A MWI and the entangled photon experiment

  • A
  • Thread starter Thread starter kered rettop
  • Start date Start date
  • #51
kith said:
I don't see how we can do without it.

If I prepare the single particle state ##|\uparrow\rangle + |\!\downarrow\rangle## and perform the corresponding spin measurement, branching occurs. Have I measured spin up or spin down? On the one hand, we have to say "There's a world where I have measured spin up and a world where I have measured spin down. But looking at the needle of my apparatus I see it pointing upwards and conclude "I have measured spin up".

So either we have a contradiction or the "I"s in the previous two sentences don't refer to the same thing. The "I" in the second sentence is what I would call something like an "instance", "version", etc. of the generic "I" of the first sentence.
Vaidman's description is probably useful here. Re/ a measurement in a conventional Stern-Gerlach experiment, he says.
Vaidman said:
The MWI tells that in the future there will be “I” that see “up” and another “I” that see “down”. In the MWI I advocate, it is meaningless to ask which “I” shall “I”, making the experiment, be. There is nothing in the theory which connects “I” before the experiment to just one of the future “I”s
I.e. All instances of you after the experiment are distinct, but equally continuous with the instance of you before the experiment. An alternative approach is offered by Wilson. He accounts for scenarios like the above with diverging instances of you. I.e. even before measurement there were two instances of you. They are just qualitative duplicates. And after measurement, they diverge, each continuous with their own history. Ultimately there is no single account agreed upon by all Everettians.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes mattt and gentzen
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
Morbert said:
Ultimately there is no single account agreed upon by all Everettians.

Is that fair on Everettians? You-counting would appear to be a matter of semantics. The two approaches are different and I liked your clear exposition, thank you. But the physics is the same whether you leave the wave function intact or chop it up (I hesitate to use the word decompose!) into two identical half-amplitude wave functions.

So, should you say "There's one you spread over two wave functions" , or "There are two yous, one in each wave function"? It depends on the context, there is no single correct way. They are not different accounts, though, that's for sure. I think.
 
Last edited:
  • #53
DrChinese said:
1. None of my comments in this post should be taken as disagreement with you. Every time I examine what MWI says about the details, I get squirmy answers (in sources supporting MWI) to the obvious tough questions. So let's examine your 2. and 3. in a very specific MWI example.
I didn't take it as disagreement with my opinions. As I said, I don't understand, what the MWI solves wrt. the observable facts, which for me imply that there's "objective randomness" in Nature, i.e., that we cannot find any causes for the outcome of a measurement of an observable which was not determined by the state preparation before this measurement. For me, from a purely empirical point of view, it also doesn't help that MWI claims that the universe splits into branches, because this also doesn't explain in any way, why the outcome on a specific system was the one that is observed in "my branch".
DrChinese said:


We have a straight Type I PDC setup outputting a pair of entangled photons in the |HH> + |VV> Bell basis. The inputs are single photons oriented diagonal at 45 degrees (which could also be considered an equal superposition of |H> + |V>). Each entangled output pair is sent to linear polarization detector setups far distant from each other, and are measured at the same angle - but at an angle randomly selected mid-flight and outside the light cone of the photons at time of selection. Here are the questions I have:
The input photons are prepared in the pure state
$$\hat{\rho}_{12}=|\Psi \rangle \langle \Psi| \quad \text{with} \quad \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (|HH \rangle +|VV \rangle).$$
The single photons' state is then given by the so-called "reduced state", which is the partial trace over the other photon. You get
$$\hat{\rho}_1 = \hat{\rho}_2=\frac{1}{2} \hat{1}.$$
They are not in a pure state but in the maximally uncertain (maximum entropy) state, i.e., perfectly unpolarized photons.

DrChinese said:
i. The output pairs must not yet have a specific definite polarization, correct? Because we need them to match at whatever angle they are to be detected at, and that has not been selected yet. So they must still be in a superposition (due to their "preparation" as you call it).
Indeed they their polarization is maximally uncertain.

