B Spagettification and a singularity

  • B
  • Thread starter Thread starter HansH
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Singularity
  • #51
Dale said:
Inside or outside the horizon the Schwarzschild spacetime is spherically symmetric and is foliated by 2-spheres. Each event in the spacetime belongs to exactly one such sphere, so you can unambiguously construct the “tangential” directions.

I don’t know if there is a geometric method that can be used to construct a unique “radial” direction. Simply requiring orthogonality to the “tangential” directions gives a 2D plane. That plane could be spanned by a spacelike and a timelike vector. If that could be done in a unique way then the spacelike vector could indeed be called “radial”. But I don’t know how to do it uniquely.
There's a Killing vector field, which is the Schwarzschild ##t## basis vector field outside the horizon and the "axial" direction inside. It lies in the 2d plane to which you refer, and the orthogonal direction is radial. (Doesn't work on the horizon where the Killing field is null.)
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
Ibix said:
There's a Killing vector field, which is the Schwarzschild ##t## basis vector field outside the horizon and the "axial" direction inside. It lies in the 2d plane to which you refer, and the orthogonal direction is radial. (Doesn't work on the horizon where the Killing field is null.)
You are right, but outside the horizon ##\partial_r##, the direction orthogonal to the Killing field, is the spatial direction away from the center, whereas inside the horizon ##\partial_t##, the direction of the Killing field itself, is the spatial direction away from the center.

I mean, I guess we can do a piecewise construction, but I couldn’t come up with one geometric rule that works everywhere.
 
  • #53
Suppose that when you enter the hole, just before passing the horizon, you attach a measuring tape to a station hovering above the horizon. What will the tape, rolling off from some magical device, show when you hit the singularity?

Will this even be possible (since no information can leave in the direction of the event horizon behind you)?

When you fall freely behind another particle, will you actually see that particle? Or will the light coming from it never reach you, because that radiation can only flow towards the singularity, its light one being inwardly directed directed? Or are the lightcones, in a freely falling frame, normal, since it's locally flat?
 
Last edited:
  • #55
BoraxZ said:
When you fall freely behind another particle, will you actually see that particle?
Post #14 show the future light cones of an infalling particle. If you add the complementing past light cones you will recognize that a second particle can see the first one crossing the horizon and for some time within the horizon but can't see it reaching the singularity.
 
  • #56
Ibix said:
Outside the hole, independent of your state of motion you can point at the hole.
Yes. And you can also point exactly opposite from that direction and point away from the hole.

And inside the hole, independent of your state of motion, you can point away from the hole. So you can also point exactly opposite from that direction and point towards the singularity. (Note that this is true even though the singularity is in your future--there are always timelike, null, and spacelike directions that point towards the singularity.) As I said, there is always a spacelike radial direction you can point in.

Ibix said:
You could also call it an axial direction because (unless you are hovering) it has a component in the Schwarzschild ##t## direction
Now you are restricting your definition to spacelike vectors that are orthogonal to your worldline. But I did not claim that there is always a spacelike radial direction orthogonal to your worldline. That depends on your worldline. My claim was weaker: that there is always some spacelike vector at whatever event on your worldline you pick that points in a purely radial direction (i.e., no ##\theta## or ##\phi## components).

That said, for realistic worldlines for actual observers free-falling radially into the hole, I think you will always be able to find a spacelike radial vector that is orthogonal to your worldline. For example, this is easy to prove for a Painleve observer, free-falling radially from rest at infinity.

Here's a heuristic argument for the claim I just made (which is stronger than the claim I made before): pick any event on the infalling observer's worldline that is inside the horizon. Take the ingoing radial null curve that intersects that point (there will always be exactly one). This can be thought of as light coming in from some distant object that is "directly overhead" for the radial infaller. Convert that null direction to a spacelike direction in the observer's orthonormal frame at that event. That spacelike direction is "radially outward". (And note that, for a radial infall, the same distant object can serve as the reference for "directly overhead" during the entire infall process.)

