Preferred Basis and Superposition

In summary, the conversation discusses the concept of superposition and the basis problem within the Many Worlds Hypothesis. It is explained that when in a superposition state of an observable, one is also in a definite state of another observable. The mathematical representation of the splitting of the superposition component states is questioned as to whether it is a real ontological split or just part of the mathematical eigenbasis representation chosen. It is clarified that the process of doing the math is not the same as the process of doing a measurement. The favored basis is determined by the physical setup of the experiment. Finally, the concept of equality with respect to mass is used as an analogy to explain the distinction between mathematical representation and physical reality.
  • #1
Cp3
6
0
Hi Guys, I have a question about observable's and superposition's that I haven't been able to find a definitive answer to (purely for the fact that it doesn't seem to be addressed), and would greatly appreciate an answer.

When in a superposition state of an observable, you are also in a definite state of another observable. For example, suppose you have two incompatible observable's from the 1/2 spin states: X-spins and Z-spins. If you are in a definite X-up position, then you are in a superposition of Z-spin down and Z spin up. So mathematically we could express this as:

[tex](1.0)\mid S_x=+ \frac{1}{2}> = a\mid S_z=+\frac{1}{2}> + b\mid S_x=-\frac{1}{2}>[/tex]
Where: [tex]\mid a \mid ^2 +\mid b \mid ^2 =1[/tex]

In the MWH (Many Worlds Hypothesis), we have a problem known as the 'basis problem'. Essentially the crux of the problem is due to the fact that when we perceive the 'collapse of the wavefunction' and thus the splitting of the superposition component states into different branches (or worlds), it all is all dependent on the observable we choose to use, so is the mathematical representation of the splitting a real ontological split or just part of the mathematical eigenbasis representation we chose? That is the 'basis problem' in the MWH.

Now that makes sense to me, but it made me think about superpositions and choosing an observable to measure in general and what it actually means (regardless if we adhere to the MWH or not).

So my question going back to equation (1.0) is: if the system is in a definite state of X spin-up, does that mean X spin-up is a superposition of the Z-spin? So when we have a definite state of X-spin up, are we are also observing a superposition of the Z-spins (a superposition of Z spins is the definite state of X spin up) or is it just Z-spins are in a superposition, when we have a definite X spin-up?

I know the distinction can be hard to grasp so I'm trying to make an effort to spell it out. What I'm trying to say is, because the mathematical Hilbert space representation says X spin-up equals the superposition of z-spin down and z-spin up, does that mean they are identical things? Being in an X-spin up state is a superposition of z-spin down and z-spin up? Or is it just the case that when a particle is in a definite state of X spin-up, the other observable Z-spins are in a superposition, but they are not identical things?
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
If you are in a definite X-up position, then you are in a superposition of Z-spin down and Z spin up.
Correction: If you are in a definite spin z state, you are also in a superposition of x and y states.

so is the mathematical representation of the splitting a real ontological split or just part of the mathematical eigenbasis representation we chose?
That is the issue - but it makes no difference in fact.

Note: The process of doing the math is not the same thing as the process of doing a measurement.

The basis, irl, depends on the experimental setup - the rest is just maths.
i.e. the reason we care about a particular spin component is that there is some apparatus imposing some directionality wrt the spin.

More generally - just because we can expand out a state vector in a basis does not mean anything about the physical situation ... just like we may have 4lbs of mass... we also know that 2+2=4, but that does not mean that it makes sense in every situation to say that out 4lbs of mass is literally the same as having two separate 2lb masses. It just tells us what we may be able to have should the situation warrant (the mass passes through a cutting machine).
 
Last edited:
  • #3
Simon Bridge said:
Correction: If you are in a definite spin z state, you are also in a superposition of x and y states.

Yes my mista'ke, I should've stated I was assuming the partial representation of spin states in R^2 for simplicity of my illustration (since y spin states are represented in C^2).

