and Part III of this series of papers explained and justified the reasons for the departure from tradition, the present Part IV summarizes the main features and adds intuitive explanations and new technical developments.
  • It is shown how the spectral features of quantum systems and an approximate classical dynamics arise under appropriate conditions.
  • Evidence is given for how, in the thermal interpretation, the measurement of a qubit by a pointer q-expectation may result in a binary detection event with probabilities given by the diagonal entries of the reduced density matrix of the prepared qubit.
  • Differences in the conventions about measurement errors in the thermal interpretation and in traditional interpretations are discussed in detail.
  • Several standard experiments, the double slit, Stern-Gerlach, and particle decay are described from the perspective of the thermal interpretation.
Some of the material in this paper may be familiar to you from my contributions to one of the other recent threads on the subject. The analysis of the classical dynamics and the qubit, however, are new. An explanation of the relation to decoherence is given here.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes julcab12, dextercioby, Mentz114 and 1 other person
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I find the following on p. 5 very interesting:

"Even before the advent of quantum mechanics, it turned out that, in classical statistical mechanics, atoms are indistinguishable not only due to practical limitations but in principle, and that there is no theoretically conceivable way to distinguish them as individuals – if it were possible, the resulting predictions would have an additional entropy of mixing, which is in conflict with the observed thermodynamical properties of bulk systems. This means that there are fundamental constraints that forbid the atom in a classical multiparticle system to have individual values."

In order for this to "directly lead" to the thermal interpretation, as the paper says (in the next sentence after what I have just quoted), doesn't there need to be an additional premise, to the effect that in order to make a measurement, some macroscopic system must be involved to which the indistinguishability argument just given can apply? After all, if we run a Stern-Gerlach experiment on a single electron, the electron is not a multi-particle system and is distinguishable from other electrons because we specifically prepared it that way. But the detector is a many-particle system, and we can't know how the experiment turned out without the detector.
 
  • #3
I also want to check my understanding of a statement on p. 6:

"Quantized measurement results (as observed angular momentum measurements) are explained by environment-induced randomness and environment-induced dissipation, as for a classical, environment-induced diffusion process in a double-well potential. Born’s statistical interpretation follows, in the limited range where it applies, from this and the deterministic rules."

So just to be clear, the thermal interpretation is not the MWI: if we make a single run of a Stern-Gerlach experiment, there is only one result. Which result it is depends on random fluctuations in the environment (which in this case would, I think, be random fluctuations in the huge number of degrees of freedom in the detector).
 
  • #4
A. Neumaier said:
  • It is shown how the spectral features of quantum systems and an approximate classical dynamics arise under appropriate conditions.
  • ...
Some of the material in this paper may be familiar to you from my contributions to one of the other recent threads on the subject. The analysis of the classical dynamics and the qubit, however, are new.

What prevents the TI being wholly classical?
 
  • #5
PeterDonis said:
Which result it is depends on random fluctuations in the environment (which in this case would, I think, be random fluctuations in the huge number of degrees of freedom in the detector).

The predictive detector hidden variables will not generally dictated by random fluctuations, but by nonlocal hidden variables.

Consider an experiment in which an (SG-like) device A makes a non-demolition spin measurement of an N=1 beam, and in doing so diverts the spin-up component of the beam upwards, so that it enters into SG device B. Likewise, the spin-down component is diverted downwards, so that it feeds into device C instead. Devices B and C can be arbitrarily far away from A in space and time.

According to TI, there is no collapse due to measurement A, so the q-expectation value of the beam entering devices B and C is equal. But despite this, in the case that device A already clicked "up", it is now impossible for device C to click, and mandatory (up to experimental error) that device B click. Device A (or the universe as a whole) has to non-locally constrain the fluctuations of the degrees of freedom in devices and B and C, which the TI takes as predictive of the local measurement outcome. In realistic settings apart from optics, these non-local, historical constraints will dominate the behavior of the local detector HVs, rather than local environmental fluctuations.

This inter-detector holism is equivalent in function to a pilot wave, but because the TI demands the particle beams are non-collapsing and (as I understand it) not assigned their own HVs, the TI has to utilize non-locality more broadly than Bohmians. At least for the above experiment, Bohmians can get away without relying on any non-local effects. But from a philosophical perspective, if you are already comfortable with a pilot wave, I don't think this should really feel like too much of a leap.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #6
charters said:
According to TI, there is no collapse due to measurement A

No, according to TI there is no measurement at all at A, because the beam never hits a detector; it just gets deflected. Which is the same thing that standard QM says.

charters said:
in the case that device A already clicked "up"

Device A can't click anything because the A "up" beam does not hit a detector; it passes through a second SG apparatus. Similarly for the A "down" beam.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #7
So you are saying non-demolition spin measurements are impossible in the TI? That would be a problem because they are possible in reality. It is possible to macroscopically record the spin of the system at A and then let the system proceed to additional detectors.
 