DrChinese said:
ii. The selected angle by some RNG is 120 degrees. Alice measures first (say), and gets result V. When exactly does that branching occur? We know in some other MWI branch the outcome was definitely H, right? The polarization detection setup itself consists of 3 components: the polarizing beam splitter (PBS) and the 2 avalanche detectors (one H, and one V). The branching occurs at one or more of these spots: a) the PBS; b) the V detector; and/or c) the H detector (which didn't fire in our branch). And in fact, the relative time of fire of the V and H detectors can be adjusted (by distance of placement after the PBS) so that they are clearly separated. Where/when does the branching occur? a)? Of course, this is a point at which the action is still reversible. b)? Of course, there has certainly been branching by this point in our particular branch, because we measured the V outcome. c)? The H detector did not fire in our branch, but we are certain it did in the other branch. But that outcome presumably came later in that branch, right?
You select to set both polarization filters to be oriented at an angle ##\phi## wrt. the direction you label with H. The states when measuring the linear polarization wrt. to that direction I label with ##|\phi_{\parallel} \rangle## and ##|\phi_{\perp} \rangle##. In terms of the original basis it's
$$|\phi_{\parallel} \rangle=\cos \phi |H \rangle + \sin \phi |V \rangle, \quad |\phi_{\perp} \rangle=-\sin \phi |H \rangle + \cos \phi |V \rangle.$$
The possible outcomes are ##\phi_{\parallel} \phi_{\parallel}##, ##\phi_{\parallel} \phi_{\perp}##, ##\phi_{\perp} \phi{\parallel}##, and ##\phi_{\perp} \phi_{\perp}##. The probabilities are given by
$$\langle \phi_{\parallel} \phi_{\parallel}|\Psi \rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (\cos^2 \phi+\sin^2 \phi)=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} \Rightarrow P(\phi_{\parallel},\phi_{\parallel})=1/2,$$
$$\langle \phi_{\parallel} \phi_{\perp}|\Psi \rangle=\langle \phi_{\perp} \phi_{\parallel}|\Psi \rangle =\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (-\cos \phi \sin \phi + \cos \phi \sin \phi)=0 \Rightarrow P(\phi_{\parallel},\phi_{\perp})= P(\phi_{\perp},\phi_{\parallel})=0,$$
$$\langle \phi_{\perp} \phi_{\perp}|\Psi \rangle=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (\sin^2 \phi + \cos^2 \phi)=\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} \; \Rightarrow \; P(\phi_{\perp},\phi_{\perp})=\frac{1}{2},$$
i.e., you get with probability 1/2 either both photons being ##\phi_{\parallel}##-polarized or both photons being ##\phi_{\perp}## polarized, i.e., you have 100% correlation between the outcome of measurements although the single photons' polarization states where maximally uncertain before the measurement.
DrChinese said:
iii. Here's the hard part: how does the branching from ii. above affect the photon Bob is getting ready to detect? That photon is far away. How does the branching action over by Alice affect Bob? Because we presumably determined Bob's photon was still in superposition as a result of i. above, right? Some of us here suspect that something "nonlocal" might be occurring. Even Vaidman seems to acknowledge something along this line. To quote, and note that there were no answers to any of my questions in his paper (and certainly no answers in his "next" section):