My question however was not about the basis problem as it pertains to the MWH, but rather my query further in the post.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
Note: a specific z state for spin is not "the same thing" as the superposition of x and y states.
But as you note - that just means you pulled a poor example out of your hat.

It is possible to represent a state vector as a superposition of eigenstates of some observable.
There are many such superpositions possible.

You are asking about the physical reality of the superposition.
It's not real - it's just maths. The physical setup of the experiment determines the favored basis.
i.e. in the Stern-Gerlach experiment, the apparatus decides on which direction counts as z. Without the magnets, all spin components are uncertain.

Note: I edited the previous post while you were replying.
 
  • Like
Likes 1 person
  • #5
Simon Bridge said:
More generally - just because we can expand out a state vector in a basis does not mean anything about the physical situation ... just like we may have 4lbs of mass... we also know that 2+2=4, but that does not mean that it makes sense in every situation to say that out 4lbs of mass is literally the same as having two separate 2lb masses. It just tells us what we may be able to have should the situation warrant (the mass passes through a cutting machine).

The reason we 2+2=4 is not 'literally' the same as having two separate 2lb masses is because the equality sign in that respect is not in relation to entities but rather 'mass'. It is the case that 2lb+2lb is identical to 4lb with 'respect to the mass'. The equality sign in that equation (=) represents identity with respect to mass not anything else.

If I had apples which were all 2lb's each and banana's which were also 2lb's each per unit. Then i can easily construct the mathematical equation 2apples (lb) = 2 banana's (lb), since they are 'identical' in respects to mass. But it would be absurd to say 2 apples = 2 banana's without specification because those two things are not identical with respect to colour, appearance, taste, geometrical shape etc.

So in regards to superposition, I am asking, what is the equality sign referring with respect to? Is it saying a definite X Spin-up state is the superposition of Z states (and Y states) or that whenever we have a definite X Spin-up state, we will also have superposition's of Z and Y states?

If we take the former to be true, then it is possible for us to say that being in a definite X state is what it means to be in a superposition of Z and Y states. To imagine a superposition of Y and Z states is to see an definite X-state, since they are identical.

Simon Bridge said:
You are asking about the physical reality of the superposition.
It's not real - it's just maths.

Well that is the question. Alot of physicists and philosophers would say a superposition is represented in physical reality rather than just being a mathematical construct. That is after all how the many worlds hypothesis came to be. Its adherents believes that the wavefunction is a true physcial construct which obeys the dynamical evolution as postulated by the Schrodinger equation and superposition is a real feature of reality, its just the constituents states of superposition's occupy different worlds which cannot be directly measured within 'our' world, hence why they had the 'basis problem' in the first place. If the splitting of worlds is predicated on the wave function which was to be regarded as real - which 'basis' should it take? since there is an infinite amount of ways of representing observable's. A good book talking about the ontology of the wavefunction is The Wave Function: Essays on the Metaphysics of Quantum Mechanics edited by Alyssa Ney and David Albert. But that's correct, I was trying to ask what is the true physical meaning of a superposition. If you take the statistical view of QM and see it rather as an instrumental tool than actually representing physical reality, then of course my questions would seem quite irrelevant.

But thanks anyway in showing me why it seems I don't see this question directly addressed within textbooks, considering i assume many physicists would follow your interpretation of the mathematics, and wouldn't be interested in the interpretational issues of QM but the more 'practical' aspects of the theory.
 
Last edited:
  • #6
So in regards to superposition, I am asking, what is the equality sign referring with respect to?
Maths.

But thanks anyway in showing me why it seems I don't see this question directly addressed within textbooks, considering i assume many physicists would follow your interpretation of the mathematics, and wouldn't be interested in the interpretational issues of QM but the more 'practical' aspects of the theory.
That topic is banned here. You want a quantum philosophy forum.
 