  • #8
charters said:
So you are saying non-demolition spin measurements are impossible in the TI?

No. Sorry, I missed the "nondemolition" in your post before.

charters said:
they are possible in reality

Yes, but not, AFAIK, with Stern Gerlach apparatus.

As I understand it, TI has no problem with nonlocal q-expectations, and that, broadly speaking, is how it would handle the scenario you describe.
 
  • #9
charters said:
So you are saying non-demolition spin measurements are impossible in the TI? That would be a problem because they are possible in reality. It is possible to macroscopically record the spin of the system at A and then let the system proceed to additional detectors.
That is speculative and seems unecessary. It is the magnitude of the spin that is quantised not the direction. The impotance of the experiment is that the two beams have equal intensity. The direction of the spin does not enter the Hamiltonian unless there is an interaction with an inhomogenous magetic field. In that case the deflection can be described by classical evolution. The separation of the beam is a demolition-neutral measurement of a classical force.
 
  • #10
PeterDonis said:
As I understand it, TI has no problem with nonlocal q-expectations, and that, broadly speaking, is how it would handle the scenario you describe.

Right, this is all I was saying - that these nonlocal variables are doing a good deal of the work in ensuring it is a deterministic interpretation that conforms to QM. They're more central to this task than the local evolution of the local detector hidden variables/degrees of freedom.

Fwiw, I'd also say the same thing to a Bohmian who suggested measurements were a straightforward function of their local particle trajectories. In BM, the non-local trajectory corrections are similarly not to be understated in their importance (though often I find they are).
 
  • #11
Mentz114 said:
That is speculative and seems unecessary. It is the magnitude of the spin that is quantised not the direction. The impotance of the experiment is that the two beams have equal intensity. The direction of the spin does not enter the Hamiltonian unless there is an interaction with an inhomogenous magetic field. In that case the deflection can be described by classical evolution. The separation of the beam is a demolition-neutral measurement of a classical force.

Sorry, I don't understand your point/what this has to do with the issue of how deterministic hidden variable interpretations work.
 
  • #12
charters said:
Sorry, I don't understand your point/what this has to do with the issue of how deterministic hidden variable interpretations work.
Sorry, I was actually commenting (obliquely) on this
This inter-detector holism is equivalent in function to a pilot wave, but because the TI demands the particle beams are non-collapsing and (as I understand it) not assigned their own HVs, the TI has to utilize non-locality more broadly than Bohmians. At least for the above experiment, Bohmians can get away without relying on any non-local effects. But from a philosophical perspective, if you are already comfortable with a pilot wave, I don't think this should really feel like too much of a leap.
My point about the classicity is that this ensures there is always a local HV and makes the speculation about non-local guide waves irrelevant.
 
  • #13
charters said:
these nonlocal variables are doing a good deal of the work in ensuring it is a deterministic interpretation that conforms to QM.

Agreed.

charters said:
In BM, the non-local trajectory corrections are similarly not to be understated in their importance (though often I find they are).

Agreed.
 
  • Like
Likes eloheim
  • #14
Mentz114 said:
My point about the classicity is that this ensures there is always a local HV and makes the speculation about non-local guide waves irrelevant.

The HVs in this interpretation live on the various detectors, which are spatially separated. So it doesn’t make sense to say they are always local.

And my point really nothing specific to do with any details of spin. It goes through the same with abstract operators and detectors.
 
  • #15
charters said:
The HVs in this interpretation live on the various detectors, which are spatially separated. So it doesn’t make sense to say they are always local.

...but because the TI demands the particle beams are non-collapsing and (as I understand it) not assigned their own HVs, ...
I'm referring to an HV for each particle. Like you, I'm not sure if the TI allows this but it predicts the correct outcomes.

And my point really nothing specific to do with any details of spin. It goes through the same with abstract operators and detectors.
Hmm. Probably too abstract for me so I'll refrain from commenting further.
 
  • #16
PeterDonis said:
"This means that there are fundamental constraints that forbid the atom in a classical multiparticle system to have individual values."