Ibix said:
Much the same argument applies the other way around inside the hole. Certainly there are spacelike directions that point to spherially symmetric surfaces of different radii, but I wouldn't call them "radial directions" for the same reason I wouldn't call radial directions outside the hole "axial directions".
The "axial" direction inside the hole is the direction of integral curves of ##\partial_t## (the fourth Killing field, which is timelike outside the horizon, null on the horizon, and spacelike inside the horizon). Yes, that direction is not aptly referred to as "radial". But the timelike "radial" direction orthogonal to it is not the worldline of any observer that free-falls in from outside the hole: it can't be, because it comes from the bifurcation point (the intersection of the axes on the Kruskal diagram), which is not a point that can be traversed by any timelike observer falling into the hole from outside. The only way for a timelike observer to reach that point is to come from the white hole region on the diagram. So calling that direction "radial" is also not very apt. But it's also not a direction that is relevant if you're thinking of an observer who fell into the hole from outside.
 
  • #57
Dale said:
I don’t know if there is a geometric method that can be used to construct a unique “radial” direction.
See the ingoing light ray construction I described in post #56.
 
  • #58
BoraxZ said:
two marbles released one second after one another from a fixed height above the Earth will end up at the same location on the surface below them. Such a surface is absent in a black hole. Nevertheless, they end up in the same amount of proper time on the singularity.
They take the same amount of proper time to fall, yes. But they don't end up at the same point on the singularity, because they didn't start from the same point on the worldline of the platform they fell from. One started at a point one second later in proper time along that worldline than the other.
 
  • Like
Likes BoraxZ
  • #59
BoraxZ said:
Will the total proper time elapsed for the second particle be just one second longer than the total proper time "experienced" by the first one
The total proper time during the fall will be the same for both. But the total proper time starting from the time when the first one is dropped will be one second longer for the second particle--because it waits for one second before being dropped itself.
 
  • Like
Likes BoraxZ
  • #60
Dale said:
The calculation of this quantity would be fairly involved.
The actual numerical value would be (since the infalling worldlines after being dropped would be the worldlines of Novikov observers, who fall from rest at a finite altitude, which are more complicated to compute than those of Painleve observers, who fall from rest at infinity). But the comparisons @BoraxZ is asking about don't require the full computation. See my previous posts in response to him.
 
  • #61
Ibix said:
There's a Killing vector field, which is the Schwarzschild ##t## basis vector field outside the horizon and the "axial" direction inside. It lies in the 2d plane to which you refer, and the orthogonal direction is radial.
The orthogonal direction is unproblematically radial outside the horizon. Inside, I don't think that description works well, for the reason I gave in the last part of post #56.

Dale said:
whereas inside the horizon ##\partial_t##, the direction of the Killing field itself, is the spatial direction away from the center.
I don't think this is true. The integral curves of ##\partial_t## stay at a constant ##r## coordinate; they do not point in a direction of increasing ##r##. A past-directed tangent vector along an integral curve of ##\partial_r## (Schwarzschild) points in a direction of increasing ##r##, but of course this direction is timelike, not spacelike (and it doesn't point outside the hole, for the reason I gave in the last part of post #56--which also explains why this timelike direction is the wrong one to think of if you are considering observers free-falling into the hole from outside).
 
  • #62
BoraxZ said:
Suppose that when you enter the hole, just before passing the horizon, you attach a measuring tape to a station hovering above the horizon. What will the tape, rolling off from some magical device, show when you hit the singularity?
It won't show anything. It will break. To stay attached to you once you fall below the horizon, the tape would have to unroll faster than the speed of light, which is impossible.

BoraxZ said:
When you fall freely behind another particle, will you actually see that particle?
Yes.

BoraxZ said:
Or will the light coming from it never reach you, because that radiation can only flow towards the singularity
No. It's true that the light can only move in the direction of decreasing ##r##, even though it's radially outgoing--but, heuristically, it does that more slowly than you do, so you catch up to it as you fall and can see it.

BoraxZ said:
are the lightcones, in a freely falling frame, normal, since it's locally flat?
Yes. This is a good way to avoid confusion when considering local behavior in scenarios like this.
 