  • #7
I was asking what is the equality sign (=) referring to? The equality sign is a mathematical symbol so I don't know what you mean by its referring to maths, I'm asking what is it referring to as being equal between the LHS and RHS of the equation. In the (2 + 2)lb = 4lb example, the equality sign (this '=' sign) is referring to equality of masses. The mass of the LHS equals (is in equality, is identical, is the same as - they all mean the same thing they all mean this '=' symbol) the mass of the RHS of the equation.

All I'm asking is what is the equality sign (=) is referring to being equal to in the superposition equation in (1.0)? What's the physical interpretation of the mathematics. That is not a philosophical question, we interpret the mathematics to be different things all the time. Calculus for example can be used to represent economic, physics or social science phenomena, they're all interpretations of the mathematics into physical reality - the maths abstractly doesn't mean anything.

So once again, I'm just asking, what is the LHS of equation (1.0) equal to, in the RHS of the equation? As I showed earlier the 2+2=4 example you showed, the equality sign just tells us the masses of the LHS and the RHS are equal, not anything else. Simply I am asking what is equal with respect to the LHS and RHS of the wavefunction equation in (1.0).
 
  • #8
When we say that |z> = a|x> + b|y> we mean exactly that state vector |z> is mathematically the same thing as a|x> + b|y> ... if you were to work out the full mathematical structure behind the symbols you'd end up with the same numbers for both sides. It's just maths.

A wavefunction can be expanded in a wide range of different bases.
This has no meaning by itself. It's just different ways of writing it down using different symbols. It's just maths.

The wavefunction does not mean anything until you operate on it - then the outcome of the operation may be assigned a meaning.

[edit] I have a feeling I'm talking at a tangent to what you are asking though.
 
Last edited:
  • #9
Cp3 said:
If the splitting of worlds is predicated on the wave function which was to be regarded as real - which 'basis' should it take?

This is the so called preferred basis problem.

You need to consult tomes on decoherence for exactly how that happens - eg a bit of a technical argument shows that for radial type interactions (which are the majority) a position basis is usually singled out.

If you want to pursue it further the book to get is Schlosshauer's:
https://www.amazon.com/dp/3540357734/?tag=pfamazon01-20

Regarding what superposition means its simply an artifact of the math of QM. Technically the reason has to do with having continuous transformations between so called pure states. If you want to pursue this check out:
http://www.scottaaronson.com/democritus/lec9.html

At an even deeper level it has to do with entanglement:
http://arxiv.org/abs/0911.0695

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • Like
Likes 1 person
  • #10
Yeah, I was just spelling out what the preferred basis problem was in the context of the Many Worlds Hypothesis, I knew what it was hence the title of the thread. Thank you very much though for the further readings, this will help me a lot with my honours thesis that I'm getting prepared for. The first book looks like a great introduction to decoherence.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Note that when you say 4lb = 4lb, you are saying the number of pounds are equal. You have assigned units, which makes it "more understandable" in a way. When you say 2 = 2 with no units its difficult to say what a standalone 2, with no units, represents other than the value or state 2. So how does one talk about the units or value of the state vector |x> + |y>, or assign it meaning when it stands alone? Or even |z>? It's a notation that represents numbers or values describing the possible states of a system. The state of the system is the sum of the states of 2 sub-systems?
 
  • #13
bhobba said:
This is the so called preferred basis problem.

You need to consult tomes on decoherence for exactly how that happens - eg a bit of a technical argument shows that for radial type interactions (which are the majority) a position basis is usually singled out.

If you want to pursue it further the book to get is Schlosshauer's:
https://www.amazon.com/dp/3540357734/?tag=pfamazon01-20

Regarding what superposition means its simply an artifact of the math of QM. Technically the reason has to do with having continuous transformations between so called pure states. If you want to pursue this check out:
http://www.scottaaronson.com/democritus/lec9.html

At an even deeper level it has to do with entanglement:
http://arxiv.org/abs/0911.0695

Thanks
Bill

Did I understand you to say that talking about quantum interpretations is banned on this forum? Because invoking 'decoherence' as a solution to the preferred basis problem is an interpretational approach that is not immune to problems. E.g. there is circular argumentation involved there. The original poster is asking very good questions about what determines the basis of measurement. These are best answered by taking absorption into account, i.e., in the transactional picture.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #14
Cp3 said:
Yeah, I was just spelling out what the preferred basis problem was in the context of the Many Worlds Hypothesis, I knew what it was hence the title of the thread. Thank you very much though for the further readings, this will help me a lot with my honours thesis that I'm getting prepared for. The first book looks like a great introduction to decoherence.