"But there are connections between different parts of the Universe, the wave function of the Universe is entangled. Entanglement is the essence of the nonlocality of the Universe. “Worlds” correspond to sets of well localized objects all over in space, so, in this sense, worlds are nonlocal entities. Quantum measurements performed on entangled particles lead to splitting of worlds with different local descriptions. Frequently such measurements lead to quantum paradoxes which will be discussed in the next section."
I'd say the branching occurs as soon as the outcome of the first measurement occuring. I.e., in your assumption when A's detector fixes the polarization state of her photon. Then, because of the preparation in the original entangled state, according to our above analysis, the other photon's polarization, i.e., what Bob will measure later, is also determined to be the same, because you have ##\phi_{\parallel} \phi_{\parallel}## or ##\phi_{\perp} \phi_{\perp}##, and thus the split is in these two possible branches.
DrChinese said:
But in his parlance, whatever "nonlocal" occurs cannot quality as "action at a distance". I don't have a particular objection to this characterization, but I would not call it "spot on" either.
According to relativistic QFT there's no action at a distance. What's non-local is the correlation due to the preparation in the entangled state, i.e., a correlation between the outcomes of measurements at far distant polarization-measurement places, not the interaction between the measurement devices and the single photons. They are local at the place where the equipment is built up to measure the polarization.

The above analysis in fact is based on the assumption that A's measurement doesn't influence in any way B's photon, before B measures its polarization.
DrChinese said:
iv. And finally, this little gem of a question which is often overlooked with Type I PDC. We may say MWI is deterministic, but this leads to something of a paradox. Type I PDC consists of 2 thin orthogonal crystals placed face to face. One has an input of H and produces |VV>, while the other takes an input of V and produces output of |HH>. Neither of those are entangled outputs! So how does the entanglement occur? The answer is that the diagonal input to the pair of crystals takes an indistinguishable path, and the particular spot where down conversion occurs is indeterminate. So for the MWI explanation to make sense, we need to assert that NO branching occurs as the input photon splits into 2 entangled photons. What? So branching occurs everywhere else BUT the very spot where/when there's a choice of paths through the PDC setup. Huh?
As you say, the entanglement occurs, because you can't say whether you get ##|VV \rangle## or ##HH \rangle## when choosing precisely those photon pairs, where this "which-way information" is not known, i.e., that they come out precisely in the said state ##\hat{\rho}_{12}##.

Concerning the PDC process you have of course a lot of splittings, according to all possible outcomes of sending a coherent laser-light state into the crystal. The two-photon down-conversion probabilities are usually in the order of magnitude of ##10^{-6}## only!
DrChinese said:
We must have the entangled pair exit in a superposition for the rest of the MWI magic to occur. And yet, we need there to be branching by the time Alice and Bob read and record their respective results. But aren't we capable of establishing a consistent rule as to when branching occurs that doesn't appear ad hoc? Because I say that according to the MWI concept of definite deterministic outcomes: the diagonal input photon split at either the H PDC crystal (in our branch) or the V PDC crystal (in the other branch, or vice versa) - and would NOT have led to an entangled state if either of those things occurred. They would instead exit as VV or HH, and there would not be perfect correlations when later measured at 120 degrees (as selected by the RNG).
But I thought according to MWI the splitting always occurs according to the possible outcomes of measurements given the state, i.e., the branchings can only be into 100% correlated ##120_{\parallel} 120_{\parallel}## or ##120_{\perp} 120_{\perp}## branches.
DrChinese said:


Making sense of this kind of setup causes me all kinds of confusion, and yet this is precisely the kind of experiment that a viable interpretation should explain today. I am *not* trying to support or reject MWI by any of my comments, I am just trying to understand the rules MWI plays by. Every interpretation seems to have some consistency issues at some level, and I believe MWI does too.
I think, all that can be observed are what's really measured, and the outcome is random, i.e., there's no cause for a specific outcome. What "additional explanation" MWI gives, to solve this quibble of the measurement problem, i.e., to find a cause for the specific outcome, I never understood since in which branch of the world my equipment will be and determining to what I as the experimenter read off as a measurement result is simply random with probabilities given by Born's rule.
 
  • #54
kered rettop said:
Is that fair on Everettians? You-counting would appear to be a matter of semantics. The two approaches are different and I liked your clear exposition, thank you. But the physics is the same whether you leave the wave function intact or chop it up (I hesitate to use the word decompose!) into two identical half-amplitude wave functions.