  • Like
Likes BoraxZ
  • #63
PeterDonis said:
I don't think this is true. The integral curves of ##\partial_t## stay at a constant ##r## coordinate; they do not point in a direction of increasing ##r##. A past-directed tangent vector along an integral curve of ##\partial_r## (Schwarzschild) points in a direction of increasing ##r##, but of course this direction is timelike, not spacelike (and it doesn't point outside the hole, for the reason I gave in the last part of post #56--which also explains why this timelike direction is the wrong one to think of if you are considering observers free-falling into the hole from outside).
I certainly could be wrong, but I don’t think I am. Inside the horizon you still have the foliation of the spacetime as 2-spheres. Because the signature is (-+++) and that 2D foliation is spacelike, that means that there is one spacelike and one timelike direction remaining. We are looking (or at least I am looking) for the spacelike direction that is orthogonal to the 2-sphere. That is ##\partial_t##.

Now, you said “The integral curves of ##\partial_t## … do not point in a direction of increasing ##r##”, which is true but not what I said. I said “inside the horizon ##\partial_t##, the direction of the Killing field itself, is the spatial direction away from the center.”

The 2-spheres partition spacetime into two regions, one of which contains spacelike infinity and the other which does not. If you have a vector which is both spacelike and orthogonal to the vectors in the sphere then that vector must either point into the region which contains spacelike infinity or into the region which does not. If it points to the region with spacelike infinity then it is the spatial direction away from the center. I believe that inside the horizon ##\partial_t## is in the spacelike direction orthogonal to the 2-sphere and pointing away from the center.

It is true that the integral curves of ##\partial_t## do not point in a direction of increasing ##r##, but that is not the same as pointing away from the center. If spacetime were flat, then that would be the case. However, because spacetime is curved, the relationship between going away from the center and changing the ##r## coordinate (the area-radius) differs from what you would expect. Inside the horizon the spatial direction away from the center (which I think is ##\partial_t##) leads to another 2-sphere of the same surface area (same ##r##).

I could still easily be wrong. But if I am then I don’t think it is for the reason you gave. The reason you gave confounds a statement that I actually said with a different statement that is equivalent in flat spacetime, but I believe is not equivalent here.
 
  • #64
Dale said:
nside the horizon you still have the foliation of the spacetime as 2-spheres.
Yes, that's true everywhere. Each point in the Kruskal diagram labels a 2-sphere.

Dale said:
Because the signature is (-+++) and that 2D foliation is spacelike, that means that there is one spacelike and one timelike direction remaining.
More precisely, it is always possible to choose an orthonormal basis for the remaining 2D subspace (the one that the Kruskal diagram represents) with one timelike and one spacelike vector; but it is not possible to choose an orthonormal basis with two spacelike vectors.

Dale said:
We are looking (or at least I am looking) for the spacelike direction that is orthogonal to the 2-sphere.
Every direction in the 2D subspace that the Kruskal diagram represents is orthogonal to every 2-sphere. That is an elementary consequence of the hairy ball theorem (any such vector that was not orthogonal to every 2-sphere would create an everywhere non-vanishing vector field on a 2-sphere, which cannot exist). So this criterion does not help at all in picking out one direction in the 2D subspace vs. another.

I'll refrain from responding to the rest of your post because I think it needs to be rethought in the light of the above.
 
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #65
PeterDonis said:
Every direction in the 2D subspace that the Kruskal diagram represents is orthogonal to every 2-sphere.
That is a good point, and it does bring me back to what I said earlier to @Ibix about not having a good way to pick a specific direction.

PeterDonis said:
I'll refrain from responding to the rest of your post because I think it needs to be rethought in the light of the above.
I don’t think that it requires much revision. ##\partial_t## remains an orthogonal spacelike direction pointing away from the center as I said. It simply is not unique in that regard, which was the main motivation for my comment to @Ibix.
 
Last edited:
  • #66
Dale said:
$\partial_t$ remains an orthogonal spacelike direction pointing away from the center as I said.
I don't think "pointing away from the center" is a good description, since integral curves of ##\partial_t## point in a direction of constant ##r##. "Away from the center" IMO implies increasing ##r##. I don't see how the spacetime being curved changes that. I would ask what "center" you think ##\partial_t## inside the horizon points away from, since it doesn't seem to be pointing away from ##r = 0##. [Edit: but see a subtlety I describe in my next post.]

But ordinary language descriptions are always vague, so I know that it's worth taking too much time to argue over them. It doesn't seem like we disagree on the math in this respect.
 