It's THE book on decoherence.

I always recommend it to people after they have a good foundation in QM and an interest in interpretations - it explains the issues clearly - as well as the problems. And even aside from its value wrt interpretations its a very important and interesting phenomena.

I don't know your background in QM but I think its very important when doing anything related to this area to understand its exact axiomatic basis.

Its really based on two axioms and in fact the superposition principle is really a consequence of one of those axioms called the Born Rule. Schrodinger's equation etc actually follow from symmetry, and are not really separate axioms - which is also a VERY important foundational point - even aside the fact its a pretty amazing result in and of itself.

You will find this approach in what I (and others) think is THE book on QM - Ballentine - Quantum Mechanics - A Modern Development:
https://www.amazon.com/dp/9810241054/?tag=pfamazon01-20

The other interesting thing is the Born Rule is not entirely independent of the first axiom (it's that the possible outcomes of an observation are the eigenvalues of its observable). There is this marvelous theorem called Gleason's Theorem that shows it follows from that if you assume basis independence:
http://kof.physto.se/theses/helena-master.pdf

It seems almost like magic that QM can be derived from just one axiom. Of course it can't - its just that in this approach each further assumption is simply very reasonable eg in Gleason's Theorem it's very reasonable to assume your measure is basis independent - but it's an assumption - and careful analysis shows its quite a strong one at that leading to what's called non-contextuality.

Anyway I do strongly suggest you at least scan through the first 3 chapters of Ballentine. Once you do that you will see, for example, the superposition principle is a pretty trivial requirement following from the Born rule for so called pure states. But I won't go into it further - its better if you nut it out.

Post here if you have any problems.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • Like
Likes 1 person
  • #15
meBigGuy said:
Note that when you say 4lb = 4lb, you are saying the number of pounds are equal. You have assigned units, which makes it "more understandable" in a way. When you say 2 = 2 with no units its difficult to say what a standalone 2, with no units, represents other than the value or state 2. So how does one talk about the units or value of the state vector |x> + |y>, or assign it meaning when it stands alone? Or even |z>? It's a notation that represents numbers or values describing the possible states of a system. The state of the system is the sum of the states of 2 sub-systems?

That's exactly what I was trying to get at before. What property is the LHS and RHS equal with respect to in equation 1.0? Like I said earlier, you can say 2 Banana's (4lb) = 2 Apple's (4lb) because the equality sign is with respect to the mass of the LHS and RHS as being equal even though 2 Bananas do not equal 2 Apples with respect to other properties. I could say 1 Banana is 2lb and 10 oranges are 2lbs thus 1 bannana (lb) = 10 oranges (lb) with respect to mass, however without that interpretation 1 = 10 does not make any sense.
 
Last edited:
  • #16
rkastner said:
Did I understand you to say that talking about quantum interpretations is banned on this forum? Because invoking 'decoherence' as a solution to the preferred basis problem is an interpretational approach that is not immune to problems. E.g. there is circular argumentation involved there. The original poster is asking very good questions about what determines the basis of measurement. These are best answered by taking absorption into account, i.e., in the transactional picture.

It's not banned - just kept on a tight reign to ensure it doesn't slip on over to philosophy which is off-topic for this forum.

And decoherence does have issues in explaining all aspects of the preferred basis problem (in particular the problem of why we get any outcomes at all - which is a doodle in your interpretation, MW, Bohm etc - but by itself decoherence can't do it) - but the standard text I linked to explains carefully what it does and does not do.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #17
Thanks -- although from what I've seen, Schlosshauer does not really acknowledge the extent of the circularity facing the decoherence account of the preferred basis.
 