So, should you say "There's one you spread over two wave functions" , or "There are two yous, one in each wave function"? It depends on the context, there is no single correct way. They are not different accounts, though, that's for sure. I think.
The use of "I" and "you" either way is fine so long as everyone is on the same page. The differing accounts I was referring to was deeper though, pointing to ontological differences. E.g. Carroll and Sebens present a "global branching" account, where a measurement causes everywhere to branch instantly. Vaidman and Wallace present a local account where distant systems do not immediately branch. Wilson presents an account where numerically identical, overlapping branches are replaced with qualitatively duplicate, locally diverging histories. When you move into Everettian field theory it gets even hairier with ##\rho##-realism and spacetime-state realism. etc etc. All of these have different metaphysical commitments, with their own strengths and weaknesses.
 
  • Informative
  • Like
Likes kered rettop and PeroK
  • #55
Morbert said:
The use of "I" and "you" either way is fine so long as everyone is on the same page. The differing accounts I was referring to was deeper though, pointing to ontological differences. E.g. Carroll and Sebens present a "global branching" account, where a measurement causes everywhere to branch instantly. Vaidman and Wallace present a local account where distant systems do not immediately branch. Wilson presents an account where numerically identical, overlapping branches are replaced with qualitatively duplicate, locally diverging histories. When you move into Everettian field theory it gets even hairier with ##\rho##-realism and spacetime-state realism. etc etc. All of these have different metaphysical commitments, with their own strengths and weaknesses.
Great. Thanks. For what it's worth I think that "global branching vs local" can also be settled by being careful with what you mean. (I am moderately familiar with both ideas and know some of the reasoning behind them, though I'd have to grovel to Google to check whether it's what your authors mean.) The instantaneous branching presumably reflects the way the global wave function branches; the local branching presumably reflects the expansion of the region which has actually interacted with the system in decoherence and where information about the interaction has reached. Totally different things, therefore no confusion - as long as you make sure you don't use the same word. No idea what people mean when they talk about different kinds of realism. K.I.S.S. is what I say!
 
Last edited:
  • #56
DrChinese said:
Read the Vaidman 2014 paper also. Although I disagree strongly with his final conclusion(s)*, he covers the pros and cons better than anything I've seen anywhere else. It's 25 pages, and 175 references!

*"The theory of Universal wave function is deterministic, local, free of paradoxes, and fully consistent with
our experience.
"
That it is fully consistent with our experience is stretching a point, IMO. Or, to turn it round, our experience is hardly consistent with MWI!
 
  • #57
Morbert said:
You adopted a specific convention re/pronouns, not insisted upon by the interpretation
I don't know what you mean. You have to take into account what I said about pronouns in order to talk consistently about the MWI. You cannot use pronouns the way we do in ordinary language; if you do, you will be saying wrong things about the MWI.

Morbert said:
They are pointing out that the lab experience of performing measurement and observing a unique outcome is not immediately squared with property instantiations in branching worlds.
And that means they do not think the MWI is correct. Which is fine in itself--but it does not mean they can misstate what the MWI says. The MWI says what it says, and requires pronouns to be interpreted in the way I described. You can't say, "Well, I think the MWI is wrong so I'm going to describe it in a way that misstates what it says."
 
  • #58
kered rettop said:
Surely MWI requires decoherence theory to complete it?
In the modern view, yes, decoherence is required for branching to occur in the MWI.

kered rettop said:
In which case there needs to be a third premiss, namely that there is an environment with certain properties, such as 1) a large number of degrees of freedom
A large number of untrackable degrees of freedom, yes.

kered rettop said:
2) a high degree of interactivity with the system
Not necessarily "high", just enough for entanglement to spread. Most of the interactivity could be within the environment itself; only a few degrees of freedom in the environment would need to interact with the system and the measuring apparatus.

kered rettop said:
and 3) the ability to propagate (disseminate or "amplify") information about an outcome.
This "information about an outcome" is not retrievable, so it is not where the person doing the experiment, for example, would read off the result. They would do that from the trackable degrees of freedom of the measuring apparatus.