  • #67
Dale said:
The 2-spheres partition spacetime into two regions, one of which contains spacelike infinity and the other which does not.
In the maximally extended manifold, this is actually not true, because there are two spacelike infinities, not one, and the two are on opposite sides of each 2-sphere.

If we restrict attention to a realistic collapse spacetime, like the Oppenheimer-Snyder model, then there is only one spacelike infinity and your statement is correct.

Dale said:
If you have a vector which is both spacelike and orthogonal to the vectors in the sphere then that vector must either point into the region which contains spacelike infinity or into the region which does not.
Yes, but there are subtleties involved that I think are worth mentioning.

First, the integral curves of ##\partial_t## are not geodesics. So we have to distinguish two things if we look at the ##\partial_t## vector at some particular event inside the horizon: the spacelike geodesic that passes through that event with that tangent vector, and the integral curve that passes through that event with that tangent vector.

The latter of the above (the integral curve) does not go to spacelike infinity; it stays inside the horizon forever. That is how we both have been implicitly been interpreting things, when we say that this vector points in the direction of constant ##r##.

The former of the above (the spacelike geodesic) should, however, go to spacelike infinity--or more precisely one end of it, the outgoing end, should (the other end, the ingoing end, should end on the ##r = 0## line somewhere inside the collapsing matter that forms the hole). I have not actually computed it to make sure, though.

The obvious next question would then be whether there are any spacelike geodesics on the outgoing side of an event inside the horizon that do not go to spacelike infinity. I think that is in fact the case--some of them will end on the singularity. (This seems obvious looking at a Penrose diagram--the Kruskal diagram is harder because the singularity is a hyperbola instead of a straight line.) So there should be some way of picking out the dividing line between the outgoing spacelike geodesics that reach spacelike infinity and the ones that don't. I'm not sure if that would have any obvious physical meaning, though.
 
  • #68
PeterDonis said:
If we restrict attention to a realistic collapse spacetime, like the Oppenheimer-Snyder model, then there is only one spacelike infinity and your statement is correct.
I am fine with that restriction.

The other possibility would be to specify one spacelike infinity as the spacelike infinity for “this” universe. Then “away from the center” would be the partition with “this” universe’s spacelike infinity and “toward the center” would be the partition with “that” universe’s spacelike infinity.

It is probably easier to just go with the realistic restriction.

PeterDonis said:
First, the integral curves of ∂t are not geodesics.
So you are the one bringing in both integral curves and geodesics. I was only looking at which partition the vector is pointing in. It is a much more primitive notion I was considering.

PeterDonis said:
The latter of the above (the integral curve) does not go to spacelike infinity; it stays inside the horizon forever. …

The former of the above (the spacelike geodesic) should, however, go to spacelike infinity
That is fine. I am not actually concerned about linking the vectors to any sort of curve going to spacelike infinity. I am simply identifying which region a vector is in.

PeterDonis said:
I think that is in fact the case--some of them will end on the singularity. (This seems obvious looking at a Penrose diagram--the Kruskal diagram is harder because the singularity is a hyperbola instead of a straight line.)
I think you are right about that. In the Kruskal diagram you can see it by considering the light cone at an event in the interior. The outgoing light ray is parallel to the horizon (in that diagram), and since the singularity is asymptotic to the horizon the outgoing light ray must intersect it. Any event “on” the horizon beyond that point would be spacelike separated from the given event.
 
  • #69
Dale said:
I was only looking at which partition the vector is pointing in.
Yes, but I don't think that's enough in itself to determine whether a vector is pointing "at spatial infinity". The geodesic defined by that vector would have to actually reach spatial infinity, and I don't think all of them in the partition you have picked out do. (But again, this is a matter of choice of ordinary language, not physics. I don't think we disagree on the physics.)
 
  • #70
PeterDonis said:
Yes, but I don't think that's enough in itself to determine whether a vector is pointing "at spatial infinity".
I never claimed it was pointing at spatial infinity. I wasn’t making that claim and I don’t think that claim is necessary.
 