In order for this to "directly lead" to the thermal interpretation, as the paper says (in the next sentence after what I have just quoted)
Well, it leads directly only to the main innovation of the thermal interpretation, that expectations are beables. Of course, classical statistical mechanics says nothing about quantum mechanics, and hence nothing about the thermal interpretation of it. Thus I'd have been more careful in the formulation...

PeterDonis said:
doesn't there need to be an additional premise, to the effect that in order to make a measurement, some macroscopic system must be involved to which the indistinguishability argument just given can apply? After all, if we run a Stern-Gerlach experiment on a single electron, the electron is not a multi-particle system and is distinguishable from other electrons because we specifically prepared it that way. But the detector is a many-particle system, and we can't know how the experiment turned out without the detector.
Yes, in a Stern-Gerlach experiment, a lone electron in the beam is distinguished. Without the detector no measurement.

But it is not the indistinguishability of the detector particles that causes the measurement but the fact that the energy from the impact of the silver is dissipated into detector oscillations (phonons) that leave the impact region and hence have an irreversible asymptotic effect, similar to the one discussed for the pointer in Section 3 of Part IV. Because of the bilocality, the details are more complicated than for the pointer discussed there, and I haven't yet worked them out, but the principle is the same.
 
Last edited:
  • #17
PeterDonis said:
I also want to check my understanding of a statement on p. 6:

"Quantized measurement results (as observed angular momentum measurements) are explained by environment-induced randomness and environment-induced dissipation, as for a classical, environment-induced diffusion process in a double-well potential. Born’s statistical interpretation follows, in the limited range where it applies, from this and the deterministic rules."

So just to be clear, the thermal interpretation is not the MWI: if we make a single run of a Stern-Gerlach experiment, there is only one result. Which result it is depends on random fluctuations in the environment (which in this case would, I think, be random fluctuations in the huge number of degrees of freedom in the detector).
According to the thermal interpretation, if we make a single run of a Stern-Gerlach experiment, there is indeed only one result. Which result it is (i.e., whether a silver atom is deposited at the left or the right spot) depends on in practice unpredictable details in the deterministic environment - the whole universe apart from the beam and the two detector spots. For all practical purposes, these are random fluctuations.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #18
N88 said:
What prevents the TI being wholly classical?
In a classical world governed by the thermal interpretation, the particle operators (in a discrete world) or field operators (in a continuum world) would commute.
 
  • #19
Mentz114 said:
The separation of the beam is a demolition-neutral measurement of a classical force.
No, unless you measure one of the resulting two beams. The separation of the beam is a unitary transformation in the full state space of the particle, hence no measurement is involved.

Mentz114 said:
I'm referring to an HV for each particle. Like you, I'm not sure if the TI allows this but it predicts the correct outcomes.
There are local variables at each detector position and nonlocal variables at pairs of detector positions. In addition, the particle in the beam is fully described only by nonlocal variables.
 
  • #20
A. Neumaier said:
No, unless you measure one of the resulting two beams. The separation of the beam is a unitary transformation in the full state space of the particle, hence no measurement is involved.
So no work is done on the particles during the separation and it is reversible ? I could believe that if the magnetic field was homogenous.

There are local variables at each detector position and nonlocal variables at pairs of detector positions. In addition, the particle in the beam is fully described only by nonlocal variables.
Thanks for the clarification.
 
  • #21
Mentz114 said:
So no work is done on the particles during the separation and it is reversible ? I could believe that if the magnetic field was homogenous.
It is reversible even classically. Mechanical work is done, but in a reversible way.

The irreversible stuff happens upon impact at the screen.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #22
A. Neumaier said:
It is reversible even classically. Mechanical work is done, but in a reversible way.

The irreversible stuff happens upon impact at the screen.
That clears up my problem, I guess.

I found this paper in a journal called 'Entropy' which is peer reviewed

A Quantum Description of the Stern–Gerlach Experiment
Håkan Wennerström and Per-Olof Westlund
https://www.mdpi.com/1099-4300/19/5/186/pdf
They appear to use q-expectations without calling them by that name. They claim that their conclusions are the same as those of other more conventional approaches ( references are given in the above).
Do you have any thoughts on their approach ?
 
  • #23
Mentz114 said:
They appear to use q-expectations without calling them by that name. They claim that their conclusions are the same as those of other more conventional approaches ( references are given in the above).
Do you have any thoughts on their approach ?
They interpret the q-expectations in the conventional way; see p.4 after (14).

Note that books and articles on quantum physics are full of computations with and of q-expectations. But their interpretation has in the past always been in terms of an ensemble mean over many independent realizations. In the thermal intepretation, the same computations are given a different meaning.