  • #18
Cp3 said:
What property is the LHS and RHS equal with respect to in equation 1.0? Like I said earlier, you can say 2 Banana's (4lb) = 2 Apple's (4lb) because the equality sign is with respect to the mass of the LHS and RHS as being equal. I could say 1 Banana is 2lb and 10 oranges are 2lbs thus 1 bannana (lb) = 10 oranges (lb) with respect to mass, however without that interpretation 1 = 10 does not make any sense.

OK. I was hoping you would nut it out for yourself from Ballentine, but I can see its something that's perplexing you a bit so I will make a stab at it now.

A key foundational axiom of QM is the so called Born rule.

It says given an observable O then there exists a positive operator of unit trace P such that the expected value of the observation associated with O is Trace (PO). By definition P is called the state of the system.

By definition states of the form |x><x| are called pure. States that are the convex sum of pure states are called mixed ie of the form ∑ pi |xi><xi| pi positive, ∑ pi = 1. It can be shown all states are either mixed or pure.

The usual states you read about in beginning and intermediate texts on QM are pure states - but in fact its a lot wider than that including mixed states. This is explained carefully in Ballentine. The other thing is they are not elements of a vector space - they are operators. But for pure states one can associate the |x> in |x><x| with elements of the underlying vector space - but not uniquely - multiplying by a phase factor gives exactly the same operator. Its this association that leads to the superposition property, principle, or whatever you want to call it - it's simply that it forms a vector space - which is hardly surprising since you have mapped it to a vector space. What such an equality 'means' is determined by the Born rule - you can derive all sorts of connections - but I will leave you to play around with that.

Please do read Ballentione - he explains it all carefully.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes 1 person
  • #19
rkastner said:
Thanks -- although from what I've seen, Schlosshauer does not really acknowledge the extent of the circularity facing the decoherence account of the preferred basis.

He is pretty careful in looking at its problems, and explaining you need further interpretative assumptions to make use of it.

I don't think the issue is one of circularity but, for things like why we get any outcomes at all, decoherence is silent about.

Although it must be said that tracing over the environment can only be justified by first assuming the Born Rule, so later you can't use the improper mixed state that comes out of that to justify the Born rule - that is circular. One must accept tracing over the environment as a separate process and interpret that to avoid circularity. Care is certainly required to prevent circularity.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #20
Quantumental said:
Interesting related paper on the basis problem in MWI: http://arxiv.org/abs/1210.8447

This is the so called factoring problem.

I originally thought Schlosshauer didn't cover it in his text - but my memory was faulty - he does.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #21
The circularity I'm concerned about is the same sort of problem facing Boltzmann's "H-theorem" allegedly proving that entropy always increases. Boltzmann assumed 'molecular disorder' to get the result, which amounted to assuming what he was trying to prove. Similarly, 'derivations' of decoherence assume that you can define already-decoherent environmental subsystems - i.e. they divide everything into observed system + environment where the environmental subsystems have random phases wrt each other and the system. Thus they have to presuppose a crucial degree of already-existing decoherence in order to 'demonstrate' the decoherence of the system's relevant degrees of freedom.
 
  • #22
rkastner said:
Thus they have to presuppose a crucial degree of already-existing decoherence in order to 'demonstrate' the decoherence of the system's relevant degrees of freedom.

That's the so called factoring problem a link was given about.

Indeed key theorems are missing showing regardless of how you factor it exactly the same basis results. I did come across a paper a while ago that, for a simple model, showed just that - but it needs to be greatly extended.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #23
bhobba said:
This is the so called factoring problem.

I originally thought Schlosshauer didn't cover it in his text - but my memory was faulty - he does.

Thanks
Bill

Could you please quote? Because this is new and interesting to me.
Recently I saw Max Tegmark had a knack at it, as well as Lev Vaidman recognizing it, so if it's already "solved" I would imagine these guys would've been in the know.
 