  • #71
Dale said:
I never claimed it was pointing at spatial infinity. I wasn’t making that claim and I don’t think that claim is necessary.
Ok, so to you, "pointing away from the center" and "pointing at spatial infinity" are two distinct things. Fair enough. The first is the one you pick out by the outgoing side of the spacelike exterior of the light cone in the 2D ##t##-##r## subspace. The second you gave no specific definition for since I'm the one that brought it up, but I think "defines a spacelike geodesic that reaches spatial infinity" is reasonable.
 
  • #72
Dale said:
It is probably easier to just go with the realistic restriction.
I agree. Another advantage of that restriction is that it makes it easier to justify the term "away from the center" for all spacelike vectors in the outgoing half of the light cone in the 2D ##t##-##r## subspace, even the ones that define spacelike geodesics that end on the singularity: they all do obviously point away from the timelike part of the ##r = 0## locus, the worldline of the center of the collapsing matter that formed the hole. But that locus is only there in the realistic restriction.
 
  • #73
PeterDonis said:
In the sense that there is a finite "distance" along the r=0 line from the event where you hit it, to the event where the first particle hit it, yes. But this "distance" is not radial. It can't be, since it is entirely along the r=0 line, i.e., along a line with the same value of r everywhere.
Does this mean that different points on r=0 correspond to different times, like in GP coordinates? So, for example, one particle ends up at r=0 on Friday, and the other on Monday (so to speak)? If so, does this mean that the tidal forces that initially separated two particles spatially (together with an acceleration on the hovering platform), will somehow change into separating them temporarily, while spatially they get on top of each other again (like they started at infinity, after which one of them is accelerated at the platform before continuing)?
 
  • #74
BoraxZ said:
Does this mean that different points on r=0 correspond to different times, like in GP coordinates?
They correspond to different coordinate times in some charts, such as Painleve. But in those charts, the "time" coordinate is not timelike inside the horizon (in Painleve, it's spacelike), so you cannot conclude anything about "times" in a physical sense from them. To look at the physics, you have to look at invariants. The relevant invariant in this case is that the singularity is spacelike. That means it is physically meaningful to talk about arriving at the singularity at different places, but not at different times.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and BoraxZ
  • #75
PeterDonis said:
That means it is physically meaningful to talk about arriving at the singularity at different places, but not at different times.
Yes, it would be rather odd if two particles end up at the same point on different times. So they end up spatially separated while the imaginary clocks n their backs show different times?
But then again, if every particle falling in falls the same distance to the singularity, does that imply the singularity lies infinitely far away (for else they could not end up spatially separated).
 
  • #76
BoraxZ said:
So they end up spatially separated while the imaginary clocks n their backs show different times?
In the scenario you specified previously, yes.

BoraxZ said:
if every particle falling in falls the same distance to the singularity
The particle doesn't fall "the same distance". It takes the same time by its clock to fall to the singularity (if we start the clock when it begins to fall, and every particle falls from the same altitude).

The concept of what "distance" it falls doesn't even make sense, any more than the concept of what "distance" it is from now to next Tuesday noon makes sense. The singularity is a moment of time, not a place.

BoraxZ said:
does that imply the singularity lies infinitely far away
No. See above.
 
  • Like
Likes BoraxZ
  • #77
Okay. So, just for clarity, two particles on a hovering platform, are pushed off from the platform one second after one another. Say it takes 10 seconds proper time to reach the singularity from the platform (with zero initial velocity). The first one hits the singularity after ten seconds proper time while the second hits the singularity (which for both particles is the same moment in time, though their clocks show one second difference) spatially separated from the first. (which is the reason it makes no sense to ask about the distance fallen?). Is this right (more or less)?

Can we say what that moment in time (the singularity) is? Is it the time when the hole was formed?
 
  • #78
Dale said:
You are right, but outside the horizon ##\partial_r##, the direction orthogonal to the Killing field, is the spatial direction away from the center, whereas inside the horizon ##\partial_t##, the direction of the Killing field itself, is the spatial direction away from the center.

I mean, I guess we can do a piecewise construction, but I couldn’t come up with one geometric rule that works everywhere.
For that you simply need some other coordinate chart covering the Schwarzschild horizon, i.e., coordinates that are non-singular at the Schwarzschild horizon (like Kruskal coordinates etc.).
 