By the way, a nice paper about the history of the Stern-Gerlach experiment and its reception and interpretation is given in https://arxiv.org/pdf/1609.09311.pdf
 
  • Informative
Likes Mentz114
  • #24
I noticed a very bold claim in the third paper on measurement.
"claims that the unmodeled environment influences the results enough to cause all randomness in quantum physics. "

I really like the thermal interpretation for the main reason that humans can only manipulate macroscopic objects, and our ability to control microscopic objects is manifest though our ability to manipulate macroscopic objects and however I find this conclusion very farfetched and probably wrong.

Why do you think you can make such a claim? How is this implied by the Thermal Interpretation?
 
  • #25
Prathyush said:
I noticed a very bold claim in the third paper on measurement.
"claims that the unmodeled environment influences the results enough to cause all randomness in quantum physics. " [...]
How is this implied by the Thermal Interpretation?
The quoted sentence is from the abtract of Part III. The justification is a cumulative argument developed in in Sections 4.2, 4.3, 5.1 and 5.2.

Section 4.2 discusses why all our knowledge about consequences of the quantum formalism for macroscopic objects and hence for measurement comes from coarse-graining the microscopic dynamics of all q_expectations to an effective dynamics for a much smaller collection of relevant quantities.

Section 4.3 demonstrates how coarse graining the linear dynamics of q-expectations produces a nonlinear, generally chaotic dynamics of the relevant quantities. (For example, turbulent Navier-Stokes equations.)

Section 5.1 shows that results by Breuer & Pettrucione may be reinterpreted in the thermal interpretation as implying that the piecewise deterministic processes for some well-known model quantum systems are obtainable by coarse-graining. The last paragraphs reads:
Section 5.1 of Part III said:
The arguments show that to go from unitarity to irreversible discrete events in Hamiltonian quantum mechanics one does not need to assume more than to go from reversibility to irreversibility in Hamiltonian classical mechanics – namely a suitable form of the Markov approximation. Statistical assumptions are not needed to make pointers acquire a well- defined position or to create photocurrents – the standard dissipation arguments are enough. This gives stochastic equations for definite macroscopic outcomes.

Finally, Section 5.2 gives an intuitive reason that allows a better understanding of these technical developments in B&P. It is shown that the behavior discussed is fully analogous to how chaotic nonlinear phenomena in classical chaotic systems lead through bistability to binary outcomes for the observation of continuous outcomes, like in the tossing of a coin, where the common understanding is that the randomness in the unmodeled envionment (i.e., details about how the coin is thrown and lands before it settles into one of two possible equilibrium states) influences the results enough to cause all randomness in the coin toss. The coin toss is paradigmatic for the way in which randomness appears through coarse-graining in classical physics. It is generally believed to be the only such mechanism, without discussing each individual case again.

By analogy, the randomness in the unmodeled envionment (i.e., details about how the state of system plus environment behaves before it settles into one of two possible collapsed states) influences the results enough to cause all randomness in the observation of a qubit.

This is paradigmatic for all quantum processes, and leads to the assertion in the abstract.
 

1. What is the thermal interpretation?

The thermal interpretation is a scientific concept that explains the behavior of matter at the atomic and molecular level. It states that the motion and energy of particles determine their physical properties and behavior, such as temperature and phase changes.

2. How does the thermal interpretation relate to thermodynamics?

The thermal interpretation is closely related to thermodynamics, as it provides a microscopic explanation for the macroscopic principles of thermodynamics. It helps to understand how energy is transferred and transformed in systems, and how this affects their properties.

3. What are some real-life applications of the thermal interpretation?

The thermal interpretation has many practical applications, including the design of heat engines, refrigeration systems, and materials with specific thermal properties. It is also used in fields such as meteorology, engineering, and chemistry.

4. What are the main principles of the thermal interpretation?

The main principles of the thermal interpretation include the kinetic theory of gases, which states that gas particles are constantly in motion and have kinetic energy, and the laws of thermodynamics, which describe the behavior of energy in systems.

5. Are there any limitations to the thermal interpretation?

While the thermal interpretation is a useful and widely accepted concept, it does have some limitations. It does not take into account the effects of quantum mechanics at extremely small scales, and it cannot fully explain certain phenomena, such as phase transitions at absolute zero temperature.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
24
Replies
826
Views
69K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
5
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
94
Views
11K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
42
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
48
Views
4K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
49
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
59
Views
10K
Back
Top