  • #24
Quantumental said:
Could you please quote? Because this is new and interesting to me.
Recently I saw Max Tegmark had a knack at it, as well as Lev Vaidman recognizing it, so if it's already "solved" I would imagine these guys would've been in the know.

Sorry mate - I didn't take note of where it was and quoting from texts is a bit painstaking.

I will have to leave it to you to get the book and check it out for yourself.

But its pretty simple really. Its simply that current derivations use a particular factoring into system, environment, and observational apparatus. A particular basis is then singled out. Theorems are necessary to prove it happens regardless of how its done.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #25
Thanks Bill --

But there would still be circularity even if such a theorem were found.

Showing that presupposing an already-decohered division can yield 'decoherence,' regardless of which division is presupposed, doesn't remove the circularity problem. What would have to be shown is that decoherence occurs when there is no presupposed decoherence to begin with, since that's the actual circumstance that's alleged in the program of using decoherence to solve the measurement problem --i.e., 'Quantum Darwinism", that the macroscopic world of appearance emerges naturally from a quantum foundation. In my view, this is why the program is overrated and does not really work as claimed. You need absorption to define the measurement process, and without that, you end up going in circles.
 
  • #26
rkastner said:
What would have to be shown is that decoherence occurs when there is no presupposed decoherence to begin with, since that's the actual circumstance that's alleged in the program of using decoherence to solve the measurement problem --i.e., 'Quantum Darwinism",

I can quite follow your reasoning here - I suspect its showing that outcomes occur at all which is a really big problem for the decoherehnce approach.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #27
Bhobba: that's not a solution though.

Currently the factorization problem is fatal for MWI. If it can't be overcome (which it seems it can't) then "pure MWI" is dead and gone. Demystifier has a Nice blogpost about this.
It means MWI has to add *something* which then puts it on par with all other interpretations. It has to postulate something without any evidence for that thing. Occam razor isn't happy With that.
 
  • #28
rkastner said:
Showing that presupposing an already-decohered division can yield 'decoherence,' regardless of which division is presupposed, doesn't remove the circularity problem.
I agree that we need to have a division into system+environment in order to derive decoherence. But what do you mean by the division being already decohered? Does this correspond to an assumption like the initial state of the combined system is a product state or do you have something different in mind?
 
  • #29
Quantumental said:
Currently the factorization problem is fatal for MWI. If it can't be overcome (which it seems it can't) then "pure MWI" is dead and gone. Demystifier has a Nice blogpost about this.
The problem with the argument you are referring to is that it applies to classical mechanics as well. In both QM and Hamiltonian mechanics, we can transform the dynamics of the whole system away. So in both cases there is some justification to say that in the big picture, nothing happens at all. Also in both cases, if we apply the theory to an experimental situation, we get non-trivial dynamics of the system of interest relative to the observer and the environment. Demystifier's/Schwindt's argument certainly doesn't invalidate Everett's interpretation which explicitly acknowledges this relative character of the states we use to describe experiments.

Now I know you like to associate the MWI with the idea that reality is identical to the mathematical structure. But although this may be the position of certain MWI proponents, it is not a necessary feature of the MWI. For example, I don't think you'll find this notion in any of Everett's publications.
 
  • #30
kith said:
I agree that we need to have a division into system+environment in order to derive decoherence. But what do you mean by the division being already decohered? Does this correspond to an assumption like the initial state of the combined system is a product state or do you have something different in mind?

Yes, basically. In decoherence 'derivations', the only interaction between system and environment is assumed to be due to a given interaction Hamiltonian and not due to any pre-existing quantum correlations. So that begs the question. As I've said, the only way to really get quantum correlations to go away is by genuine, irreversible collapse. For details on my proposal see my guest post on F. Moldoveanu's blog, here: http://fmoldove.blogspot.com/ (Part 2 is coming next week)
 
  • #31
kith said:
...So in both cases there is some justification to say that in the big picture, nothing happens at all. Also in both cases, if we apply the theory to an experimental situation, we get non-trivial dynamics of the system of interest relative to the observer and the environment. ...