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #79
BoraxZ said:
You see the second particle move away from you during all the proper time that is left for you (I'm not sure if you can actually see the first particle ahead of you because behind the horizon, all signals travel towards the singularity).
The fact that all signals proceed toward the singularity does not prevent you from receiving them on your own trajectory toward the singularity. For instance, for a sufficiently massive black hole, you can fall feet-first through the horizon and still see your feet. Your eyes will have passed through the horizon by then, of course. Or, perhaps more aptly, the horizon will have passed through you at the speed of light.
 
  • #80
jbriggs444 said:
The fact that all signals proceed toward the singularity does not prevent you from receiving them on your own trajectory toward the singularity.
Yes, indeed. You can see the light that comes from the particles in front of you. Locally the space, in the freely falling frame, is flat. But there will come a point when the tidal forces prevents the light from reaching you.
 
  • #81
PeterDonis said:
It won't show anything. It will break. To stay attached to you once you fall below the horizon, the tape would have to unroll faster than the speed of light, which is impossible.
But suppose the tape is made of tachyonic matter instead of tardyonic. What will it show? I'm still under the impression you fall an infinite amount of space in the proper time you are inside the hole. Which makes it possible for all particles to end up with a finite mutual distance. If all particles fall to infinity they all can end up at finite distances wrt each other. All at the same time.
So you end up at infinity at the "endtime" T, and me too. We will have a spatial distance between us, and our clocks show different times. My clock, if I jumped in after you, will show a later time. So in a sense, accelerating outside the hole (in a platform) is a kind of "reverse" twin paradox (where you end up younger after accelleration).
 
Last edited:
  • Skeptical
Likes Dale
  • #82
BoraxZ said:
But suppose the tape is made of tachyonic matter instead of tardyonic.
Tachyonic matter doesn’t exist, and we don’t even have a good theory of how it would behave if it did hypothetically exist. This part of your question is unanswerable.

A note to anyone who would like to answer it: I may be wrong that there is no theory of tachyonic matter. If you would like to answer this then it is mandatory to provide a peer reviewed reference for the theory of tachyonic matter you are using. Note, this is an tachyonic tape measure, not just a tachyonic particle. Any answers without such a reference will be deleted.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis
  • #83
Dale said:
Tachyonic matter doesn’t exist, and we don’t even have a good theory of how it would behave if it did hypothetically exist. This part of your question is unanswerable.

A note to anyone who would like to answer it: I may be wrong that there is no theory of tachyonic matter. If you would like to answer this then it is mandatory to provide a peer reviewed reference for the theory of tachyonic matter you are using. Note, this is an tachyonic tape measure, not just a tachyonic particle. Any answers without such a reference will be deleted.
Okay, sorry for that. But don't we fall a distance through space? How else can it be? If I fall freely to the hole don't I fall through space? Do we fall through time inside the hole? The time/space reversal appears to a faraway observer only who coordinates the spacetime. manifold with Schwarzschild coordinates.

To put it differently, suppose a lot of particles are thrown in after one another. They all end up spatially separated from one another, but at the same time of the singularity. Will not the spatial distances between the first and last particle grow with the number of particles?
 
Last edited:
  • #84
Can we say that In Gullstrand-Painlevé coordinates the space inside is flat but a particle in front of you accelerates away from you due to "space expansion" (or the tidal effect)? The horizon behind you idem dito?

And say we place, again on the GP coordinates when we fall in freely, pendulae everywhere in front of us and behind us. What will they show?
 
Last edited:
  • #85
BoraxZ said:
The first one hits the singularity after ten seconds proper time while the second hits the singularity (which for both particles is the same moment in time, though their clocks show one second difference) spatially separated from the first.
Yes.

BoraxZ said:
Can we say what that moment in time (the singularity) is?
It is a moment of time that is to the future of all other moments inside the horizon. In general it has no well-defined relationship in time to events outside the horizon; to put it into your future, you have to fall into the hole.
 
  • #86
BoraxZ said:
don't we fall a distance through space?
You are continually "falling" into the future. What is the distance you fall between now and next Tuesday noon?

The natural way to answer this question is in terms of time, not distance. The same is true for the singularity.