The environment does of course "store information" about the outcome because that information gets spread through entanglement among the degrees of freedom in the environment. But the environment doesn't need any extra "ability" to do this; it's already there as soon as 1) and 2) above are satisfied.

kered rettop said:
you recently mentioned a case where there is no environmental interaction, namely the isolated entangled qubits in a quantum computer. They are, erroneously in your view and also in mine, referred to as worlds by some authors. Whatever they may be, they are not worlds in the MWI sense.
Yes, agreed. I believe I said that I do not think authors who talk this way are correct. (If I didn't in this thread, I have in other threads on this topic. :wink:)
 
  • Like
Likes kered rettop and gentzen
  • #59
Morbert said:
there is no single account agreed upon by all Everettians.
Yes. I believe I have commented before on this as well. That's why, when I describe the MWI, I focus on the basic premises that all accounts do share: that the wave function is real and contains all of reality, and that the dynamics is always unitary. I try to limit my discussion to what can be deduced just from those premises.
 
  • #60
kered rettop said:
The instantaneous branching presumably reflects the way the global wave function branches; the local branching presumably reflects the expansion of the region which has actually interacted with the system in decoherence and where information about the interaction has reached.
That's how I understand the two descriptions as well.

One of the references in another thread on "Is the MWI local" had what it claimed to be a completely local description, but this interpretation involved having each qubit carry with it a potentially unbounded amount of information about all of its past interactions (this information would play the same role as the global wave function in the "instantaneous branching" interpretation).
 
  • Like
Likes kered rettop
  • #61
kered rettop said:
For what it's worth I think that "global branching vs local" can also be settled by being careful with what you mean. (I am moderately familiar with both ideas and know some of the reasoning behind them, though I'd have to grovel to Google to check whether it's what your authors mean.) The instantaneous branching presumably reflects the way the global wave function branches; the local branching presumably reflects the expansion of the region which has actually interacted with the system in decoherence and where information about the interaction has reached. Totally different things, therefore no confusion - as long as you make sure you don't use the same word. No idea what people mean when they talk about different kinds of realism. K.I.S.S. is what I say!
Vaidman describes his stance re/ Sebens and Carroll here
Vaidman said:
Contrary to our analysis, Sebens and Carroll work under the assumption that “branching happens throughout the wavefunction whenever it happens anywhere". [...] Consequently, “observers here on Earth could be (and almost surely are) branching all the time, without noticing it, due to quantum evolution of systems in the Andromeda Galaxy." [...] Sebens and Carroll concede that this global branching picture is psychologically unintuitive (p11). But it also goes against the spirit of the many worlds interpretation, which involves removing as much nonlocality as possible. Thus, after removing the nonlocality of collapse, they reinsert a different kind of nonlocality.
Vaidman hopes to find a separable description of the wavefunction, but accepts that it doesn't exist at the moment. He accepts this kind of nonlocality. But he sees the Sebens and Carroll account as elevating nonseparability to a stronger nonlocality, where doing something here instantly affects something there. I don't see how this disagreement can be attributed to a confusion due to imprecise use of words.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes kered rettop, PeterDonis and gentzen
  • #62
PeterDonis said:
That's how I understand the two descriptions as well.

One of the references in another thread on "Is the MWI local" had what it claimed to be a completely local description, but this interpretation involved having each qubit carry with it a potentially unbounded amount of information about all of its past interactions (this information would play the same role as the global wave function in the "instantaneous branching" interpretation).
We seem to be agreeing to an unnerving degree today, Peter. I think I'd better quit while I'm winning,
 
  • #63
PeterDonis said:
A large number of untrackable degrees of freedom...
Fair enough. I was not trying to define the third postulate precisely, only to point out there has to be one. Happy to leave the details to people who are capable.
 
Back
Top