This sounds a lot like Rovelli's approach, which I call 'radical relationalism'. It's explicitly observer-dependent and in that sense anti-realist. I think my approach is less radical: things really do happen; what exists isn't just relative to who's looking. And you get Von Neumann's 'process 1' as well as the Born Rule out of it. And it's readily extendable into the relativistic domain, which helps to define emission and absorption and thereby the measurement process itself. I'll be dealing with the latter issues in part 2 of my blog post next week at http://fmoldove.blogspot.com/
 
  • #32
bhobba said:
If you want to pursue it further the book to get is Schlosshauer's:
This is the most recent paper I've seen by Schlosshauer discussing his views on decoherence:
...Thus if we understand the quantum measurement problem as the question of how to reconcile the linear, deterministic evolution described by the Schrodinger equation with the occurrence of random, definite measurement outcomes, then decoherence has certainly not solved this problem, as is now widely recognized. What decoherence rather solves is a consistency problem: the problem of explaining why and when quantum probability distributions approach the classically expected distributions. But this is a purely practical problem, not a game-changer for quantum foundations. To be sure, the picture associated with the decoherence process has sometimes been claimed to be suggestive of particular interpretations of quantum mechanics or to pinpoint internal consistency issues. But it might be safer to say that certain interpretations (such as the Everett interpretation) are simply more in need of decoherence to define their structure...
Entanglement, scaling, and the meaning of the wave function in protective measurement
http://arxiv.org/pdf/1402.1217.pdf
 
  • #33
bhobba said:
I can quite follow your reasoning here - I suspect its showing that outcomes occur at all which is a really big problem for the decoherehnce approach.

Thanks
Bill

Bhobba is decoherance still a valid explanation?
 
  • #34
To clarify, I'm arguing that nobody has really 'derived' decoherence because they are assuming it at the beginning by the so-called 'factoring' in system vs environment. This problem would not be solved by a theorem to the effect that any factorization gives you the right decoherence properties. This is because it would still presume decoherence in order to 'derive' decoherrence. Decoherence cannot happen without collapse, which is what actually decoheres quantum correlations. It is collapse that actally does the decohering, so 'decoherence' without collapse is not a valid explanation of the appearance of definite outcomes.
 
  • #35
rkastner said:
This sounds a lot like Rovelli's approach, which I call 'radical relationalism'. It's explicitly observer-dependent and in that sense anti-realist.
Actually, I was talking about the MWI where all final states are equally real. Relative to a certain observer state, only one outcome occurs.

rkastner said:
Yes, basically. In decoherence 'derivations', the only interaction between system and environment is assumed to be due to a given interaction Hamiltonian and not due to any pre-existing quantum correlations. So that begs the question.
Well, decoherence is primarily a physical process which is independent of the measurement process. You can make experiments with two state systems and depending on what you do with them, a state tomography either yields a decohered (mixed) state or not. So there's nothing fishy about decoherence or its derivation in the framework of open quantum systems but only about the claim that it solves the measurement problem.

I fear that the discussion might lead to semantics. Ignoring correlations doesn't imply that these correlations are absent in an ontological sense. It might simply be a practical matter, like when we use a thermal state. Such a state might "really" be a reduced state while the whole (larger) system is in a pure entangled state but since we don't check these correlations it doesn't matter. And because of this, many people don't worry about ontology at all.

Having said this, I don't think that deriving decoherence by assuming certain special initial conditions doesn't tell us something. It shifts the question from "how does decoherence happen?" to "why do we have special initial conditions?" which is a well-known -albeit controversial- question from other branches of physics.
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
4
Replies
124
Views
3K
Replies
2
Views
942
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
10
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
12
Views
861
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
39
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
12
Views
1K
Replies
2
Views
958
Replies
3
Views
838
Replies
16
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
15
Views
1K
Back
Top