BoraxZ said:
suppose a lot of particles are thrown in after one another. They all end up spatially separated from one another, but at the same time of the singularity. Will not the spatial distances between the first and last particle grow with the number of particles?
You use the phrase "the" spatial distance. There is no such thing. There is no one, unique, well-defined "spatial distance" between the particles once they are inside the horizon. So there is no one, unique, well-defined answer to your question.

As far as the "spacing" on the horizon of the events at which the particles arrive there, I have already answered that: it will be the same as the spacing in time between the particles starting to fall, provided they all fall from the same altitude above the horizon. So if they each fall one second after the previous one, each one will arrive at the singularity one light-second away from the previous one.
 
  • #87
PeterDonis said:
As far as the "spacing" on the horizon of the events at which the particles arrive there, I have already answered that: it will be the same as the spacing in time between the particles starting to fall, provided they all fall from the same altitude above the horizon. So if they each fall one second after the previous one, each one will arrive at the singularity one light-second away from the previous one.
Actually, I'm not sure this is quite true. I think an additional factor appears involving the ratio of the altitude above the horizon to the horizon radius. I'm not sure of the exact factor, though.
 
  • #88
PeterDonis said:
There is no one, unique, well-defined "spatial distance" between the particles once they are inside the horizon. So there is no one, unique, well-defined answer to your question.
Do you look at the hole from the faraway outside when saying this? Can't we assign a distance to a first particle in front of a second particle in the frame co-falling with the second?
 
  • #89
BoraxZ said:
Do you look at the hole from the faraway outside when saying this?
No. I explicitly said "once they are inside the horizon".

BoraxZ said:
Can't we assign a distance to a first particle in front of a second particle in the frame co-falling with the second?
Not for the entire infall process, no. The frame co-falling with the second particle is limited in extent; there will come a point where the worldline of the first particle will not be included in the second particle's co-falling frame (because the curvature of spacetime will be too large).

Also, the notion of "space" defined by the frame co-falling with the second particle is not unique. The frame co-falling with the first particle defines a different notion of "space"; and neither of those notions are global (both are limited to the extent of their respective co-falling frames).
 
  • #90
PeterDonis said:
What is the distance you fall between now and next Tuesday noon?
Isn't that c times the number of seconds between now and next Tuesday?
Again, If you fall in your proper time to the future time of singularity, and I arrive one second after you (according to my proper time), the above the horizon we are separated (about) one lightsecond? Is that what you said?

Can we say the future time towards which we inevitably fall in the hole, is the time that registered when the hole formed?
 
  • #91
BoraxZ said:
Isn't that c times the number of seconds between now and next Tuesday?
The distance between two objects is the space-time separation between the event of the one object "now" and the event of the other object at the "same time" according to some chosen foliation.

Next Tuesday is not at the "same time" as "now".
 
  • #92
BoraxZ said:
Isn't that c times the number of seconds between now and next Tuesday?
No. The interval between now and next Tuesday noon on your worldline is timelike, not spacelike. It's not a "distance" at all. It's a time.

You can of course measure that time in meters instead of seconds, by multiplying the number of seconds by 299,792,458. But that doesn't make the interval a distance. It just changes the units of time you are using.

BoraxZ said:
If you fall in your proper time to the future time of singularity, and I arrive one second after you (according to my proper time)
You don't. There is no way for you to say how long after me you arrive. Taking "according to my proper time" doesn't help any, because your proper time only applies along your worldline, it says nothing about times on my worldline.

Your basic problem here is that you are still thinking of the singularity as a place instead of a time. That doesn't work. The singularity is spacelike, not timelike. Only something described by a timelike curve can be thought of as a "place", and only for that kind of thing does it make sense to ask how long after person A person B arrives.

The singularity, being spacelike, has to be thought of as a time. Does it make sense to ask how long after me you arrive at next Tuesday noon? Of course not. So asking how long after me you would arrive at the singularity doesn't make sense either. The only question that makes sense is how far (i.e., what distance) apart our arrival points are.

BoraxZ said:
above the horizon we are separated (about) one lightsecond? Is that what you said?
No.

BoraxZ said:
Can we say the future time towards which we inevitably fall in the hole, is the time that registered when the hole formed?
No.
 
  • #93
jbriggs444 said:
The distance between two objects is the space-time separation between the event of the one object "now" and the event of the other object at the "same time".

Next Tuesday is not at the "same time" as "now".
But how can there be a separation in time if we don't consider different times? If you are standing still, the separation between you now and you tomorrow is the number of seconds between now and tomorrow times c. In lightseconds (one lightsecond being 300 000 meter). Or do I misunderstand you?
 
  • #94
BoraxZ said:
how can there be a separation in time if we don't consider different times?
We were considering different times: now and next Tuesday noon.

BoraxZ said:
f you are standing still, the separation between you now and you tomorrow is the number of seconds between now and tomorrow times c.
See my first response to you in post #92.
 
  • Like
Likes BoraxZ
  • #95
PeterDonis said:
It's not a "distance" at all. It's a time.
But when you label the t-axis ct doesn't it hold? Don't you have to express the time-position fourvector with equal components?

All wordlines entering the hole have their unique proper time. But they all end at the future singularity time. The difference in their proper times is not an indication of how far apart they end up wrt each other at the singularity. But what DOES determine that separation? If they fall from a platform it is the time that elapses on the platform between the first particle falling and the second.
 
  • #96
BoraxZ said:
when you label the t-axis ct doesn't it hold?
This issue has nothing to do with coordinates or labeling. The singularity is a spacelike line. That is an invariant, independent of any choice of coordinates or labeling. That invariant fact is what makes the singularity like a time (like next Tuesday noon) and not a place.

BoraxZ said:
All wordlines entering the hole have their unique proper time.
Which tells you nothing about anything off those worldlines, as I've already said.

BoraxZ said:
The difference in their proper times is not an indication of how far apart they end up wrt each other at the singularity.
That's correct.

BoraxZ said:
what DOES determine that separation? If they fall from a platform it is the time that elapses on the platform between the first particle falling and the second.
Yes. The separation in time, according to the clock on the platform, between the instants when they start to fall does tell you something about how far apart in distance their arrival points on the singularity will be. See my posts #86 and #87.
 
  • Like
Likes BoraxZ
  • #97
PeterDonis said:
We were considering different times: now and next Tuesday noon.
Yes, but I wrote this in response to a comment which said:

jbriggs444 said:
The distance between two objects is the space-time separation between the event of the one object "now" and the event of the other object at the "same time".

When a black hole has formed isn't the time on the inside the time of the constituting particles?
 
  • #98
BoraxZ said:
I wrote this in response to a comment which said
That comment specifically talked about spacelike distances, i.e., distances along a spacelike curve from one event to another. But the worldlines of objects are timelike, not spacelike.

BoraxZ said:
When a black hole has formed isn't the time on the inside the time of the constituting particles?
No. There is no such thing as "the" time on the inside.
 
  • #99
PeterDonis said:
BoraxZ said:
Can we say the future time towards which we inevitably fall in the hole, is the time that registered when the hole formed?
No.
But if we consider the particles constituting the hole, don't their proper times (since the big bang) end in the hole? Which, for example, means that when I jump into the hole a million years after its formation, my proper time ends with a million years difference (between my proper time and that of the hole particles) at the singularity? What will be then the spatial distance between me and the hole particles on the r=0 line?

I think I see the difference between staying at one position and moving in time, and moving towards the time at the singularity. With moving towards the the time at singularity you associate a spatial distance?
 
Last edited:
  • #100
BoraxZ said:
if we consider the particles constituting the hole, don't their proper times (since the big bang) end in the hole?
Their worldlines all end on the singularity, if that's what you mean.

BoraxZ said:
when I jump into the hole a million years after its formation, my proper time ends with a million years difference (between my proper time and that of the hole particles) at the singularity?
In general you have no way of making this comparison, because you don't know how big the object was that formed the hole before it started to collapse. When you say "a million years after its formation", that is not well-defined unless you can pick out a specific timelike curve that represents the "platform" from which the collapsing object started to fall (basically a hypothetical observer that sat on the surface of the object before it collapsed, and then stayed hovering at that same altitude after the object collapsed). In general you have no way of doing that.

BoraxZ said:
With moving towards the the time at singularity you associate a spatial distance?
No. I have never said any such thing. I have said the opposite, that it makes no sense to associate a "spatial distance" with a timelike curve.
 

Similar threads

Back
Top